Michael Friedman. Kant s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations

Similar documents
Paper read at History of Science Society 2014 Annual Meeting, Chicago, Nov. 9,

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Geometry and Philosophy

Kantian Essentialism in the Metaphysical Foundations 1

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time

Kant and Finitism. Crossing Worlds: Mathematical logisc, philosophy, art: For Juliette Kennedy. Bill Tait. 4 June 2016

What Comes After Structural Realism?

PHILOSOPHY OF SPACE AND TIME various authors. Philosophy of space and time is the branch of philosophy concerned with the issues

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

The Existence of Absolute Space

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Knowledge, Truth, and Mathematics

Appendix 2. Leibniz's Predecessors on the Continuum. (a) Aristotle

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 5: E = mc 2 ; Philosophical Significance of Special Relativity

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Friedman s Thesis Ryan Samaroo Department of Philosophy, University of Bristol, Bristol, BS6 6JL, UK

Galilean Spacetime (Neo-Newtonian Spacetime) P t = 2

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

SPACE, TIME AND GEOMETR Y

Temporal Extension. 1. Time as Quantity

Boscovich s theory: strict Newtonian physics, by Roger J. Anderton

Erwin Marquit. Dialectical Materialism in Physical Theory

Lecture 5: Leibniz equivalence and Putnam s paradox

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

Leibniz and Cantor on the Actual Infinite

Leibniz s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii

Name: Chris Arledge. School: Ohio University. Mailing Address: 36 Poston Rd, The Plains, OH Phone:

Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories

Contents Part A Number Theory Highlights in the History of Number Theory: 1700 BC 2008

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 6: Introduction to General Relativity

Mathematical versus physical meaning of classical mechanics quantities

o is a type symbol. There are no other type symbols.

An Ontology Diagram for Coordination of the Hylomorphically Treated Entities

PHY1020 BASIC CONCEPTS IN PHYSICS I

Intuitions, Concepts and Wholes

THE MEANING OF RELATIVITY

A PRIORI REVISABILITY AND THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS IN SCIENCE

Reviews 341. r 2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

The Real, the Infinite, Categories, and Cardinal Numbers: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

PHYSICS 107. Lecture 10 Relativity: The Postulates

Beyond Newton and Leibniz: The Making of Modern Calculus. Anthony V. Piccolino, Ed. D. Palm Beach State College Palm Beach Gardens, Florida

Class #14: Intuitionism

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Physics 141 Dynamics 1 Page 1. Dynamics 1

THE METAPHYSICS OF IMPENETRABILITY: EULER'S CONCEPTION OF FORCE

The REVOLUTION in GEOMETRY

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Module 3: Cartesian Coordinates and Vectors

INTUITION AND THE AXIOMATIC METHOD

The Epistemology of Geometry

Causality 03: The Modern "Epistemic Turn" and Causality

Topics in Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North

Observations on Category Theory. John L. Bell

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

Conventionalism and Modern Physics: A Re-Assessment*

Sortals and Criteria of Identity

Logical Idealism & Einstein s Theory of Relativity Schlick s Critique of Cassirer s Monograph Zur Einsteinschen Relativitätstheorie (1921)

Kant s Newtonianism: a reappraisal

Development of Thought continued. The dispute between rationalism and empiricism concerns the extent to which we

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design

Swiss Philosophical Preprint Series. Olivier Massin. When Forces Meet Each Other

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

Alternative Technologies

Weyl and Reichenbach on apriority

SIR ISAAC NEWTON ( )

Richard T. W. Arthur, McMaster University. 1. Commentary

This page intentionally left blank

CONSEQUENCES FOR SPECIAL RELATIVITY THEORY OF RESTORING EINSTEIN S NEGLECTED ADDITIVE CONSTANTS IN THE LORENTZ TRANSFORMATION

Hilbert s significance for the philosophy of mathematics (1922) Paul Bernays

CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

ON THE UNIFIED FIELD THEORY Bertrand Wong, Eurotech, S pore,

British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18(5) 2010: ARTICLE. Adrian Bardon

How Euler Did It. Today we are fairly comfortable with the idea that some series just don t add up. For example, the series

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

A Vindication of Kantian Euclidean Space

How Euler Did It. by Ed Sandifer. Foundations of Calculus. September 2006

Philosophiekolloquium FB Philosophie KGW

Philosophy of Physics 146

Notes de lecture 357 PROCESS PHYSICS: FROM INFORMATION THEORY TO QUANTUM SPACE AND MATTER

Leibniz s Possible Worlds. Liu Jingxian Department of Philosophy Peking University

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

1.2 Gauss Curvature (Informal Treatment)

A New Conception of Science

Aristotle, Space and Time

Elements of a Bahá í-inspired Natural Theology

διανοια IS GEOMETRY ANALYTIC? 1. INTRODUCTION MGHANGA DAVID MWAKIMA

On the Studies of Space: in Physics and Metaphysics. Alexander Ken Jie Lim, Bachelor of Arts words

MATH1014 Calculus II. A historical review on Calculus

McTaggart s Argument for the Unreality of Time:

On Objectivity and Models for Measuring. G. Rasch. Lecture notes edited by Jon Stene.

Precis of Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

Abstract and Variable Sets in Category Theory 1

Transcription:

Michael Friedman. Kant s Construction of Nature: A Reading of the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. xix + 646 pp., bibl., index. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. $110 (cloth). Kant s Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (MFNS) was published in 1786, three years after the Prolegomena and one year before the B-Edition of the Critique of Pure Reason. The MFNS plays a doubly crucial role in Kant s work: it shows how the Critique s a priori Principles of Pure Understanding become fully binding on nature, thus fulfilling one half of that book s purpose; and, because it falls between the first and second editions, it connects on many levels with Kant s revisions, which are indeed centered on questions relating to time, space and motion. The general neglect of the work among twentieth-century scholars derives from views of those such as Peter Strawson, who contended that Kant s concern with a priori principles of natural science really does have the effect of obscuring what there is of substance in a central, and crucial section of the [Critique], viz. the Analogies of Experience (The Bounds of Sense [Methuen, 1966], p. 23). By contrast, Michael Friedman s work over the last thirty years has centered on restoring Kant s connection to the exact sciences, thereby inspiring a generation of younger scholars. In this long-awaited book, he offers a detailed reading of the MFNS, triangulating its position in Kant s work relative to the Leibniz-Clarke affair and Johann Lambert s and Leonhard Euler s reactions to it, to Kant s pre-critique monadistic physics and metaphysics, and to the evolution of Kant s thought across the two editions of the Critique (1781 and 1787). The book is intended neither as a detailed commentary, such as Konstantin Pollok s comprehensive Kants Metaphysische Anfansgründe der Naturwissenschaft: Ein kritischer Kommentar (Meiner, 2001),

nor as a fully contextualized intellectual history. Rather, by analyzing Kant s theories of space, time, and motion within a thin historical slice, it will allow for further work on the deep conceptual transformation that began with Kant s scientific situation at the end of the eighteenth century and concluded with the revolutionary new (Einsteinian) space-time theories (p. xi). The place of the MFNS in Kant s system can be illustrated by the Critique s Analogies of Experience, alluded to in the quotation from Strawson, above. The Critique s functions of judgment (individual, particular, general; subject-predicate, if-then, either-or; etc.) yield the table of categories, which include fundamental logico-mathematical concepts, such as those of quantity (unity, plurality, totality), and metaphysico-dynamic concepts, such as substanceaccident, cause-effect, reciprocal causality, and so forth. Each category is then attached to a timeschema, to yield proto-physical concepts: logical quantity becomes the concept of number through the schema of addition (a totality of a plurality of unities i.e., a denumerated set), causality becomes efficient causality through the schema of an event that necessitates a succeeding effect. These schematized concepts are finally projected onto space and time to produce Principles of Pure Understanding, such as that all spatio-temporal appearances can be quantified (Axioms, Anticipations) or that all events are subject to the Law of Causality (the Second Analogy). Finally, in the MFNS, these Principles are supplemented with the concept of matter to produce embryonic laws of nature, such as the Law of Inertia (every body persists in uniform motion unless disturbed by an external cause). It is then clear why Friedman s approach will inevitably produce more interesting results. It allows us to see how the law of reciprocal causality of the Analogies connects to a theory of simultaneity based on causal dependencies within a space-time manifold whereas on Strawson s approach, stripped of these connections, even what is of substance in the Analogies

remains obscure. And even if it cannot be said that all of Kant s analyses in the MFNS are convincing, it remains the case that little of the Critique s first two sections (the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Analytic) is comprehensible without reference to it and still less the significance of Kant s revisions to the A-Edition. Since the task of the MFNS is to lay out the panoply of physico-mathematical principles that result from realizing the Principles of Pure Understanding as material laws, it has four parts: Phoronomy (kinematics), Dynamics (theory of attractive and repulsive forces), Mechanics, and Phenomenology (theory of real vs. apparent objects). These correspond to the four subsets of the categories (Quantity, Quality, Relation, Modality) and to their respective Principles. Kant s Construction of Nature follows these main divisions, devoting a chapter to each. Friedman s fundamental and fundamentally correct historical thesis is that the principles of the MFNS are themselves fully realized by Newton s laws of motion. That only a Newtonian could have arisen as a Kant was indeed a founding claim of the neo-kantian movement; however, not since Hermann Cohen s Kant s Theory of Experience (1871) has it been advocated so convincingly, and never before in such detail. Viewing both Newton and Kant through the lens of space-time theories, above all the work of Howard Stein, Friedman demonstrates convincingly that the convergent procedure for determining absolute space in the Phenomenology of the MFNS (it is the center of mass of the solar system) is nothing other than an implementation of Newton s method for determining true motions in Book 3 of Principia. Newtonian absolute space is replaced in the MFNS by an ideal on which reason converges, but which is never given as an empirical datum. But Friedman takes a further step, arguing in his introduction that the general theory of motion Kant alludes to in the B-Edition s sections on time (which explain as much a priori

cognition as the general theory of motion evinces [B49]) is nothing other than Newton s laws. This programmatic claim is developed further in his chapter on the Phoronomy, where he argues that Kant rejects not only Newton s doctrine of absolute space but also that of absolute time. Because of this deeper motivation that is central to Kant s project, Kant must hold that no temporal relations whatsoever can be viewed as pre-existing and that all temporal relations are the products of empirical constructions by means of the a priori principles of the understanding. Newton s laws therefore define what we mean by true temporal uniformity. Two temporal intervals are truly equal if they represent the times during which an inertially moving body were to traverse equal distances (p. 65). Because time has no mathematical structure at this stage (i.e., prior to the introduction of the Law of Inertia), the Phoronomy s proof of the kinematic parallelogram law must take place instantaneously, in the tangent space of the space-time point, so that there can be no question of what we now call affine structure (p. 81n). But the general theory of motion in question is neither Newton s laws, nor the MFNS as a whole, but only the Phoronomy of the latter. The constructions of the Phoronomy involve divisions into time-parts, because they are constructions describing spatia percursa, or finite path-elements, as in the De Motu in Genere of Euler s Analytical Mechanics, specifically 82f. Euler there shows how to transform a uniform motion relative to absolute space into a uniform motion relative to any other uniformly moving frame, by appealing to the nature of the triangle that the motions describe. Since, Euler explains, his laws of motion hold in all such frames ( 77) he does not have to worry about absolute space motion. which philosophers can determine relative to the fixed stars, if they like.

Kant precisely inverts Euler s proof: assuming Galiean relativity as the Fundamental Law of the Phoronomy, he appeals to the geometrical properties of the same triangle to prove the kinematic parallelogram law. Both thinkers thereby prove that the class of paths generated by means of Galilean transformations of the scales form, in Eulerian terminology, an affine family. Both thereby satisfy the Postulates of Lambert s science of Phoronomy, which, puts together space and time and thereby generates the theory of motion, by showing how any uniform motion can serve as the measure of any other. Both proofs succeed, however, under one condition only: namely, that the uniform passage of time independent of position and state of motion is given. The inferential structure of the Phoronomy is in other words incomprehensible unless absolute time is at least implicitly assumed (cf. Robert Palter, Absolute Space and Absolute Motion in Kant s Critical Philosophy, Synthese, 1971, 23:47 62). Since Kant explicitly asserts, at B67 of the Aesthetic, that time contains relations of simultaneity, duration, and asymmetric linear order [Nacheinander] before any consciousness, and that these determine how intuitions are posited, there can be little doubt that the full mathematical structure of time is already in place at this stage. Friedman, by contrast, rejects as absurd that Kant wishes to prove the parallelogram law in pure intuition, arguing instead that Kant s concern here is with a late medieval theory of intension and remission (p. 60), because there was not yet a single real number system, which was only established in the late nineteenth century (pp. 53 54) Although Euler and Lambert form, on his account, one of the triangulation-pillars of his interpretation, neither author is discussed in this chapter. The neo-kantian thesis that the Aesthetic s doctrines of space and time are somehow completed by the Principles is widely held among contemporary Kant scholars, though its

exact consequences are often unclear. In Friedman s work, by contrast, the costs and benefits of this claim are displayed with the greatest precision: because his Kant chooses a Riemannian, additive approach to space-time geometry over a Kleinian, subtractive one, it is not only the Transcendental Aesthetic that must be eliminated, as in classical neo-kantianism, but the Phoronomy as well. The problem is not that Friedman s reading is too modern, but just the opposite. By interpreting Kant against the background of the fourteenth and seventeenth centuries, he buries the connection to analytical mechanics. And by eliminating the Phoronomy from Kant s system, he renders that book incongruent with the structure of the Critique. In sum, while Kant s Construction of Nature remains a rich repository of analyses of individual passages of the MFNS and their relation to Newton s work, neither the goal of illuminating the evolution of space-time theory nor that of connecting the MFNS structurally to the Critique is achieved. Precisely because of the power of Friedman s analyses, this is a book that must be read critically. DAVID HYDER References Euler, Leonhard. Mechanica sive Motus Scientia Analytice Exposita, 2 vols. St. Petersburg: Academy of Sciences, 1736. Euler, Leonhard. Leonhard Euler s Mechanik: Oder analytische Darstellung der Wissenschaft von der Bewegung mit Anmerkungen und Erläuterungen. Ed. By J.P. Wolfers. Greifswald: C. A. Koch, 1848. Norton, John D. Geometries in Collision: Einstein, Klein and Riemann, In: The Symbolic Universe: Geometry and Physics 1890-1930. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, pp. 128-144. Palter, Robert. Absolute Space and Absolute Motion in Kant s Critical Philosophy, Synthese, 1971, 23:47 62.