Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

Similar documents
Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Solving Extensive Form Games

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

Incentives and Machine Learning

Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory

1 Extensive Form Games

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Unanimity, Pareto optimality and strategy-proofness on connected domains

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4

Mixed Strategy Equilibrium and Deep Covering in Multidimensional Electoral Competition

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Information Aggregation in Large Elections

Advanced Microeconomics

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

What is Backward Induction?

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

6 The Principle of Optimality

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Condorcet Cycles? A Model of Intertemporal Voting*

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University

THREE ESSAYS ON GAME THEORY. Demet Yilmazkuday. Dissertation. Submitted to the Faculty of the. Graduate School of Vanderbilt University

A Shut Mouth Catches No Flies: Consideration of Issues and Voting

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University

Mean-Variance Utility

game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les Illes Balears June 1, 2012 Abstract

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Intro to Economic analysis

Group strategy-proof social choice functions with binary ranges and arbitrary domains: characterization

Farsightedness in Coalition Formation

ALGEBRA. 1. Some elementary number theory 1.1. Primes and divisibility. We denote the collection of integers

Preference, Choice and Utility

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics WEAK LINKS, GOOD SHOTS AND OTHER PUBLIC GOOD GAMES: BUILDING ON BBV

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Game Theory and Social Psychology

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

Nash-solvable bidirected cyclic two-person game forms

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013

The following techniques for methods of proofs are discussed in our text: - Vacuous proof - Trivial proof

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments

Topologies on Types. Drew Fudenberg Harvard University. First Draft: April 2004 This Draft: August Abstract

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

Immunity to credible deviations from the truth

The Role of Aggregate Information in a Binary Threshold Game

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

AGM-consistency and perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Part II: from PBE to sequential equilibrium.

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Proofs. Chapter 2 P P Q Q

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006

Voting by conformity

Asymmetric Information and Bank Runs

Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom

Upstream capacity constraint and the preservation of monopoly power in private bilateral contracting

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Dynamics and Stability of Constitutions, Coalitions, and Clubs

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Game Theory Fall 2003

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma

Robust Estimation and Inference for Extremal Dependence in Time Series. Appendix C: Omitted Proofs and Supporting Lemmata

Dynamic Merger Review

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

1 The Well Ordering Principle, Induction, and Equivalence Relations

Applied cooperative game theory:

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Proofs. Chapter 2 P P Q Q

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Applied cooperative game theory:

Maximal Domains for Strategy-Proof or Maskin Monotonic Choice Rules Olivier Bochet y and Ton Storcken z

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

A fair rule in minimum cost spanning tree problems 1

A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL

Transcription:

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Egregious Errata Positive Political Theory II (University of Michigan Press, 2005) regrettably contains a variety of obscurities and errors, both typographical and substantive. Most of these are apparent and the appropriate corrections evident. Unfortunately, a few of the mistakes to surface are egregious (and thus correspondingly embarrassing...). So, with apologies to Je and to those using this book, the mistakes within this category identi ed so far are located and corrected below. (The University of Michigan Press has kindly agreed to publish a corrected version of the ms in 2015.) David Austen-Smith December 2014 p.4, following discussion of De nition 1.2. To avoid the occasional ambiguity in some subsequent examples, a sentence has been added that reads, "Hereafter, unless explicitly stated otherwise, assume an aggregation rule f satis es unrestricted domain, D = R n." Corresponding changes are thereafter made where appropriate. p.5, remarks on simple rules and the Nakamura number. The examples using majority and plurality rule on this page (from the top to the nal paragraph) presume unrestricted domain. p.22, De nition 2.4. As written, this is insu ciently tight. Replace the current de nition and subsequent paragraph with: De nition 2.4 Fix a collective choice function ' : R n! X with range '. Say that ' respects unanimity if and only if, for all 2 R n and all sets X ' such that (x; y) 2 X ' nx implies P (x; y; ) = N, '() 2 X. In words, ' respects unanimity if, at any pro le for which it is possible to partition the range of ' into two subsets such that every alternative in one subset is strictly preferred by all individuals to every alternative in the other subset, then ' surely selects an alternative from the universally more-preferred-to set. It is easy to see that if there are multiple such sets for any pro le, then they must 1

be ordered by set-inclusion. Although similar in spirit to the Pareto criterion, respecting unanimity and weak Pareto are not equivalent (where a choice function ' is weakly Paretian if, for all x; y 2 X and all 2 R n, P (x; y; ) = N implies '() 6= y). p.38, line 5. Should have k and n k + 1 below the equality, not i k and n i k + 1, respectively. p.44, Lemma 2.5. The constructive argument used in the text to prove Lemma 2.5 turns out to have paid insu cient attention to di culties at the boundaries of the feasible set of alternatives. In particular, the particular choice of pro les for the argument in one case need not be feasible. Below is a complete restatement of the required (slightly extended) Lemma and proof. Lemma 2.5 Let ' : S Q! X be strategy-proof and satisfy citizen sovereignty. Then ' is weakly Paretian and satis es peak only. Proof (Weakly Paretian) We need to prove minfx i g i2n '() maxfx i g i2n for all 2 S Q. First show that strategy-proofness and voter sovereignty imply unanimity. To this end, let 2 S Q be any pro le such that, for all i 2 N, x i = x; we want to show '() = x. By citizen sovereignty there exists a pro le 0 2 S Q such that '( 0 ) = x. By strategy-proofness, for all admissible single-peaked R 0 1, '(R 1 ; 0 1)R 1 '(R 0 1; 0 1); in particular, since '(R 0 1; 0 1) '( 0 ) = x 1 by hypothesis and ideal points are uniquely de ned, we must have '( 0 ) = '(R 1 ; 0 1). But '(R 1 ; 0 1) = x and x = x 2 ; hence, by strategy-proofness, it must also be that '(R 1 ; 0 1) = '(R 1 ; R 2 ; 0 f1;2g ). Repeating the argument for j = 3; ::; n yields '() = x. Thus ' satis es unanimity. Now consider any pro le 2 S Q such that x 1 x 2 : : : x n and x 1 < x n and suppose, contrary to ' weakly Paretian, '( ) > x n. For k = 1; 2; : : : ; n 1, x an admissible pro le k = ( 0 f1;:::;kg ; f1;:::;kg ) 2 S Q such that, for all j k, x 0 j = x n and '( )Pj 0a t for all a t < x n. By ' strategy-proof, '( )R 1 '( 1 ). By R 1 single-peaked, therefore, either '( 1 ) '( ) > x n or '( 1 ) 1 ('( )) < x 1. Suppose the latter case holds, so '( 1 ) < x 1 < x n and, by de nition of P1, 0 '( )P1'( 0 1 ). But then j = 1 can pro tably manipulate ' by reporting R 1 instead of R1 0 at 1. So, '( 1 ) '( ). Moreover, since ' strategy-proof requires '( 1 )R1'( 0 ) which, by R1 0 single-peaked, implies '( 1 ) '( ), we must have '( ) = '( 1 ). Now applying this argument iteratively, we nd '( n 1 ) = : : : = '( 1 ) = '( ) > x n. But by construction, n 1 is such that x 0 j = x n for all j 2 N, 2

in which case, ' unanimous implies '( n 1 ) = x n : contradiction. A symmetric argument accounts for the case '( ) < x 1. Hence, ' must be weakly Paretian. (Peak only) Now x 2 S Q, arbitrary i 2 N and any single-peaked preference ordering Ri 0 with x i = x 0 i. To prove the lemma, it su ces to show '() = '(Ri 0; i). If '() = x 0 i, then the result is trivial. So, without loss of generality, assume x 0 i = x i > '(). There are two cases (in what follows, the alternative 0 i (y) is de ned in exactly the same way as the alternative i (y), above, but with respect to the preference ordering Ri 0 rather than to the ordering R i). (1) 0 i ('()) < i('()): see Figure 2.3. Figure 2.3: Lemma 2.5, case (1) Suppose '() 6= '(R 0 i ; i). Then, depending on the relative position of the alternative '(R 0 i ; i) in Figure 2.3, there are three possibilities, each of which (given single-peakedness) contradicts strategyproofness. (1a): (1b): (1c): '(Ri; 0 i ) < '() ) '(Ri; 0 i ) < '() < x 0 i ) '()Pi 0 '(Ri; 0 i ) ) ' manipulable at (R 0 i; i ): '() < '(R 0 i; i ) 0 i('()) ) '() < '(R 0 i; i ) < i ('()) ) '(R 0 i; i )P i '() ) ' manipulable at : 0 i('()) < '(R 0 i; i ) ) x 0 i < 0 i('()) < '(R 0 i; i ) ) '()P 0 i '(R 0 i; i ) ) ' manipulable at (R 0 i; i ): Therefore, if, contrary to the claim, '() 6= '(Ri 0; i), we must have '(Ri 0; i) i ('()) > x 0 i and i('()) 0 i ('()), the second case. (2) i ('()) 0 i ('()). In this case, we need to take a more indirect approach than in case (1) to proving the claim. To this end, let L = fj 2 N : x j > x 0 i g. If L = ; then x0 i = x i x k for all k 2 N. 3

But since, '() 6= '(Ri 0; i) implies '(Ri 0; i) > x 0 i from Case (1), this contradicts ' weakly Paretian. So assume L 6= ;. By relabeling if necessary, let L = f1; :::; `g and x 1 x 2 : : : x`. For all j 2 L, let Rj 0 be such that x0 j = x0 i and x j 0 j ('()) j('()): see Figure 2.4 for the situation in which all of the inequalities are strict for i and some j 2 L. Figure 2.4: Lemma 2.5, case (2) Consider individual ` 2 L and the choice '(R 0`; `). Suppose '(R 0`; `) 6= '(). Arguing similarly to Case (1), single-peaked preferences implies that ' is manipulable by ` unless '(R 0`; `) `('()) > x`. But since, by de nition, x` x k for all k 2 N, '(R 0`; `) > x` contradicts ' weakly Paretian. Hence '(R 0`; `) = '(). Applying the same argument, mutatis mutandis, to ` 1 then yields '(R 0`; R0` 1 ; f`;` 1g) = '(R 0`; `) = '(). And continuing in this way iteratively for ` 2; ` 3; : : : ; 1, conclude '() = '( 0 L ; L). Now consider the pro le 0 = ( 0 L[fig ; L[fig). There are ve possibilities for the relative location of '( 0 ). In four of these, '( 0 ) 6= '() and we show that i has opportunity to manipulate the outcome pro tably; thus we must have '( 0 ) = '() and, in this case we show '( 0 ) = '(Ri 0; i) as claimed. (2a): '( 0 ) < '(). Referring to Figure 2.4, observe '( 0 ) < '() ) '( 0 ) < '() < x 0 i ) '()Pi 0 '( 0 ) ) ' manipulable at 0 : (2b): '( 0 ) = '(). In this subcase, we need to show: '( 0 ) = '(Ri 0; i). We rst show '( 0 ) = '(R 1 ; 0 1); to do this, suppose the contrary, '( 0 ) 6= '(R 1 ; 0 1). Then arguing as for Case (1), ' strategy-proof implies 0 1('( 0 ) '(R 1 ; 0 1) 1 ('( 0 )) with x 1 < '(R 1 ; 0 1). Now, for all j 6= 1, let R 00 j ordering such that x 00 j = x 1 and be an admissible single-peaked j 2 Lnf1g ) 0 j('(r 1 ; 0 1)) < 00 j ('(R 1 ; 0 1)); j =2 L ) j ('(R 1 ; 0 1)) < 00 j ('(R 1 ; 0 1)): Figure 2.5 illustrates the construction. Figure 2.5: Lemma 2.5, case (2b) Using a similar argument to that above for '() = '( 0 L ; L), conclude '(R 1 ; 0 1) = '(R 1 ; 00 1). But then x 1 = x 00 2 = ::. = 4

x 00 n < '(R 1 ; 0 1), contradicting ' unanimous; therefore, '( 0 ) = '(R 1 ; 0 1) necessarily. Repeating the preceding argument for each j 2 L yields '( 0 ) = '(R 1 ; 0 1) = '(R 1 ; R 2 ; 0 f1;2g ) = ::: = '( L; 0 L) = '(R 0 i; i ) as required. (2c): '() < '( 0 ) < i ('())). But then '() = '( 0 L ; L) implies '( 0 L; L ) < '( 0 L[fig ; L[fig) < i ('()) ) '( 0 )P i '() ) ' manipulable at : (2d): i ('()) '( 0 ) 0 i ('()). In this case, a similar argument as that for (2b) yields a contradiction of ' unanimous [Exercise]. (2e): '( 0 ) > 0 i ('()). Referring to Figure 2.4, observe '( 0 ) > 0 i('()) ) x 0 i < 0 i('()) = 0 i('( 0 L; L )) < '( 0 ) ) '( 0 L; L )P 0 i '( 0 ) ) ' manipulable at 0 : Because the situation where '() > x 0 i is completely symmetric, the lemma is proved. p.67, Section 2.10: Exercises. Exercises 2.1 and 2.9 of the original text have been eliminated. p.79, four lines up from Example 3.3. The sentence beginning, Formally, therefore,... should read: Formally, therefore, Maskin monotonicity implies monotonicity which in turn implies weak monotonicity;... p.82, De nition 3.7. The de nition should have... j\ y2x R(x; y; )j n rather than R(x; y; ) = n 1 for all y 2 X implies.... 1 implies x 2 '(), p.92, Second sentence of paragraph immediately preceding Corollary 3.2. The vote pro les m 2 M should be understood as rationalizable preference relations (see PPT I, ch.1, on rationalizable preferences). p.139, from the end of line 5 to the middle of line 12. 5

The claim made in this section is that condition (*) is a necessary condition for an alternative y to be agenda independent. This is false and the comments immediately following (*) are thereby nonsense. The text beginning on line 5 with the sentence In other words... to the end of the sentence concluding on line 12 with... S( ; P ) = y, should be deleted and replaced with the following: On the other hand, a su cient condition for an alternative y 2 Xnfx 0 g to be the sophisticated outcome irrespective of the agenda 2 A(x 0 ), is that y 2 P (x 0 ) and, 8z 2 P (x 0 )nfyg; y 2 P (z): (*) That is, if y satis es (*) then, for all 2 A(x 0 ), S( ; P ) = y. To see this, recall that every terminal node of an amendment agenda pairs the status quo x 0 against an alternative from the agenda, with every such alternative appearing on at least one terminal node. By the rst property of (*), that y 2 P (x 0 ), and the earlier logic for solving binary voting games, y must be the sophisticated equivalent of every terminal node at which y is compared with x 0. Now consider any alternative z 6= y. If z is the sophisticated equivalent of some terminal node, then either z = x 0 or z 2 P (x 0 ). In either case, (*) implies that y must be the sophisticated equivalent of any pairwise comparison between y and z at the next stage; and so on back up the voting tree, thus establishing the claim. In other words... p.172, Figure 5.12. The payo s identi ed in this diagram for Example 5.8 are incorrect. corrected example is as follows. A Example 5.8 Consider the extensive form game G summarized in Figure 5.12, where the outcome associated with each terminal node of the game tree is de ned in terms of the payo s (u 1 ; u 2 ) to individuals 1 and 2 respectively. 6

Figure 5.12: The game G The feasible strategy sets for the two individuals are M 1 = f(d; L); (D; R); (A; L); (A; R)g; M 2 = fl; rg: There are three Nash equilibria = ( 1 ; 2 ) 2 M 1 M 2 to G: = ((A; L); l); = ((A; R); l); and = ((D; R); r). To check and are both Nash equilibria note that, given 2 = l, the best 1 can do is play A at his rst decision node to obtain a payo of one rather than zero and, given 1 chooses A, no subsequent decision nodes are reached, so specifying 2 plays l is as good as anything else since 2 receives payo one in any case; similarly, given 2 plays l, 1 is indi erent between L or R at the nal decision node. That is also a Nash equilibrium follows easily from the observation that it yields the unique best payo for each individual. Moreover, we claim is the only subgame perfect Nash equilibrium to G. To see that and are not subgame perfect, consider the two proper subgames, G and G 0, in turn. The restriction of to G is the strategy pair (L; l) which is easily checked to be a Nash equilibrium for G. On the other hand, the restriction of to G 0 is the decision L for individual 1, which is clearly not a best response at this decision node. Thus is not a subgame perfect equilibrium strategy pro le for G. Similar reasoning shows is not subgame perfect: here, the restriction of to the (trivial) subgame G 0 has individual 1 choosing a best response, but then the restriction of to the subgame G is not a Nash equilibrium for G. This is 7

because individual 2 choosing l is not a best response in G to 1 s choice of R, despite the fact that 2 = l is a best response in G to 1 = (A; R). Finally, it is easy to check that is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium to G as claimed. p.178, line 4. The de nition of R(x) should read, R(x) = fy 2 X : yrxg. p.288, last expression in the proof of Theorem 7:10. By de nition of (a ; y), there should be no minus sign on the terms! i () under the summation. The same is true in the argument for Corollary 7.3. p.288, line 2 of Corollary 7.3. The assumption that p i () = p() should be replaced by! c i () is independent of i ; the rst line of the proof is then redundant. p.336, Example 8.2 (5). Proportional representation, even as described here, is not a scoring rule. p.383, Exercise 8.3(b). The last conditional,... if m is odd should read... if m = 3. Furthermore, the exercise is intended to concern only pure strategy equilibria. 8