David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Similar documents
226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

viii My God, He Plays Dice! Preface Preface

For the seminar: Ausgewählte Probleme der Quantenmechanik Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, WS 2011/2012 Christian Knobloch a

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

84 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 12. Irreversibility. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility

How does it work? QM describes the microscopic world in a way analogous to how classical mechanics (CM) describes the macroscopic world.

about Quantum Physics Bill Poirier MVJS Mini-Conference Lawrence Hall of Science July 9, 2015

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

Basics on quantum information

Q8 Lecture. State of Quantum Mechanics EPR Paradox Bell s Thm. Physics 201: Lecture 1, Pg 1

CHAPTER 5 Wave Properties of Matter and Quantum Mechanics I

CHM 532 Notes on Wavefunctions and the Schrödinger Equation

74 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 10. Bohr-Einstein Atom

Singlet State Correlations

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

CHEM-UA 127: Advanced General Chemistry I

Honors 225 Physics Study Guide/Chapter Summaries for Final Exam; Roots Chapters 15-18

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

The Wave Structure of the Electric Field Michael Harney

Bell s inequalities and their uses

Gedankenexperimente werden Wirklichkeit The strange features of quantum mechanics in the light of modern experiments

Lagrangian Description for Particle Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Single-Particle Case

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

Quantum Theory. The most accurate and complete description of physical reality

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Basics on quantum information

Double slit questions

Lecture 21 Matter acts like waves!

4.1 Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox

Light Quantum Hypothesis

Delayed Choice Paradox

ON EPR PARADOX, BELL S INEQUALITIES AND EXPERIMENTS THAT PROVE NOTHING

Wave-Particle Duality & the Two-Slit Experiment: Analysis

Wave properties of matter & Quantum mechanics I. Chapter 5

Bell s Theorem 1964 Local realism is in conflict with quantum mechanics

Holism and Non-separability Applied to Quantum Mechanics

EPR Paradox Solved by Special Theory of Relativity

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

Wave-particle duality and the two-slit experiment: Analysis

The quantum vacuum: an interpretation of quantum mechanics

Statistical Mechanics

On the role of Decoherence in Bohmian Mechanics

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Bell s Theorem...What?! Entanglement and Other Puzzles

QUANTUM MECHANICS Intro to Basic Features

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

Physics 1C Lecture 28C. "For those who are not shocked when they first come across quantum theory cannot possibly have understood it.

Exploring the quantum world

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

The Quantum Handshake Explored

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

3 Bananaworld. 3.1 Einstein Podolsky Rosen bananas

Physicists' Epistemologies of Quantum Mechanics

The Relativistic Quantum World

Modern Physics notes Paul Fendley Lecture 3

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

On the unavoidability of the interpretations of Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v2 [physics.hist-ph] 26 Sep 2013

Class 21. Early Quantum Mechanics and the Wave Nature of Matter. Physics 106. Winter Press CTRL-L to view as a slide show. Class 21.

Where is quantum theory headed?

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

Michael H. Shulman, 2006 (Revisited ) WHY QUANTUM MECHANICS IS NON-LOCAL?

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Quantum mechanics (QM) deals with systems on atomic scale level, whose behaviours cannot be described by classical mechanics.

The reality of de Broglie s pilot wave

Chapter 24: A Brief Introduction to Quantum Theory

Photons uncertainty removes Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Abstract

62 My God, He Plays Dice! Chapter 8. Specific Heat

Basic paradoxes of statistical classical physics and quantum mechanics

A Re-Evaluation of Schrodinger s Cat Paradox

Electron in a Box. A wave packet in a square well (an electron in a box) changing with time.


Understanding Long-Distance Quantum Correlations

The Measurement Problem

A history of entanglement

Why quantum field theory?

Chapter 38 Quantum Mechanics

FAPP and Non-FAPP: A Pedagogical Essay Jeremy Bernstein Stevens Institute of Technology

Is the electron s charge 2e? A problem of the de Broglie-Bohm theory

In the early years of the twentieth century, Max Planck, Albert Einstein, Louis de Broglie, Neils

Paradoxes of the Aharonov-Bohm and the Aharonov-Casher effects.

The Wave Function. Chapter The Harmonic Wave Function

Physics. Light Quanta

Popper School Methodological Disproof of Quantum Logic

Quantum Computing. Part I. Thorsten Altenkirch

Proposal of Michelson-Morley experiment via single photon. interferometer: Interpretation of Michelson-Morley

SCH4U: History of the Quantum Theory

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

Protective Measurement: A Paradigm Shift in Understanding Quantum Mechanics

Introduction. You know, it would be sufficient to really understand. If I can t picture it, I can t understand it.

40 Wave Functions and Uncertainty

ELEC4705 Fall Tom Smy. LECTURE 3 Fundamentals of Quantum Theory

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

Henok Tadesse, Electrical engineer, BSc., Debrezeit, Ethiopia Mobile: or

WAVE PARTICLE DUALITY

Transcription:

ccxxii My God, He Plays Dice! David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Hidden Variablesccxxiii David Bohm s Hidden Variables David Bohm is perhaps best known for new experimental methods to test Einstein s supposed suggestion of hidden variables that would explain the EPR paradox by providing the information needed at the distant entangled particle, so it can coordinate its properties perfectly with the local particle. Bohm wrote in 1952, The usual interpretation of the quantum theory is based on an assumption having very far-reaching implications, viz., that the physical state of an individual system is completely specified by a wave function that determines only the probabilities of actual results that can be obtained in a statistical ensemble of similar experiments. This assumption has been the object of severe criticisms, notably on the part of Einstein, who has always believed that, even at the quantum level, there must exist precisely definable elements or dynamical variables determining (as in classical physics) the actual behavior of each individual system, and not merely its probable behavior. Since these elements or variables are not now included in the quantum theory and have not yet been detected experimentally, Einstein has always regarded the present form of the quantum theory as incomplete, although he admits its internal consistency. 1 Five years later, Bohm and his Israeli student Yakir Aharonov reformulated the original EPR argument in terms of electron spin. They said experimental tests with continuous variables would be much more difficult than tests with discrete quantities, such as the spin of electrons or polarization of photons. They wrote: We consider a molecule of total spin zero consisting of two atoms, each of spin one-half. The wave function of the system is therefore ψ = (1/ 2) [ ψ+ (1) ψ- (2) - ψ- (1) ψ+ (2) ] where ψ+ (1) refers to the wave function of the atomic state in which one particle (A) has spin +ħ/2, etc. The two atoms are then separated by a method that does not influence the total 1 Bohm 1952, p.166

ccxxiv My God, He Plays Dice! spin. After they have separated enough so that they cease to interact, any desired component of the spin of the first particle (A) is measured. Then, because the total spin is still zero, it can immediately be concluded that the same component of the spin of the other particle (B) is opposite to that of A. 2 Einstein may have pressed Bohm to develop hidden variables as the source of nonlocal behavior. Einstein had heartily approved of Bohm s textbook and was initially supportive of Bohm s new mechanics. Einstein thought Bohm was young enough and smart enough to produce the mathematical arguments that the older generation of determinist physicists like Erwin Schrödinger, Max Planck, and others had not been able to accomplish. But when Bohm finished the work, based on Louis de Broglie s 1923 pilot-wave idea (which Einstein had supported), Einstein rejected it, as he always had rejected nonlocality, as inconsistent with his theory of relativity. No Hidden Variables, but Hidden Constants? There may be no hidden variables, local or nonlocal. But there are hidden constants. Hidden in plain sight, they are the constants of the motion, conserved quantities like energy, momentum, angular momentum, and spin, both electron and photon. As Bohm and Aharonov say above, because the total spin is still zero,...the spin of the other particle (B) is opposite to that of A. Einstein s objective reality asks whether the particles might not simply have continuous paths from the start of the experiment to the final measurement(s), although the limits of quantum measurement may never allow us to know those paths. Conservation of momentum requires that positions where they finally do appear are equidistant from the origin, in order to conserve linear momentum. And every other conserved quantity, like angular momentum, electron or photon spin, as well as energy, also appear perfectly correlated at the two symmetric positions. It is the fundamental principle of conservation that governs the correlated outcome, not some hypothetical, faster than light, communication of information between the particles. 2 Bohm and Aharonov, 1957, p. 1070

Hidden Variablesccxxv Einstein s objective reality suggests that the conservation laws hold at every position along the path from the preparation of the entangled particles to their measurement. Just because we cannot measure positions and paths does not mean that they don t exist. The hidden constants of the motion then include the electron spins suggested by Bohm as the best test for the hidden variables needed to support nonseparability and entanglement. If the two particles have had the same opposing spins since thir state preparation at the start of the experiment, they will have the perfectly correlated opposing spins when they get measured. No information need be transferred between the particles. The particles carry the needed information with them as they follow Einstein s objective paths. Bohmian Mechanics Bohm is also well known for his Bohmian Mechanics, a formulation of non-relativistic quantum mechanics that emphasizes the motion of particles and promises to restore causality to physics. It is a deterministic theory, one of several interpretations that are the most popular alternatives to the Copenhagen Interpretation. By emphasizing the motion of particles, Bohmian mechanics somewhat deemphasizes the wave function Ψ, limiting its role to guiding the motion of the particles, in comparison to competitive interpretations that deny the existence of particles altogether. Bohmian mechanics includes a mechanism whereby physical effects can move faster than light, providing an explanation for Einstein s nonlocality. But as we saw above, Einstein s objective reality provides a simpler solution that removes any conflict between relativity and quantum mechanics, Bohmian mechanics describes particles as moving along continuous paths, agreeing with Einstein s objective reality. In the famous two-slit experiment, Bohm s particles always move through just one slit, even as the guiding wave function moves through both when both are open. This provides an intuitive

ccxxvi My God, He Plays Dice! solution to the two-slit experiment, which Richard Feynman calls the one mystery in quantum mechanics. See chapter 33. The Bohmian solution involves three simple steps First, close slit 1 and open slit 2. The particle goes through slit 2. It arrives at x on the plate with probability ψ2(x) 2, where ψ2 is the wave function which passed through slit 2. Second, close slit 2 and open slit 1. The particle goes through slit 1. It arrives at x on the plate with probability ψ1(x) 2, where ψ1 is the wave function which passed through slit 1. Third, open both slits. The particle goes through slit 1 or slit 2. It arrives at x with probability ψ1(x)+ψ2(x) 2. Now observe that in general, ψ1(x)+ψ2(x) 2 = ψ1(x)+ψ2(x) 2= ψ1(x) 2+ ψ2(x) 2 + 2Rψ*1(x) ψ2(x). The last term comes from the interference of the wave packets ψ1 and ψ2 which passed through slit 1 and slit 2. The probabilities of finding particles when both slits are open are different from the sum of slit 1 open and slit 2 open separately. The wave function determines the probabilities of finding particles, just as Einstein first proposed. 3 Irreversibility In his excellent 1951 textbook, Quantum Theory, Bohm described the necessity for irreversibility in any measurement. Bohm followed John von Neumann s measurement theory in which recorded data is irreversible. A measurement has only been made when new 3 Dürr and Teufel, 2009, p.9

Hidden Variables ccxxvii information has come into the world and adequate entropy has been carried away to insure the stability of the new information, long enough for it to be observed by the conscious observer. From the previous work it follows that a measurement process is irreversible in the sense that, after it has occurred, re-establishment of definite phase relations between the eigenfunctions of the measured variable is overwhelmingly unlikely. This irreversibility greatly resembles that which appears in thermodynamic processes, where a decrease of entropy is also an overwhelmingly unlikely possibility... Because the irreversible behavior of the measuring apparatus is essential for the destruction of definite phase relations and because, in turn, the destruction of definite phase relations is essential for the consistency of the quantum theory as a whole, it follows that thermodynamic irreversibility enters into the quantum theory in an integral way. This is in remarkable contrast to classical theory, where the concept of thermoynamic irreversibility plays no fundamental role in the basic sciences of mechanics and electrodynamics. 4 But Bohm changed his mind when he developed his more realistic and deterministic theory. Now he became concerned with the problem of microscopic irreversibility. See chapter 12. 4 Bohm, 1951, p.168

ccxxviii My God, He Plays Dice!

Hidden Variablesccxxix