REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES

Similar documents
Interpolation and FEP for Logics of Residuated Algebras

Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic

An Overview of Residuated Kleene Algebras and Lattices Peter Jipsen Chapman University, California. 2. Background: Semirings and Kleene algebras

Meeting a Modality? Restricted Permutation for the Lambek Calculus. Yde Venema

Implicational F -Structures and Implicational Relevance. Logics. A. Avron. Sackler Faculty of Exact Sciences. School of Mathematical Sciences

Lambek grammars based on pregroups

Substructural Logics and Formal Linguistics: Back and Forth

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

AN ALTERNATIVE NATURAL DEDUCTION FOR THE INTUITIONISTIC PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

RESIDUATED FRAMES WITH APPLICATIONS TO DECIDABILITY

RESIDUATION SUBREDUCTS OF POCRIGS

Lambek calculus is NP-complete

Algebraic Logic. Hiroakira Ono Research Center for Integrated Science Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology

Distributive residuated frames and generalized bunched implication algebras

Categorial Grammars and Substructural Logics

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018

Basic Algebraic Logic

Modal systems based on many-valued logics

TR : Binding Modalities

Dual-Intuitionistic Logic and Some Other Logics

From Residuated Lattices to Boolean Algebras with Operators

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Substructural Logics and Residuated Lattices an Introduction

Some Non-Classical Approaches to the Brandenburger-Keisler Paradox

Uninorm Based Logic As An Extension of Substructural Logics FL e

Universal Algebra for Logics

Omitting Types in Fuzzy Predicate Logics

TABLEAUX VARIANTS OF SOME MODAL AND RELEVANT SYSTEMS

ON THE LOGIC OF DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES

Categorial Grammar. Algebra, Proof Theory, Applications. References Categorial Grammar, G. Morrill, OUP, 2011.

CHAPTER 10. Gentzen Style Proof Systems for Classical Logic

A Kripke-Joyal Semantics for Noncommutative Logic in Quantales

CHARACTERIZATION THEOREM OF 4-VALUED DE MORGAN LOGIC. Michiro Kondo

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Display calculi in non-classical logics

03 Review of First-Order Logic

Pregroups and their logics

Algebras of Deductions in Category Theory. 1 Logical models from universal algebra

On rigid NL Lambek grammars inference from generalized functor-argument data

An Algebraic Proof of the Disjunction Property

Propositional Logic Language

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

A Bimodal Perspective on Possibility Semantics

Complexity of the Lambek Calculus and Its Fragments

On Urquhart s C Logic

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

Grammatical resources: logic, structure and control

ON THE ATOMIC FORMULA PROPERTY OF HÄRTIG S REFUTATION CALCULUS

Mathematical Logic. An Introduction

IDEMPOTENT RESIDUATED STRUCTURES: SOME CATEGORY EQUIVALENCES AND THEIR APPLICATIONS

An Introduction to Modal Logic III

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

KLEENE LOGIC AND INFERENCE

Duality in Logic. Duality in Logic. Lecture 2. Mai Gehrke. Université Paris 7 and CNRS. {ε} A ((ab) (ba) ) (ab) + (ba) +

Algebraic Canonicity in Non-Classical Logics

A VIEW OF CANONICAL EXTENSION

Partially commutative linear logic: sequent calculus and phase semantics

1. Algebra H-B-M-S- <A, 0, 1,,,,,, >

by KOSTA DOSEN in Belgrade (Yugoslavia) )

RELATION ALGEBRAS AS EXPANDED FL-ALGEBRAS

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems (1)

Chapter 11: Automated Proof Systems

MIXING MODAL AND SUFFICIENCY OPERATORS

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

The Lambek-Grishin calculus for unary connectives

FROM AXIOMS TO STRUCTURAL RULES, THEN ADD QUANTIFIERS.

RELATION ALGEBRAS. Roger D. MADDUX. Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa USA ELSEVIER

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

Logic Synthesis and Verification

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS

Displacement Logic for Grammar

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

How and when axioms can be transformed into good structural rules

CUT ELIMINATION AND STRONG SEPARATION FOR SUBSTRUCTURAL LOGICS: AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH.

Sequent calculi of quantum logic with strict implication

From Semirings to Residuated Kleene Lattices

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor

Equivalent Types in Lambek Calculus and Linear Logic

Semantics: Residuated Frames

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Axiom schema of Markov s principle preserves disjunction and existence properties

MAI0203 Lecture 7: Inference and Predicate Calculus

Relevance Logic as an Information-Based Logic. J. Michael Dunn Indiana University Bloomington

Positive Logic with Adjoint Modalities: Proof Theory, Semantics and Reasoning about Information

TR : Tableaux for the Logic of Proofs

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

Classical Gentzen-type Methods in Propositional Many-Valued Logics

Distributive Substructural Logics as Coalgebraic Logics over Posets

Fuzzy Logics and Substructural Logics without Exchange

The problem of judgment aggregation in the framework of boolean-valued models

ACLT: Algebra, Categories, Logic in Topology - Grothendieck's generalized topological spaces (toposes)

Exploring a Syntactic Notion of Modal Many-Valued Logics

Preuves de logique linéaire sur machine, ENS-Lyon, Dec. 18, 2018

On relational interpretation of multi-modal categorial logics

Overview of Logic and Computation: Notes

Kazimierz SWIRYDOWICZ UPPER PART OF THE LATTICE OF EXTENSIONS OF THE POSITIVE RELEVANT LOGIC R +

On interpolation in existence logics

Multiplicative Conjunction and an Algebraic. Meaning of Contraction and Weakening. A. Avron. School of Mathematical Sciences

Investigation of Prawitz s completeness conjecture in phase semantic framework

Transcription:

Wojciech Buszkowski REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES Professor Rasiowa [HR49] considers implication algebras (A,, V ) such that is a binary operation on the universe A and V A. In particular, there are studied implicative algebras, positive implication algebras and implication algebras; the second kind corresponds to the logic of positive implication, and the third one to the logic of classical implication. In each case, the distinguished element V is interpreted as the equivalence class of all theorems in the appropriate Lindenbaum algebra. Accordingly, the approach cannot be directly applied to logics in which theorems do not form a single equivalence class (e.g. BCI) or there are no theorems at all (e.g. the Lambek calculus); such logics are typical for the world of substructural logics, arising from Gentzen style systems of intuitionistic logic by dropping structural rules (see [3]). Instead of implication algebras in the sense of [HR49], one should consider implication structures (A,, ) such that (A, ) is a poset, and is a binary operation on A. In the Lindenbaum algebra, corresponds to the (sequential) consequence relation, determined by the given logic. Usually, implication structures are obtained as reducts of residuated groupoids (A,,,, ), where (A, ) is a poset, and,, are binary operations on A, fulfilling the equivalences: (RG) b a c iff a b c iff a c b, for all a, b, c A. Notice that (RG) mirrors introduction and elimination rules for implication in the Natural Deduction format; is the product (or: fusion) operation which corresponds to joining formulas in the antecedent of a sequent. If the order of formulas in the antecedent of a sequent is irrelevant, then is supposed to be commutative, and consequently, = corresponds to the logical constant. Noncommutative structures are related to noncommutative logics with two conditionals and. If is associative (antecedents of sequents are strings of formulas), then the 152

structure above is called a residuated semigroup. If additionally 1 A is the unit for, then this structure is called a residuated monoid; residuated monoids correspond to logics with theorems (provable sequents with empty antecedents). Observe that each residuated groupoid satisfies the monotonicity conditions: (M1) if a b, then c a c b and a c b c, (M2) if a b, then c a c b and b c a c, (M3) if a b, then a c b c and c b c a. We shall consider residuated algebras of sets: concrete residuated algebras in the sense of Dunn [4] and powerset residuated algebras in the sense of [2]. The former come from Kripke style frames for relevant logics. A ternary frame is a pair (U, R) such that U is a nonempty set, and R U 3. For X, Y U, we define: X Y = {z U : ( x X)( y Y ) R(x, y, z)}, X Y = {y U : ( x, z)(if x X and R(x, y, z) then z Y )}, X Y = {x U : ( y, z)(if y Y and R(x, y, z) then z X)}. The structure (P (U),,,, ) is a residuated groupoid, called the concrete residuated groupoid over (U, R). If R fulfils the condition: ( z)(r(x, y, z) R(z, u, w)) iff ( v)(r(y, u, v) R(x, v, w)), then the concrete residuated groupoid over (U, R) is a residuated semigroup. Other constraints upon R yield commutative residuated semigroups, groupoids, monoids, etc. More special structures are based on groupoids (U, ) which give rise to ternary frames (U, R) such that R(x, y, z) holds iff x y = z; we call them powerset residuated groupoids over groupoids (U, ). Notice that, in the powerset residuated groupoid, is the standard powerset operation determined by: X Y = {x y : x X, y Y }, while, are given by: X Y = {y U : ( x X) x y Y }, X Y = {x U : ( y Y ) x y X}. 153

Clearly, if (U, ) is a (resp. commutative) semigroup, then P (U) is a (resp. commutative) residuated semigroup, and if (U,, 1) is a (resp. commutative) monoid, then (P (U),..., {1}) is a (resp. commutative) residuated monoid. We refer to these structures as (resp. commutative) powerset residuated semigroups and monoids over the appropriate (resp. commutative) semigroups and monoids. Representation theorems to be discussed here are of the general form: each implication structure (residuated algebra) of the given kind is isomorphic to a substructure of some concrete or powerset residuated algebra. Representation in concrete residuated algebras can be accomplished by methods analogous to those used in [HR49] for implication algebras (which follow the well known Stone representation theorem for Boolean algebras). We give a typical example (after Dunn [4]). Let (A,,,, ) be a residuated groupoid. We show that this structure is isomorphic to a substructure of a concrete residuated groupoid. By a cone we mean a set A such that, for all x, y A, if x and x y, then y. Let U be the set of all cones, and let R U 3 be defined by: R( 1, 2, 3 ) iff ( x 1 )( y 2 ) x y 3. As above, we construct the concrete residuated groupoid P (U). One shows that the mapping: h(x) = { U : x } is a monomorphism of the residuated groupoid (A,...) into the concrete residuated groupoid P (U) which fulfils the equivalence: x y iff h(x) h(y), for all x, y A. Consequently, each residuated groupoid is embeddable into a concrete residuated groupoid. Quite analogously, one proves other theorems of that kind, for instance: (A) each (commutative) residuated semigroup (monoid) is embeddable into a (commutative) concrete residuated semigroup (monoid), (B) each implication structure (A,,, ), fulfilling (M2), (M3) and the laws: a b (a b), a (b a) b is embeddable into a concrete residuated groupoid, 154

(C) each implication structure (A,, ), fulfilling (M2), is embeddable into a concrete residuated groupoid. For (B) and (C), one defines ternary relations: R ( 1, 2, 3 ) iff ( x 1 )( y)( if x y 2 then y 3 ), R ( 1, 2, 3 ) iff ( y 2 )( x)( if x y 1 then x 3 ). The additional laws in (B) yield R = R, and the monomorphism h is defined as above. Representation in powerset residuated algebras can be accomplished by the above methods only for implication structures but not for structures with. Again, let (A,, ) be an implication structure. Let U be defined as above. The operation on U is given by: 1 2 = {y A : ( x 1 ) x y 2 }. We construct the powerset residuated groupoid P (U) and define h as above. If (A,, ) fulfils (M2), then h is a monomorphism from (A,, ) to the, -reduct of P (U). Also, if (A,,, ) fulfils the conditions from (B), then h is a monomorphism from the latter structure to the,, -reduct of P (U). However, h is not a homomorphism from the residuated groupoid (A,,,, ) to P (U); we only have h(x) h(y) h(x y), while the converse inclusion fails, in general. The following representation theorem: (RT) each residuated semigroup is embeddable into a powerset residuated semigroup and similar results for residuated groupoids, monoids, commutative structures etc. can be proven with the aid of proof-theoretic tools from [1]. We use the Lambek calculus L [7] which deals with sequents A B, where A, B are propositional formulas with logical constants,,. The axioms and rules of L are: (A0) A A, (A1) (A B) C A (B C)), (A2) A (B C) (A B) C, (R1) A B C B A C, (R2) A B C A C B, 155

(R3) B A C A B C, (R4) A C B A B C, (CUT) A B; B C. A C If Φ is a set of sequents, then L(Φ) denotes the system L enriched by all sequents from Φ as new axioms. It is easy to show that sequents derivable in L are precisely those which are valid in all residuated semigroups (that means, true under all valuations α; A B is true under α, if α(a) α(b)). Further, sequents derivable in L(Φ) are precisely those which are true in all residuated semigroups under all valuations α which satisfy all sequents from Φ. Thus, L is strongly complete with respect to the semantics of residuated semigroups (use Lindenbaum algebras). We construct a Labelled Deductive System (in the sense of Gabbay [5]), denoted by LDS, which is a conservative extension of L(Φ). Labels are defined as follows: (i) all formulas are labels, (ii) if s and t are labels, then st is a label, (iii) if s is a label, and A, B are formulas, then (s, 1, A B) and (s, 2, A B) are labels. LDS deals with labelled formulas s : A whose intended meaning is: the element s M belongs to the set α(a) M. The axioms and rules of LDS are: (I ) s : A; t : B st : A B, (E 1) (I ) (I ) (A) A : A, s : A B (s, 1, A B) : A, (E 2) As : B s : A; t : A B, (E ), s : A B st : B sa : B s : B A; t : A, (E ), s : B A st : B (R) s : A, if s reduces to t, t : A (RΦ) s : A, if A B is in Φ. s : B s : A B (s, 2, A B) : B, In rule (R), s reduces to t, if t arises from s by a finite number of replacements of a redex (u, 1, B C)(u, 2, B C) with its contractum u. For every term s, there is precisely one irreducible term s such that s reduces to s. Let M consist of all irreducible terms. We consider the semigroup (M, ), 156

where, for s, t M, s t = (st). The powerset model (P (M), α) such that α(p) = {s M : LDS s : p} satisfies the canonical equivalence: (P (M), α) = A B iff L(Φ) A : B. Further, LDS is conservative over L(Φ): A B is derivable in L(Φ) iff A : B is derivable in LDS. That immediately yields the strong completeness of L with respect to powerset residuated semigroups. We prove the representation theorem (RT). Let (A,,,, ) be a residuated semigroup. To each a A we assign a different atomic formula p a ; we assume all atomic formulae are of that form. An assignment µ in (A,...) is given by µ(p a ) = a. Let Φ consist of all sequents A B which are true in the model (A, µ). We construct the canonical model (P (M), α) for L(Φ), as above. It is easy to show that the mapping h : A P (M), defined by h(a) = α(p a ) is a monomorphism of (A,...) into (P (M),...). Analogous theorems can be proven for residuated groupoids, monoids etc. In [6], similar results have been obtained for abstract residuated algebras. We can also consider richer structures with additional operations, e.g. lattice operations and negation, and we can prove representation theorems either by the methods of [HR49] (for structures without ), or by the methods akin to the above. Let us mention an open question. According to Bia lynicki-birula and Rasiowa [HR18], a De Morgan negation in the poset (A, ) is a unary operation on A such that there hold the laws of Double Negation a = a and Transposition: a b implies b a. For X U, the quasi-boolean complement of X is defined by: X = U f[x], where f is a fixed mapping from U onto itself such that f(f(x)) = x, for all x U. One can prove that each residuated groupoid (semigroup) with De Morgan negation is embeddable into a concrete residuated groupoid (semigroup) with quasi-boolean complement (an analogue of the representation theorem for quasi-boolean algebras in [HR18]). In the universe U, of all cones, define f( ) = A ( ), where ( ) is the set of all (a), for a. In a similar way, one can prove that the -free reduct of any residuated groupoid (semigroup) with De Morgan negation is embeddable into a powerset residuated groupoid with quasi-boolean complement. We do not know if each residuated groupoid (semigroup) with De Morgan negation is embeddable into a powerset residuated groupoid with quasi-boolean complement. 157

References [1] W. Buszkowski, Completeness Results for Lambek Syntactic Calculus, Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 32 (1986), pp. 13 28. [2] W. Buszkowski, Mathematical Linguistics and Proof Theory, [in:] J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen (eds.), Handbook of Logic and Language, North Holland, Amsterdam, to appear. [3] K. Došen and P. Schroeder-Heister (eds.), Substructural Logics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1993. [4] J. M. Dunn, Partial Gaggles Applied to Logics with Restricted Structural Rules, in: [2]. [5] D. Gabbay, Labelled Deductive Systems, CIS-Muenchen, Munich, 1991. [6] M. Ko lowska-gawiejnowicz, Powerset Residuated Algebras and Generalized Lambek Calculus, Mathematical Logic Quarterly, to appear. [7] J. Lambek, The mathematics of sentence structure, American Mathematical Monthly 65 (1958), pp. 154 170. [8] H. Ono and Y. Komori, Logics without the contraction rule, Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1985), pp. 169 201. Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Adam Mickiewicz University Matejki 48/49 60-769 Poznań, Poland e-mail buszko@math.ann.edu.pl 158