A strategic implementation of the Talmud rule based on concede-and-divide algorithm

Similar documents
Bilateral consistency and converse consistency in axiomatizations and implementation of the nucleolus

Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems

On properties of division rules lifted by bilateral consistency. Hokari, Toru and Thomson, William. Working Paper No. 536 December 2007 UNIVERSITY OF

The Nucleolus of the Bankruptcy Problem by Hydraulic Rationing

Discussion Paper Series

Volume 29, Issue 4. Population monotonicity, consistency and the random arrival rule

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

On Bankruptcy Game Theoretic Interval Rules

Lecture 7. Simple Dynamic Games

Priority weights in claims problems

Minimal Overlap Rules for Bankruptcy

THE DISPUTED GARMENT PROBLEM: THE MATHEMATICS OF BARGAINING & ARBITRATION. Richard Weber

Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: an update

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002)

A Noncooperative Support for Equal Division in Estate Division Problems

Four Lectures on the Nucleolus and the Kernel Delivered at the hebrew University of Jerusalem 10th Summer School in Economic Theory

Three ancient problems solved by using the game theory logic based on the Shapley value

Col.lecció d Economia E15/329. Generalized rationing problems and solutions. Pere Timoner Lledó Josep Maria Izquierdo Aznar

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Abstract When a rm goes bankrupt, how should its liquidation value be divided among its creditors? This essay isanintroduction to the literature devot

Negotiation: Strategic Approach

Utilitarian resource allocation

No THE TWO-STAGE CONSTRAINED EQUAL AWARDS AND LOSSES RULES FOR MULTI-ISSUE ALLOCATION SITUATIONS

Shapley like values for interval bankruptcy games. Abstract

Evolutionary Bargaining Strategies

Non-Manipulable Division Rules in Claim Problems and Generalizations

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie**

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

Dual Bargaining and the Talmud Bankruptcy Problem

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11

The Uniform Allocation Rule and the Nucleolus

Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution

ON THE COASE THEOREM AND COALITIONAL STABILITY: THE PRINCIPLE OF EQUAL RELATIVE CONCESSION

4: Dynamic games. Concordia February 6, 2017

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge

Implementing equal division with an ultimatum threat

Dynamic Games, II: Bargaining

Impartiality principles in claims problems with indivisibilities

A New Solution to the Problem of Adjudicating Conflicting Claims. Diego Dominguez and William Thomson. Working Paper No.

For general queries, contact

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 13: Extensive Form Games

Games with Perfect Information

A Folk Theorem For Stochastic Games With Finite Horizon

Lecture 2 The Core. 2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

Maskin Meets Abreu and Matsushima

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Extensive Form Games I

Bargaining with a Claims Structure: Possible Solutions to a Talmudic Division Problem

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Discussion Papers Department of Economics University of Copenhagen

Lecture notes on Bargaining and the Nash Program

Integer Solutions to Bankruptcy Problems with Non-integer Claims

Theory of Auctions. Carlos Hurtado. Jun 23th, Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Solving Extensive Form Games

Copyright (C) 2013 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of the Creative

The Minimal Overlap Rule: Restrictions on Mergers for Creditors' Consensus

Essays in Bargaining and Cooperative Game Theory with an Application to Environmental Negotiations

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich

Lecture Notes: Self-enforcing agreements

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Dividends and Weighted Values in Games with Externalities

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Information transmission in coalitional voting games

Hypothetical Bargaining and Equilibrium Refinement in Non-Cooperative Games

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Lecture Notes: Self-enforcing agreements

Adverse selection, signaling & screening

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games

Money, Barter, and Hyperinflation. Kao, Yi-Cheng Department of Business Administration, Chung Yuan Christian University

Sender s Small Concern for Credibility and Receiver s Dilemma

Majority bargaining for resource division

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007

Repeated bargaining. Shiran Rachmilevitch. February 16, Abstract

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Are Obstinacy and Threat of Leaving the Bargaining Table Wise Tactics in Negotiations?

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Working Paper Series

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Economics 3012 Strategic Behavior Andy McLennan October 20, 2006

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

The Core of a Strategic Game *

Péter Csóka, P. Jean-Jacques Herings. An Axiomatization of the Proportional Rule in Financial Networks RM/17/001

A New Perspective on Kesten s School Choice with. Consent Idea

Binding Agreements II: Coalition Formation

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

COALITIONAL GAMES WITH VETO PLAYERS: MYOPIC AND FARSIGHTED BEHAVIOR

A New Perspective on Kesten s School Choice with. Consent Idea

Voluntary Leadership in Teams and the Leadership Paradox

Coalition Formation and Asymmetric Information in a Legislative Bargaining Game

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: the Stochastic Stability of Edgeworth s Recontracting. Roberto Serrano Oscar Volij. January 2003

1 Basic Game Modelling

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Trade Rules for Uncleared Markets with a Variable Population

Transcription:

A strategic implementation of the Talmud rule based on concede-and-divide algorithm Min-hung Tsay and Chun-Hsien Yeh Department of Economics, National Chung Cheng University, Taiwan Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica, Taiwan July 2, 2018 CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 1 / 31

Bankruptcy problem When a firm goes to bankrupt, how to divide its liquidation value among its creditors? This is the so-called bankruptcy problems motivated by the two puzzles in the ancient Jewish document (the Talmud). This literature was initiated by O Neill (1982). For an updated survey, see Thomson (2015). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 2 / 31

Bankruptcy Problem: initiation Contest Garment Problem Worth of the garment Claimant 1 Claimant 2 100 200 200 50 150 CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 3 / 31

Research agenda Estate Division Problem Estate of the man Wife 1 Wife 2 Wife 3 100 100 3 100 200 300 100 3 100 3 200 50 75 75 300 50 100 150 CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 4 / 31

The Model: formal definition Many mathematicians and economists try to rationalize the numbers in Puzzles I and II. However, almost all of them fail, including O Neill (1982). Instead of looking at the specific numerical examples, O Neill (1982) give a general description for this class of resource allocation problems (bankruptcy problems) as follows: CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 5 / 31

The Model ( ϕ N {1,, n}, c (c 1,, c n ) R N +, E R + with ) c i E i N = (x 1,, x n ) R N + s.t. for each i N, 0 x i c i, and i N x i = E. The first condition, 0 x i c i, says that creditor i should not receive more than his claim (claims boundedness) and a negative award (non-negativity). The condition is called reasonableness. The second condition, i N x i = E, says that a rule should allocate the entire resource. This condition is called efficiency or feasibility. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 6 / 31

Central rules A number of bankruptcy rules have been proposed. Among them, the following rules are central in the literature as well as in our analysis. They are: The Constrained Equal Awards (CEA) rule (egalitarianism form the perspective of gains) assigns equal awards to all creditors subject to no one receiving more than his claim. Formally, for each N N, each (c, E) C N, and each i N, CEA i (c, E) min {c i, λ}, where λ R + is chosen such that i N CEA i (c, E) = E. The Constrained Equal Losses (CEL) rule (egalitarianism from the perspective of losses) assigns awards such that the loss (the difference between a creditor s claim and award) experienced by each creditor is equal subject to no one receiving a negative award. Formally, for each N N, each (c, E) C N, and each i N, CEL i (c, E) max {c i λ, 0}, where λ R + is chosen such that i N CEA i (c, E) = E. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 7 / 31

Central rules The Talmud (T) rule (Aumann and Maschler, 1985) rationalizes several numerical examples made in the Talmud, and is a hybrid of the CEA and CEL rules. Formally, for each N N, each (c, E) C N, and each i N, { min { c i 2 T i (c, E), λ} if c i i N E; 2 c i + max { c i λ, 0} otherwise, 2 2 where λ R + is chosen such that i N T i (c, E) = E. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 8 / 31

Serrano (1995) s game Stage 1: Creditor n announces y. Stage 2: Creditor n-1 Stage n-p+1: Creditor p Reject y p CC p (c p, c n ; w n p+1 + y p ) Accept y p Creditor p-1 Stage n: Creditor 1 where w n 1 = y n 1 and, for each p = n 1,,1, w p n = w p+1 n ii cccccccc p aaaaaaa y p ; CC n (c p, c n ; w p+1 n + y p ) ooheeeeee. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 9 / 31

Serrano (1995) s result He shows that Theorem: For each N N and each (c, E) B N, the unique Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPE) outcome of the game Γ CG (c, E) is T (c, E). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 10 / 31

Serrano (1995) s result Remark: The exogeneity of the proposer and outcome uniqueness: Creditor n is the only creditor to propose an awards vector. However, if the proposer is not creditor n, the outcome uniqueness of his result does not hold. His work relies on contested garment rule (a two-creditor version of the Talmud rule) in solving bilateral negotiations. This leaves a room for improvement since the purpose of the Nash program is to justify cooperative solutions through non-cooperative procedures, ideally no cooperative solution should get involved in the details of non-cooperative procedures. Thus, it would be preferable if bilateral negotiations were resolved by (non-cooperative) procedures. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 11 / 31

Our first goal Our first goal is to strategically justify (or implement) the Talmud rule by introducing a game in which bilateral negotiations are resolved by non-cooperative bilateral bargaining procedures. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 12 / 31

Our second goal It can be seen that the half-claim vector c plays an important role in 2 rationalizing the numerical examples in the Talmud. Aumann and Maschler (1985) justify the vector by invoking legal conventions in the Talmud and psychological presumption (namely, more than half is like the whole and less than half is like nothing). However, there is still no strategic interpretation of the vector. Our second goal is to fill this gap. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 13 / 31

Concede-and-divide algorithm Aumann and Maschler (1985) mention that for two-creditor problems, the awards vector prescribed by the Talmud rule can be obtained by the following concede-and-divide algorithm. To introduce the algorithm, we define the minimal award of a creditor. The minimal award of a creditor is the remaining endowment after the other has been fully reimbursed if this remaining endowment is positive; it is zero, otherwise. Namely, it is the maximum of the difference between the endowment and the other s claim, and zero. Aumann and Maschler (1985) refer to this minimal award of a creditor as the minimal right of a creditor, and consider it as the least concession amount by the other from the perspective of gains. The algorithm says that each creditor first receives her minimal award and then is awarded an equal share of the residual endowment (if any). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 14 / 31

Concede-and-divide algorithm Cj minimal award of creditor i E CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 15 / 31

Concede-and-divide algorithm E minimal award of creditor j Ci CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 16 / 31

Concede-and-divide algorithm Cj Divide-and-choose part minimal award of creditor i E minimal award of creditor j Ci CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 17 / 31

Concede-and-divide algorithm This algorithm suggests a two-creditor non-cooperative procedure that involves the following Minimal concession First (MCF) process with respect to the minimal awards of creditors. Suppose that the perspective of gains is given. The MCF process suggests first assigning each creditor her minimal award and next dividing the residual endowment. It is a natural and common in the literature on bargaining to allow for a stage of concession during negotiation. For instances, Harsanyi (1956) and Ordover and Rubinstein (1986). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 18 / 31

Two-creditor concession game Nature Select creditor d N Creditor d Propose (MCF, D) with D {a, b} such that a, b R + and their sum satisfies feasibility w.r.t. MCF. Propose (, D) with D {a, b} such that a, b R + and a + b = E. Creditor r N\{d} Creditor r Pick x r D Pick x r D (z d, z r ) (w d, w r ) where z r = mmm{e c d, 0} + x r and z d = E z r ; w r = x r and w d = E w r. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 19 / 31

Inapplicability of the above game Example. Let N {1, 2} and let ( ) c ( c 1, c 2 ), Ẽ = ((3, 5), 4). We exhibit an NE outcome of Ω T ( c, Ẽ) that is not the Talmud outcome ( 3 ( ) 2, 2) 5. Consider the strategy profile σ T σ T 1, σt 2 : each creditor i N takes one of the following actions. Let j N \ {i}. i is the divider: She proposes (p T,i, D T,i ) = { (, {2, 2}) if i = 1; ( MCF, { 3 2, 3 2}) if i = 2. i is the responder: Given creditor j s proposal (p, D), creditor i picks max D. Clearly, σ T is an SPE of Ω T ( c, Ẽ), and is an NE. If Nature chooses creditor 1 as the divider, then by following σ T, the game ends up with outcome (2, 2) ( 3 2, 5 2). However, if Nature chooses creditor 2 as the divider, then by following σ T, the game ends up with the Talmud outcome ( 3 2, 5 2). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 20 / 31

Intuition behind the example After the decision on whether or not the MCF is conducted, the divide-and-choose mechanism is adopted to perform a division of the corresponding endowment. Given this, if creditor 1 (the creditor with the smallest claim) is chosen to be the divider, she will not conduct the MCF process. The game ends up with an outcome that is not the Talmud outcome. If creditor 2 (the creditor with the biggest claim) is the divider, she will conduct the MCF process. The game ends up with the Talmud outcome. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 21 / 31

Overcome the inapplicability and treat creditors symmetrically One way to recover the unique Talmud outcome of the procedure Ω T (c, E) is to drop Nature and designate creditor 2 as the divider. However, by doing so, the strategy space of creditor 2 is different from that of creditor 1. Thus, the creditors are not treated symmetrically like Serrano (1995) and Dagan et al. (1997). To avoid such an asymmetric treatment and recover the unique Talmud outcome, we introduce the following procedure Ω T in which the choice between the perspective of gains and the perspective of losses is determined endogenously rather than exogenously. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 22 / 31

Our two-creditor Talmud game Nature Creditor s Select creditor s N Pick u {G, L} Creditor d N\{s} Propose (MCF, D) with D {a, b} such that a, b R + and their sum satisfies feasibility w.r.t. u and MCF. Creditor s Propose (, D) with D {a, b} such that a, b R + and their sum satisfies feasibility w.r.t. u. Creditor s Pick x s D Pick x s D (z s, z d ) (w s, w d ) where mmm{e c z s = d, 0} + x s ii u = G; and z c s mmm{(c s + c d E) c d, 0} x s ii u = L, d = E z s ; x w s = s ii u = G; and w c s x s ii u = L, d = E w s. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 23 / 31

Base result We show that Proposition: Let N N with N = 2 and (c, E) B N. The unique NE outcome of Ω T (c, E) is T (c, E). Moreover, it can be supported by a pure strategy SPE. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 24 / 31

A strategic interpretation of the half-claim vector Let N N and (c, E) B N with N {1, 2} and c 1 c 2. Nature chooses one of the two creditors as perspective setter. Given that the divide-and-choose mechanism is adopted to perform a division of the corresponding endowment or deficit, creditor 1 prefers the perspective of gains to the perspective of losses and creditor 2 has reverse preference. Thus, the setter would pick a perspective that is beneficial to her. To balance the advantage given to the setter, the other, called the divider, is allowed to choose either to conduct, or not to conduct the MCF process. It can be seen that in equilibrium, if creditor 2 (creditor 1) is the perspective setter and chooses the perspective of losses (the perspective of gains), then creditor 1 (creditor 2) as the divider conducts the MCF process and proposes a division of the remaining deficit E (c 1 + c 2 E) (ξ 1 + ξ 2 ) (the remaining endowment E E (η 1 + η 2 )). CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 25 / 31

A strategic interpretation of the half-claim vector Furthermore, ( in equilibrium, ) the creditors awards vector η 1 + E 2, η 2 + E 2 (when creditor 1 is the setter) is symmetric to the ( ) creditors losses vector ξ 1 + E 2, ξ 2 + E 2 (when creditor 2 is the setter) with respect to the half-claim vector. Thus, the vector is a consequence of balancing advantages between the creditors and exploiting the divide-and-choose mechanism. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 26 / 31

A strategic implementation of the Talmud rule We now extend our base result to more than two creditors. We introduce the following tree-stage extensive form game. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 27 / 31

A strategic implementation of the Talmud rule Stage 1: Each creditor i N announces (y i, π i ). Let π π 1 π n and π(1) = k. Let y be the proposal. If for each i, h N\{k}, y i = y h, then y = y i ; otherwise, y = y k. Stage 2: Creditor k either takes A (accepts y) or (R, l) (rejects y and chooses one creditor from N\{k}, say creditor l). (R, l) A (R, i 1 ) (R, i n-1 ) y (y i ) i N Stage 3: Each creditor i N\{k, l} receives y i, and creditors k and l play the twocreditor game Γ φ (c k, c l ), y k + y l. Let (z k, z l ) be an outcome of Γ φ (c k, c l ), y k + y l. Γ φ (c k, c l ), y k + y l (y i ) i N\{k,l}, (z k, z l ) CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 28 / 31

A strategic implementation of the Talmud rule Replace ϕ with T in the above game Ω ϕ and call the resulting game Ω T. We show that Theorem: Let N N and (c, E) B N. The unique NE outcome of Ω T (c, E) is T (c, E). Moreover, it can be supported by a pure strategy SPE. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 29 / 31

Concluding remarks Our paper improves the existing implementation of the Talmud rule in Serrano (1995) by opening up the black boxes of bilateral negotiations. Unlike Serrano (1995), our game capture the spirit of the Talmud rule. (Serrano (1995) uses a random dictator game, which captures the spirit of the random arrival rule.) In addition, Nature plays an important role in deriving equilibrium outcome of the game in Serrano (1995). Thus, he obtains an implementation of the Talmud rule in expected term. Our paper obtains exact implementations of the Talmud rule. Our paper is the first one to offer a strategic interpretation of a key element (the half-claim vector) in the Talmud rule. CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 30 / 31

Thank you!! CH Yeh (IEAS) bankruptcy problem July 2, 2018 31 / 31