Appendix to Hilbert s lecture The foundations of mathematics (1927) Paul Bernays

Similar documents
THE CONSTRUCTIVE SECOND NUMBER CLASS*

A SYSTEM OF AXIOMATIC SET THEORY PART VI 62

17.1 The Halting Problem

Almost von Neumann, Definitely Gödel: The Second Incompleteness Theorem s Early Story

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Footnotes to Linear Algebra (MA 540 fall 2013), T. Goodwillie, Bases

0.Axioms for the Integers 1

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Math Solutions to homework 5

The Independence of Peano's Fourth Axiom from. Martin-Lof's Type Theory without Universes. Jan M. Smith. Department of Computer Science

Appendix: Bar Induction in the Proof 1 of Termination of Gentzens Reduction 2 Procedure 3

Proving Completeness for Nested Sequent Calculi 1

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

Frege s Proofs of the Axioms of Arithmetic

A Semantics of Evidence for Classical Arithmetic

Introduction to Metalogic

Great Theoretical Ideas

Ordinalize! Peter Koepke University of Bonn January 28, Cantor s ordinals extend the standard natural numbers into the transfinite:

The natural numbers. The natural numbers come with an addition +, a multiplication and an order < p < q, q < p, p = q.

Sets and Infinity. James Emery. Edited: 2/25/ Cardinal Numbers 1. 2 Ordinal Numbers 6. 3 The Peano Postulates for the Natural Numbers 7

Victoria Gitman and Thomas Johnstone. New York City College of Technology, CUNY

17.1 Correctness of First-Order Tableaux

Supremum and Infimum

Mathematical Foundations of Programming. Nicolai Kraus. Draft of February 15, 2018

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

Cardinality of Sets. P. Danziger

Practice Test III, Math 314, Spring 2016

Takeuti s finitism and his proof of the consistency of arithmetic

THE FIVE GROUPS OF AXIOMS.

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

Lecture 14 Rosser s Theorem, the length of proofs, Robinson s Arithmetic, and Church s theorem. Michael Beeson

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter

Lecture Notes on Combinatory Modal Logic

Lecture 5 : Proofs DRAFT

Predicate Logic. Andreas Klappenecker

Hilbert s problems, Gödel, and the limits of computation

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

... The Sequel. a.k.a. Gödel's Girdle

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

Informal Statement Calculus

SOCRATES DID IT BEFORE GÖDEL

On the Representation of Involutive Jamesian Functions

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES

Turing Centenary Lecture

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Paucity, abundance, and the theory of number: Online Appendices

An Abstract Path Ordering

Measurable Choice Functions

10.1.1Theorem: Module 4 : Local / Global Maximum / Minimum and Curve Sketching

1.2 MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. Peano s Postulates and Induction. 10 Chapter 1 The Real Numbers

Peano Axioms. 1. IfS x S y then x y (we say that S is one to one).

Reckhow s Theorem. Yuval Filmus. November 2010

Lecture 1: The arithmetic hierarchy

Classical Text in Translation An Example of Statistical Investigation of the Text Eugene Onegin Concerning the Connection of Samples in Chains

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Math 117: Topology of the Real Numbers

Model Checking for Propositions CS477 Formal Software Dev Methods

Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic

PREDICATE LOGIC: UNDECIDABILITY AND INCOMPLETENESS HUTH AND RYAN 2.5, SUPPLEMENTARY NOTES 2

Cantor s Letter to Dedekind

ON THE PROBLEM OF CHARACTERIZING DERIVATIVES

Automata theory. An algorithmic approach. Lecture Notes. Javier Esparza

Logik - WS16/17. Iosif Petrakis. December 16, 2016

WUCT121. Discrete Mathematics. Logic. Tutorial Exercises

Syntax and Semantics. The integer arithmetic (IA) is the first order theory of integer numbers. The alphabet of the integer arithmetic consists of:

Chapter 1. Introduction to prime number theory. 1.1 The Prime Number Theorem

Cantor (1). Georg Cantor ( ) studied in Zürich, Berlin, Göttingen Professor in Halle

Characterization of Semantics for Argument Systems

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Problem Set 14: To be discussed Tuesday, April 24

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015)

The Axiom of Choice and its Discontents

Unfolding finitist arithmetic

Math 324 Summer 2012 Elementary Number Theory Notes on Mathematical Induction

CS280, Spring 2004: Final

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

Series of Error Terms for Rational Approximations of Irrational Numbers

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Prentice Hall Algebra 1, Foundations Series 2011 Correlated to: Washington Mathematics Standards, Algebra 1 (2008)

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

MA103 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Second part, Analysis and Algebra

Multitape Ordinal Machines and Primitive Recursion

THE FOUNDATIONS OF PHYSICS (SECOND COMMUNICATION)

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

3.C. Further comments on axioms for geometry

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9

The constructible universe

Understanding Computation

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

The Church-Turing Thesis and Relative Recursion

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1666)

FORMAL PROOFS DONU ARAPURA

ALGEBRA. 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers

Relation of the Bell inequalities with quantum logic, hidden variables and information theory

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 20 Apr 2002

Transcription:

Bernays Project: Text No. 6 Appendix to Hilbert s lecture The foundations of mathematics (1927) Paul Bernays (Zusatz zu Hilbert s Vorlesung Die Grundlagen der Mathematik, 1927.) Translation by: Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg and Dagfinn Føllesdal Comments: none 1. To supplement the preceding paper [[by Hilbert]] let me add some more detailed explanations concerning the consistency proof by Ackermann that was sketched there. First, as for an upper bound on the number of steps of replacement in the case of embedding, it is given by 2 n, where n is the number of ε-functionals distinct in form. The method of proof described furnishes yet another, substantially closer bound, which, for example, for the case in which there is no embedding at all yields the upper bound n + 1. 1 2. Let the argument by which we recognize that the procedure is finite in the case of superposition be carried out under simple specializing assumptions. 1 [[See in Hilbert and Bernays 1939, pp. 96 97, how this bound is obtained.]] 1

The assumptions are the following: Let the ε-functionals occurring in the proof be ε a A(a, ε b K(a, b)) and ε b K(a 1, b), ε b K(a 2, b),..., ε b K(a n, b), where a 1,..., a n may contain ε a A(a, ε b K(a, b)) but no other ε-functional. The procedure now consits in a succession of total replacements ; each of these consists of a function replacement χ(a) for ε b K(a, b)), by means of which ε a A(a, ε b K(a, b)) goes over into ε a A(a, χ(a)), and a replacement for ε a A(a, χ(a)), by means of which a 1,..., a n go over into numberals z 1,..., z n and the values χ(z 1 ),..., χ(z n ) are obtained for ε b K(a 1, b),..., ε b K(a n, b). We begin with the function χ 0 (a), which has the value 0 for all a ( zero replacement ), and accordingly also replace the terms ε b K(a 1, b),..., ε b K(a n, b) by 0. Holding this replacement fixed, we apply to ε a A(a, χ 0 (a)) the original testing procedure, which after two steps at most leads to the goal; that is, all the critical formulas corresponding to ε a A(a, χ 0 (a)) 2

then become true. Thus we obtain one or two total replacements, E 0, or E 0 and E 0, respectively. Now either E 0 (or E 0) is final or one of the critical formulas corresponding to ε b K(a 1, b), ε b K(a 2, b),... becomes false. Assume that this formula corresponds to, say ε b K(a 1, b) and that a 1 goes into z 1. Then we find a value z such that K(z 1, z) is true. Now that we have this value, we take as replacement function for ε b K(a, b) not χ 0 (a), but the function χ 1 (a) defined by χ 1 (z 1 ) = z χ 1 (a) = 0 for a z 1. At this point we repeat the above procedure with χ 1 (a), the values of the ε b K(a ν, b) (ν = 1,..., n) now being determined only after a value has been chosen for ε a A(a, χ 1 (a)), and thus we obtain one or two total replacements, E 1, or E 1 and E 1. Now either E 1 (or E 1) is final or for one of the ε-functionals that result from ε b K(a 1, b),..., ε b K(a n, b), by the previous total replacement we again find a value z, such that for a certain z 2 K(z 2, z ) 3

is true, while K(z 2, χ 1 (z)) is false. From this it directly follows that z 2 z 1. Now, instead of χ 1 (a) we introduce χ(a) 2 as replacement function by means of the following definition: χ 2 (z 1 ) = z χ 2 (z 2 ) = z χ 2 (a) = 0 for a z 1, z 2. The replacement procedure is now repeated with this function χ 2 (a). As we continue in this way, we obtain a sequence of replacement functions χ 0 (a), χ 1 (a), χ 2 (a),..., each of which is formed from the preceding one by addition, for a new argument value, of a function value different from 0; and for every function χ(a) we have one or two replacements, E p, or E p and E p. The point is to show that this sequence of replacements terminates. For this purpose we first consider the replacements E 0, E 1, E 2,.... In these, ε a A(a, ε b K(a, b)) is always replaced by 0; the ε b K(a ν, b) (ν = 1,..., n) therefore always go over into the same ε-functionals; for each of these we put either 0 or a numeral different from 0, and this is then kept as a final replacement. Accordingly, at 4

most n + 1 of the replacements E 0, E 1, E 2,... can be distinct. 2 If, however, E k is identical with E l, then neither one has, or else each has, a successor replacement E k, or E l, and in these ε a A(a, ε b K(a, b)) is then in both cases replaced by the same number found as a value, so that, for both replacements, the ε b K(a ν, b) (ν = 1,..., n) also go over into the same ε-functionals. Accordingly, of the replacements E l for which E l coincides with a fixed replacement E k again at most n + 1 can be distinct. Hence there cannot be more than (n + 1) 2 distinct E p, or E p and E p altogether. From this it follows, however, that our.procedure comes to an end at the latest with the replacement function χ (n+1) 2(a). For, the replacements associated with two distinct replacement functions χ p (a) and χ q (a), q > p, cannot coincide completely, since otherwise we would by means of χ q (a) be led to the same value z that has already been found by means of χ p (a), whereas this value is already used in the definition of the replacement functions following χ p (a), hence in particular also in that of xχ q (a). 3. Let us note, finally, that in order to take into consideration the axiom of mathematical induction, which for the purpose of the consistency proof may be given in the form (ε a A(a) = b ) Ā(b), we need only, whenever we have found a value z for which a proposition B(a) holds, go to the least such value by seeking out the first true proposition in 2 [[See footnote 1.]] 5

the sequence B(0), B(0 ),..., B(z) of propositions that have been reduced to numerical formulas. 3 3 [[ In 1935, p. 213, end of footnote 1, Bernays writes that this last paragraph, on mathematical induction, should be deleted. In 1927 Hilbert and his collaborators had not yet gauged the difficulties facing consistency proofs of arithmetic and analysis. Ackermann had set out (in 1924 ) to prove the consistency of analysis; but, while correcting the printer s proofs of his paper, he had to introduce a footnote, on page 9, that restricts his rule of substitution. After the introduction of such a restriction it was no longer clear for which system Ackermann s proof establishes consistency. Certainly not for analysis. The proof suffered, moreover, from imprecisions in its last part. Ackermann s paper was received for publication on 30 March 1924 and came out on 26 November 1924. In 1927, received for publication on 29 July 1925 and published on 2 January 1927, von Neumann criticized Ackermann s proof and presented a consistency proof that followed lines somewhat different from those of Ackennann s. The proof came to be accepted as establishing the consistency of a first-order arithmetic in which induction is applied only to quantifierfree formulas. When he was already acquainted with von Neumann s proof, Ackermann communicated, in the form of a letter, a new consistency proof to Bernays. This proof developed and deepened the arguments used in Ackermann s 1924 proof, and, like von Neumann s, it applied to an arithmetic in which induction is restricted to quantifier-free formulas. It is with this proof of Ackermann s that Hilbert s remarks above (pp. 477-479) and Bernays s present comments are concerned. It was felt at that point, among the members of the Hilbert school, that the consistency of full first-order arithmetic could be established by relatively straightforward extensions of the arguments used by von Neumann or by Ackermann (see Hilbert 1928a, p. 137, lines 20-21; 1930, p. 490, line 4u, to p. 491, line 2; Bernays 1935, p. 211, lines 4-7). These hopes were dashed by Gödel s 1931. Ackermann s unpublished proof was presented in Hilbert and Bernays 1939, pp. 93-130. In 1940 Ackermann gave a consistency proof for full first-order arithmetic, using a principle of transfinite induction (up to ε 0 ) that is not formalizable in this arithmetic.]] 6