Ambiguous implementation: the partition model

Similar documents
A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Incentive compatibility of rational expectations equilibrium in large economies: a counterexample

Equilibrium Theory under Ambiguity

On non-revealing rational expectations equilibrium

A new perspective to rational expectations: maximin rational expectations equilibrium

Ambiguity aversion solves the conflict between efficiency and incentive compatibility

On extensive form implementation of contracts in differential information economies

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

1 Web Appendix: Equilibrium outcome under collusion (multiple types-multiple contracts)

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Definitions and Proofs

Mechanism Design with Ambiguous Transfers

Rational Expectations Equilibrium Under Ambiguity

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Efficient Random Assignment with Cardinal and Ordinal Preferences: Online Appendix

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation

Incentives and the core of an exchange economy: a survey

Monotonic models and cycles

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

Continuous and Feasible Implementation of Rational-Expectations Lindahl Allocations

Mechanism Design with Ambiguous Transfers

Elimination of Arbitrage States in Asymmetric Information Models

Introduction to Game Theory

On the Maximal Domain Theorem

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk

Uncertainty, Efficiency and Incentive Compatibility

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Social Choice and Welfare Epsilon-Ex Post Implementation

Computation of Efficient Nash Equilibria for experimental economic games

Notes on Mechanism Designy

On the Impossibility of Black-Box Truthfulness Without Priors

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Fault Tolerant Implementation

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach)

Revenue Maximization in Multi-Object Auctions

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Information, Bargaining Power and Efficiency: Re-examining the Role of Incomplete Information in Crisis Bargaining.

Preference, Choice and Utility

Values for cooperative games with incomplete information: An eloquent example

Indescribable Contingencies versus Unawareness and Incomplete Contracting

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

Market Equilibrium and the Core

IMPOSSIBILITY OF A WALRASIAN BARGAINING SOLUTION 1

PREFERENCE REVELATION GAMES AND STRONG CORES OF ALLOCATION PROBLEMS WITH INDIVISIBILITIES

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information

Interim efficiency with MEU-preferences

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Basic Game Theory. Kate Larson. January 7, University of Waterloo. Kate Larson. What is Game Theory? Normal Form Games. Computing Equilibria

Rational expectations can preclude trades

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Network Topology, Higher Orders of Stability and Efficiency

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

Equilibrium theory with asymmetric information and with infinitely many commodities

Correlated Equilibria of Classical Strategic Games with Quantum Signals

Competitive Equilibrium

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Notes on General Equilibrium

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS

Existence of Nash Networks in One-Way Flow Models

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation

Robustness of Equilibria in Anonymous Local Games

Implementability, Walrasian Equilibria, and Efficient Matchings

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

First Welfare Theorem

A Game-Theoretic Analysis of Games with a Purpose

An Efficient Solution to the Informed Principal Problem

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

ROBUST IMPLEMENTATION: THE CASE OF DIRECT MECHANISMS. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris. March 2006 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION PAPER NO.

Efficient Repeated Implementation

Virtual Robust Implementation and Strategic Revealed Preference

Mechanism Design: Dominant Strategies

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Référence bibliographique. "Incentives and the core of an exchange economy: a survey" Forges, Françoise ; Minelli, Enrico ; Vohra, Rajiv

Transcription:

Econ Theory 2017 63:233 261 DOI 101007/s00199-016-1023-y RESEARCH ARTICLE Ambiguous implementation: the partition model Luciano I de Castro 1 Zhiwei Liu 2 Nicholas C Yannelis 1 Received: 22 February 2016 / Accepted: 1 December 2016 / Published online: 23 December 2016 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2016 Abstract In a partition model, we show that each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation of a single good economy is implementable as a maxi equilibrium When there are more than one good, we introduce three conditions If none of the three conditions is satisfied, then a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation may not be implementable However, as long as one of the three conditions is satisfied, each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is implementable Our work generalizes and Different versions of this paper were presented at the University of Queensland, Australian Econometric Society meetings, SWET conference, Paris, University of Glasgow, Midwest Economic Theory Meetings at Lawrence, USC, University of St Andrews, UC-Davis, UIBE, Johns Hopkins University, UC-Santa Barbara, Ecole Polytechnique, SAET conference, Portugal, Rice University and the NBER/GE conference at Indiana We have greatly benefited from comments, discussions and suggestions by many participants in the above presentations, and a referee Special thanks to Filipe Marins da Rocha who read earlier versions of this paper and whose suggestions lead to the current one Liu gratefully acknowledges the funding from NSFC No 71571122; the funding from the Research and Innovation Centre of Metropolis Economic and Social Development, Capital University of Economics and Business; and the funding from the humanities university project of China University of Political Science and Law B Zhiwei Liu liuzhiwei@cuebeducn Luciano I de Castro decastroluciano@gmailcom Nicholas C Yannelis nicholasyannelis@gmailcom 1 Department of Economics, The University of Iowa, Iowa City, IA, USA 2 International School of Economics and Management, Capital University of Economics and Business, Beijing, China

234 L I de Castro et al extends the recent paper of de Castro et al Games Econ Behav 2015 doi:101016/j geb201510010 Keywords Maxi preferences Maxi efficient allocations Maxi equilibrium Implementation JEL Classification D51 D61 D81 D82 1 Introduction We study the implementation of maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocations in an ambiguous asymmetric information economy The implementation notion is the same as in de Castro et al 2015 That is, we check whether each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation can be reached through a mechanism as a maxi equilibrium In a maxi equilibrium, each agent maximizes the payoff that takes into account the worst actions of all the other agents against him and also the worst state that can occur This paper differs from de Castro et al 2015 in that we consider a more general setup, which includes de Castro et al 2015 as a special case This new and more general framework allows us to consider the standard exchange economies with differential information that have been studied in the literature, eg, Angelopoulos and Koutsougeras 2015, Castro et al 2011, Yannelis 1991 among others In particular, we adopt a partition model and indicate that the results of this paper cannot be captured by the type model of de Castro et al 2015 As a matter of fact, the type model cannot capture the standard two persons economies as it is shown in Sect 3 Our economy consists of a finite set of states of nature, a finite set of agents, each of whom is characterized by an information partition,a multi-prior set, arandom initial endowment and an ex post utility function Furthermore, the agents have maxi preferences In an ambiguous asymmetric information economy, de Castro and Yannelis 2009 showed that any efficient allocation is incentive compatible with respect to the maxi preferences 1 This is not true in the standard expected utility Bayesian framework Indeed, an efficient allocation may not be incentive compatible with respect to the Bayesian preferences as it was shown by Holmström and Myerson 1983 Furthermore, Palfrey and Srivastava 1987 showed that under the Bayesian preferences, neither efficient allocations nor core allocations define implementable social choice correspondence, when agents are incompletely informed about the environment In a recent paper, de Castro et al 2015 showed that if an ambiguous asymmetric information economy can be represented by the standard type model of the implementation literature, then each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is implementable as a maxi equilibrium 1 A related work is done by Bosmans and Ooghe 2013 They showed that maxi is the only criterion satisfying anonymity, continuity, weak Pareto and weak Hammond equity

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 235 However, many economies are not representable by the standard type model Our partition model includes these economies We illustrate with an example that in such an economy, the agents may strictly prefer a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation to their initial endowment Consequently, the problem of implementation in these economies is relevant and interesting The main result of the paper is that each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation of a single good economy is implementable When there are more than one good, we characterize three sufficient conditions As long as one of the three conditions is satisfied, each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is implementable We show by means of examples that if none of the three conditions holds, then a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation may not be implementable However, the three conditions are not necessary for implementation Since the concepts maxi core allocations, maxi value allocations and maxi Walrasian expectations equilibrium allocations defined in de Castro and Yannelis 2009,Angelopoulos and Koutsougeras 2015, He and Yannelis 2015 are all maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient, the implementation of these allocations in a more general model is captured by this paper We differ from de Castro et al 2015 in that we allow the players reports to be incompatible It follows that the type model of de Castro et al 2015 can be converted into a partition model However, the converse is not true in general as we will show in Sect 3 The paper is organized as follows Section 2 defines an ambiguous asymmetric information economy and introduces the maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient notions In Sect 3, we present a counterexample which indicates why the type model cannot capture the case of incompatible reports when agents preferences are maxi In Sect 4, we introduce the direct revelation mechanism and the maxi equilibrium Sections 5 and 6 present the main results of the paper Finally, we conclude in Sect 7 2 Ambiguous asymmetric information economy Let denote a finite set of states of nature, ω a state of nature, R l + the l-goods commodity space and I the set of N agents, ie, I = 1,,N} An ambiguous asymmetric information economy E is a set E = ; F i, P i, e i, u i : i I } F i is a partition of Let F i denote an event and ω a state in the event Then, in the interim, if the state ω occurs, agent i only knows that the event has occurred We impose the standard assumption, that when a state occurs, and all agents truthfully report their information, they will know the realized state 2 That is, Assumption 1 For each ω, j I EF j ω = ω}, where E F j ω denotes the element in F j that contains the state ω 2 This assumption is without loss of generality, since if there exist two different states ω and ω, such that no agent is able to distinguish them, then the two states may as well be treated as one state

236 L I de Castro et al Since the events are observable in the interim, it is natural to assume that at ex ante each agent is able to form a probability assessment over his partition For each i, let μ i : σ F i [0, 1] be a probability measure defined on the algebra generated by agent i s partition Assumption 2 For each i and for each event F i, μ i > 0 Each μ i is a well-defined probability, but it is not defined on every state of nature Indeed, if = ω,ω } with ω = ω, then the probability of the event is well defined, but not the probability of the event ω} or the event ω } Let i be the set of all probability measures over 2 that agree with μ i Formally, i = probability measure π i : 2 [0, 1] π i A = μ i A, A σ F i } Let P i, a nonempty, closed and convex subset of i, be agent i s multi-prior set Agent i s random initial endowment is e i : R l + Each agent receives his endowment in the interim That is, e i is F i -measurable, meaning that e i is constant on each element of F i Formally, Assumption 3 Let F i be agent i s partition and fix any ω k Wehavee i ω = e i ω k for any ω ω k This ensures that at each state ω, the event ω incorporates the information revealed by the endowment Clearly, if each e i is state independent, then it is automatically F i -measurable Assug e i to be F i -measurable is more general than being constant Finally, u i : R l + R is agent i s ex post utility function, taking the form of u i c i ; ω, where c i denotes agent i s consumption The ex post utility function u i is strictly monotone in consumption 3 Also, we assume that each agent knows his utility function in the interim, and consequently, each agent s utility function needs to be F i -measurable Formally, Assumption 4 For each i and for each fixed c i R l +, u i c i ; is F i -measurable That is, given any c i R l +, and any two states ω, ˆω, with ω = ˆω, wehave u i c i ; ω = u i ci ;ˆω, whenever ω E F i ˆω The F i -measurability of the ex post utility functions is often assumed in games with incomplete information Indeed, one may regard F i as agent i s type space, and F i as a possible type of agent i Then clearly, assug the function u i c i ; to be F i -measurable, is the same as assug u i to depend on agent i s type Let L denote the set of all functions from to R l + Agent i s allocation or in short, i-allocation specifies his consumption bundle at each state of nature, ie, x i LLet x = x 1,,x N denote an allocation of the above economy E An allocation x is said to be feasible, if for each ω, i I x i ω = i I e i ω We postulate that the agents have maxi preferences see Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989 3 For each fixed ω, wehaveu i c i ; ω < u i c i + ɛ; ω, whenever ɛ is a none zero vector in R l +

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 237 Definition 1 Take any two allocations of agent i, f i and h i, from the set L Agent i prefers f i to h i under the maxi preferences written as f i MP i h i π i P i ω u i f i ω ; ω π i ω π i P i ω u i h i ω ; ω π i ω 1 Furthermore, agent i strictly prefers f i to h i, f i i MP h i, if he prefers f i to h i but not the reverse, ie, f i i MP h i but h i i MP f i The Bayesian and the Wald-type maxi preferences of de Castro and Yannelis 2009 4 are special cases of this general multi-prior model Indeed, if each agent has a prior, ie, P i is a singleton set for each i, then the multi-prior preferences become the Bayesian preferences If P i = i for each i, then the multi-prior preferences become the maxi preferences in de Castro and Yannelis 2009 They de Castro and Yannelis 2009 showed that 1 is equivalent to the following formulation F i F i u i f i ω ; ω ω μ i u i h i ω ; ω ω μ i 2 The interest of the maxi preferences in de Castro and Yannelis 2009 comes from that only under these preferences any efficient allocation is incentive compatible 5 Indeed, under the Bayesian preferences, an efficient allocation may not be incentive compatible as it was shown by Holmström and Myerson 1983 The notions of individual rationality and efficiency below are standard, except now the preferences are maxi Definition 2 A feasible allocation x = x i i I is said to be maxi individually rational, if for each i I, x i i MP e i Definition 3 A feasible allocation x = x i i I is said to be ex ante maxi efficient, if there does not exist another feasible allocation y = y i i I, such that y i i MP x i for all i, and y i i MP x i for at least one i Remark 1 Some examples of maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocations are maxi core allocations, maxi value allocations and 4 See also de Castro et al 2015 5 In addition to the fact that there is no longer a conflict between efficiency and incentive compatibility under the maxi preferences, the adoption of these preferences provides new insights and superior outcomes than the Bayesian preferences as it has been shown in Angelopoulos and Koutsougeras 2015, Bodoh-Creed 2012, Bose et al 2006, de Castro and Yannelis 2009, Castro et al 2011, de Castro et al 2015, Gollier 2014, He and Yannelis 2015, Koufopoulos and Kozhan 2016, Liu 2014, Ohtaki and Ozaki 2015, Traeger 2014, just to name a few Furthermore, the maxi preferences solve the Ellsberg Paradox see, eg, Castro and Yannelis 2013 Interestingly, ambiguity does not necessarily vanish through statistical learning in an one-urn environment Zimper and Ma 2016

238 L I de Castro et al maxi Walrasian expectations equilibrium allocations defined in de Castro and Yannelis 2009, Angelopoulos and Koutsougeras 2015, He and Yannelis 2015 3 A comparison with de Castro Liu Yannelis With the standard type model, de Castro et al 2015 showed that in an l-goods economy, each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation can be reached by means of noncooperation The standard type model is less general than the partition model of this paper A partition model can be represented by the standard type model if the economy satisfies a stronger assumption than Assumption 1: Assumption 5 For any j I and E F j F j, j I EF j = ω} for some ω Assumption 5 ensures that there is always an agreed state, regardless of the agents reports 6 Unlike Assumption 1, Assumption 5 does not allow incompatible reports, ie, the existence of a combination E F 1,,E F N with j I EF j = Clearly, Assumption 5 is not satisfied by many economies For a detailed discussion on the relationship between partition model and type model, please see de Castro et al 2016 Below we present a counterexample which indicates why the type model cannot capture the case of incompatible reports when agents are ambiguous This is not the case for agents with Bayesian preferences Furthermore, in the economy below, the agents are strictly better off if they trade, and therefore, the problem of implementation is relevant and interesting Example 1 There are two agents, one good, and three possible states of nature = a, b, c} The ex post utility function of each agent i is u i c i ; ω = c i The agents random initial endowments, information partitions and multi-prior sets are: e 1 a, e 1 b, e 1 c = 5, 5, 1 ; F 1 = a, b}, c}} e 2 a, e 2 b, e 2 c = 5, 1, 5 ; F 2 = a, c}, b}} P 1 = probability measure π 1 : 2 [0, 1] π 1 a, b} = 2 3 and π 1 c}= 1 } 3 P 2 = probability measure π 2 : 2 [0, 1] π 2 a, c} = 2 3 and π 2 b}= 1 } 3 A maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is x = x1 a x 1 b x 1 c = x 2 a x 2 b x 2 c 5 48 12 5 12 48 6 Indeed, in the standard type model, each agent i has a type set T i, and the set of states of nature is T = T 1 T N LetT i = F i and T =,thenwehavet = T 1 T N because of Assumption 5 That is, if a partition model satisfies Assumption 5, then it can be represented by the standard type model

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 239 Notice that both agents strictly prefer the allocation x to the initial endowment e under the maxi preferences Indeed, we have for each i, 2 3 } 5, 5 + 1 2 1 = 1824 < 3 3 } 5, 48 + 1 12 = 1826 3 This economy cannot be captured by the type model adopted in de Castro et al 2015 Indeed, in the terology of a type model, each player has two types, T 1 = a, b}, c}} and T 2 = a, c}, b}} It follows that the set of states of nature T = T 1 T 2 has four elements Since there are only three states of nature a, b and c in this economy, it is not possible to represent the economy by the type model, unless we add a zero probability state d Due to the nonzero probability event assumption Assumption 1 of de Castro et al 2015, we cannot have d} T i, i = 1, 2 The only way to incorporate the state d is to have T 1 = a, b}, c, d}} and T 2 = a, c}, b, d}} However, this is not consistent with the non-bayesian expected utility of this paper In a Wald-type maxi model, an agent does not form a probability assessment on the states that he cannot distinguish 7 Since states c and d are in the same event, agent 1 cannot distinguish these two states However, if agent 1 knows that state d occurs with probability zero, then he can form a unique probability assessment on the states within the event c, d}, ie, π 1 c} = 1 3 and π 1 d} = 0 This contradicts the fact that an ambiguous agent assigns a probability only on an event and not on the states in the event that he cannot distinguish A similar argument holds for agent 2 at the event b, d} The question we pose is the following: Could one provide a noncooperative foundation for the maxi efficient and maxi individually rational notions in a general partition model? We address this question in the next section Since the type model of de Castro et al 2015 cannot cover incompatible reports, the proof of de Castro et al 2015 does not work here Our work generalizes and extends de Castro et al 2015 4 The direct revelation mechanism and the maxi equilibrium A direct revelation mechanism is a noncooperative game, which is defined based on an allocation and its underlying ambiguous asymmetric information economy In the interim, a state of nature ω is realized Each player i privately observes the event ω and receives the initial endowment e i ω Then, each player i reports F i, but the report may not be truthful Definition 4 Suppose the realized state the true state is ω Then, a report of player i, F i, is a lie, if it differs from the event ω Definition 5 A strategy of player i is a function s i : F i F i Let S i denote player i s strategy set, S = i I S i the strategy set and s S a strategy profile For simplicity, we slightly abuse the notation, and use s ω to 7 In this paper, an agent cannot distinguish the states of nature within an event F i

240 L I de Castro et al Fig 1 Timeline denote the players reports, when they adopt the strategy profile s, and the realized state is ω, ie, s ω = s 1 E F 1 ω,,s N E F N ω Clearly, for any ω, s ω i I F i The players report events simultaneously The reports then detere their net transfers Figure 1 shows the timeline, as in de Castro et al 2015 Definition 6 Let x be the planned allocation The planned redistribution planned net transfer is given by x e That is, the planned redistribution is the adjustments needed to go from the initial endowment e to x The planned redistribution and the players reports together detere the actual redistribution From Assumption 1, we know for any collection of reports E F 1,,E F N,the j I EF j is either singleton or empty Definition 7 We say the reports E F 1,,E F N are compatible, if j I EF j = ω}, for some ω Furthermore, we refer the state ω as the implied state the agreed state The implementation literature often assumes a feasibility condition, ie, the set of feasible alternatives is the same across the states of nature Now, our players receive initial endowments first, and then redistribute the endowments based on their reports, as in de Castro et al 2015 We adopt the feasibility condition of de Castro et al 2015 that each player is rich enough to participate in the revelation mechanism That is, for each i, ω and ω, wehavee i ω + x i ω e i ω R l + When the reports E F 1,,E F N are compatible, the players end up with e ω + x ω e ω, where ω is the agreed state, and x ω e ω is the planned redistribution specified for the state ω Clearly, if all the players tell the truth, then ω = ω and the players get what they planned to get, e ω + x ω e ω = x ω However, since some player may successfully lie, ω may not be the true state As a consequence, e ω + x ω e ω may differ from x ω, ie, the players may not end up with the planned allocation When the reports are not compatible at the realized state ω, lies are detected There are many ways to resolve the players payoffs In a single good economy, the mechanism designer MD could appropriate ω x i e i } from each player i The MD does not know the realized state, but he knows the planned redistribution

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 241 x e, so he knows ω x i e i } for each player i Inanl-goods economy, the mechanism designer could randomly pick a state ω and enforce the net transfer x ω e ω Furthermore, no trade is also an option, that is, each player keeps his initial endowments The role of the MD is standard That is, the MD is not a player in this paper 8 When a punishment is due according to the rules of the mechanism, the MD does not worry about whether carrying out this punishment is socially optimal or not As we will show in the proof of Theorem 1, the MD does not need to actually impose the punishment The threat that he will appropriate ω x i e i } from each player when the reports are incompatible, will induce the players to report truthfully Let D i x e, E F 1,,E F N denote the actual redistribution of player i It depends on the planned redistribution x e and the players reports Its exact form will be defined in Sects 5 and 6 Definition 8 Let g i be the outcome function of player i, which depends on the planned redistribution, the reports of the players and the realized state of nature, ie, g i x e, E F 1,,E F N,ω = e i ω + D i x e, E F 1,,E F N, 3 where e i ω + D i x e, E F 1,,E F N is the bundle of the goods, that player i ends up consug Finally, define for each i a final payoff function, which tells us the final payoff that player i ends up Formally, Definition 9 Denote by v i the final payoff function of player i It takes the form of v i x e, E F 1,,E F N ; ω = u i ei ω + D i x e, E F 1,,E F N ; ω In what follows, we write v i E F 1,,E F N ; ω instead of v i x e, E F 1,,E F N ; ω forconvenience A direct revelation mechanism associated with a planned allocation x and its underlying ambiguous asymmetric information economy E = ; F i, P i, e i, u i i I } is a set Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I In view of the players Wald-type maxi preferences, we adopt the maxi equilibrium of de Castro et al 2015 It says that every player adopts a criterion ala Wald Wald 1950 That is, each player maximizes the payoff that takes into account the worst actions of all the other players against him and also the worst state that can occur Definition 10 In a direct revelation mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I, a strategy profile s = s1,,s N constitutes a maxi equilibrium ME, iffor each player i, his strategy si maximizes his interim payoff lower bound, that is, the function si : F i F i satisfies, for each F i, 8 There are interesting papers in which the MD is a player We refer interested readers to Chakravorty et al 2006andBaliga et al 1997

242 L I de Castro et al v i s E F i F i ; i, E F i ; ω v i ÊF i, E F i ; ω, E F i F i ; 4 for all Ê F i F i, where E F i denotes the reports from all the other players, so E F i F i = j =i F j The maxi equilibrium has the flavor of the robust control of Hansen and Sargent 2001 in which the decision maker maximizes his payoff taking into account the worst possible model 9 Unlike the restricted maxi equilibrium notion of Dasgupta et al 1979, the maxi equilibrium does not need each player to correctly guess his opponents strategies to reach an equilibrium Moreover, the maxi equilibrium is unique, whenever truth telling is optimal for each player 10 Now, we say an allocation x is implementable, if x can be realized through a maxi equilibrium of the direct revelation mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I Let ME Ɣ denote the set of maxi equilibria of the mechanism Ɣ Definition 11 Let x be an allocation of an ambiguous asymmetric information economy E, and ME Ɣ the set of maxi equilibria of the mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, gi } i I, v i } i I Wesaythe allocation x is implementable as a maxi equilibrium of the mechanism Ɣ if, s ME Ɣ, such that g i x e, s ω,ω = x i ω, for each ω and for each i I Definition 12 A strategy profile s is truth telling, if for each i, s i = for each F i We denote such a strategy profile by s T Remark 2 Clearly, if the mechanism Ɣ has a truth telling maxi equilibrium, ie, s T ME Ɣ, then the allocation x is implementable as a maxi equilibrium of Ɣ Indeed, for each state ω, s T ω = E F 1 ω,,e F N ω It follows that g i x e, s T ω,ω = g i x e, E F 1 ω,,e F N ω = e i ω + D i x e, = e i ω + x i ω e i ω = x i ω,,ω E F 1 ω,,e F N ω for each ω and for each i I, which is the requirement of Definition 11 Remark 3 The implementation results depend on the payoff rules of the direct revelation mechanism In a type model, the players reports are always compatible de 9 The robust control approach presumes that decision makers are able to specify the set of possible models, but are either unable or unwilling to form a prior over the forms of model misspecification 10 Aryal and Stauber 2014 introduced the notions of ɛ-perfect max equilibrium, perfect max equilibrium and robust sequential equilibrium Their notions allow players to make small mistakes which is not the case with our notion of maxi equilibrium

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 243 Castro et al 2015 implements each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation of an l-goods economy In this paper, the players reports may not be compatible We include the players net transfers redistribution when their reports are not compatible Interestingly, if these net transfers punishments are too gentle or too crude, then a lie can be profitable The punishments of this paper are just right to induce truth telling In a single good economy, if the planned redistribution for ω is larger than the planned redistribution for ˆω, then a player likes the former more regardless of the realized state, since his utility function is strictly monotone in consumption It follows that if a player can strictly benefit from lying, then it is possible to Pareto improve the planned allocation by reducing the variation of the planned redistribution across states This contradicts with the efficiency of the planned allocation That is, if the planned allocation is efficient, then it is not possible to benefit from lying However, in an l>1 goods economy, the argument for the single good economy does not work In particular, when a player can benefit from lying, it may not be possible to alter the planned redistribution to achieve a Pareto improvement Indeed, now a player may like good 1 more than good 2 at state ω, and like good 2 more than good 1 at state ω That is, it is possible to benefit from lying, even when the planned allocation is efficient It follows that we need additional conditions to implement each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation 5 Implementation in a single good economy 51 Implementation We show that each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation x in a single good economy is implementable through its corresponding mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I Let x e denote a planned redistribution, and E F 1,,E F N a list of reports Definition 13 The actual redistribution of player i is given by D i x e, E F 1,,E F x i ω e i ω if j I E F j = ω} N = ω xi ω e i ω } if j I E F j = That is, when reports are not compatible, the mechanism designer MD appropriates ω x i e i } from each player i Theorem 1 Denote by x a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation of a single good economy and ME Ɣ the set of maxi equilibria of the direct revelation mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I Then, there exists a truth telling maxi equilibrium s T, which is the unique maxi equilibrium of the mechanism Ɣ ie, s T } = MEƔ, for which we have g i x e, s T ω,ω = x i ω, for each ω and for each i I, ie, the allocation x is implementable as a maxi equilibrium of its corresponding mechanism Ɣ

244 L I de Castro et al Remark 4 Since maxi core allocations, maxi value allocations and maxi Walrasian expectations equilibrium allocations are maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient in a partition model, it follows that they are implementable as a maxi equilibrium Remark 5 We differ from the full implementation of Jackson 1991, Palfrey and Srivastava 1987, Palfrey and Srivastava 1989 and Hahn and Yannelis 2001 in that, our players are Wald-type maxi not Bayesian Furthermore, we do not implement all equilibrium allocations Instead, we pick an allocation and fully implement the allocation with a mechanism, alabergemann and Morris 2009 de Castro et al 2015 showed that the maxi implementation of this paper and the robust implementation of Bergemann and Morris 2009 are different For further discussion on the relationship between robust implementation and maxi implementation in a general setting, we refer readers to Guo and Yannelis 2015 52 Heuristic proof Now we provide a heuristic proof by means of an example A complete proof will be given in the next section Example 2 Recall Example 1 There are two agents, one commodity, and three possible states of nature = a, b, c} The ex post utility function of each agent i is u i c i ; ω = c i The agents random initial endowments, information partitions and multi-prior sets are: e 1 a, e 1 b, e 1 c = 5, 5, 1 ; F 1 = a, b}, c}} e 2 a, e 2 b, e 2 c = 5, 1, 5 ; F 2 = a, c}, b}} P 1 = probability measure π 1 : 2 [0, 1] π 1 a, b} = 2 3 and π 1 c}= 1 } 3 P 2 = probability measure π 2 : 2 [0, 1] π 2 a, c} = 2 3 and π 2 b}= 1 } 3 and A maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is x = x1 a x 1 b x 1 c = x 2 a x 2 b x 2 c 5 48 12 5 12 48 Let the planned allocation be x Then, the planned redistribution x e is x 1 a e 1 a, x 1 b e 1 b, x 1 c e 1 c = 0, 02, 02 x 2 a e 2 a, x 2 b e 2 b, x 2 c e 2 c = 0, 02, 02

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 245 Fig 2 An informal game tree Fig 3 At player 1 s information sets The game tree is presented in Fig 2, in which for simplicity, we let A 1 = a, b}, c 1 = c}, A 2 = a, c}, and b 2 = b} We will show that the truth telling strategy profile constitutes the only maxi equilibrium of the game, and the immediate consequence is that the allocation x is implemented Formally, we will show that the strategy profile s = s 1 A 1 = A 1, s 1 c 1 = c 1 ; s 2 A 2 = A 2, s 2 b 2 = b 2, constitutes the only maxi equilibrium of the game We look at player 1 first, and she has two information sets I 1 and I 1 Fig 3 If she is at I 1, then she must have seen the event A 1 from nature She can either tell the truth A 1 or the lie c 1 Player 1 cannot distinguish the two decision nodes within the set I 1, so her action is common at the two nodes Figure 3a shows that, being truthful reports A 1, she may end up with, from the left to the right, 5, 48, 5 or 48 units of the good That is, at the information set I 1, if player 1 tells the truth, then she may go down one of the four paths aa 1 A 2, aa 1 b 2, ba 1 A 2 and ba 1 b 2, for which she ends up with g 1 x e, A 1, A 2, a = e 1 a + x 1 a

246 L I de Castro et al e 1 a = 5 + 0 = 5, g 1 x e, A 1, b 2, a = e 1 a + x 1 b e 1 b = 5 02 = 48, g 1 x e, A 1, A 2, b = e 1 b + x 1 a e 1 a = 5 + 0 = 5, and g 1 x e, A 1, b 2, b = e 1 b + x 1 b e 1 b = 5 02 = 48 units of the good, respectively Similarly, by lying reports c 1, she may end up with, from the left to the right, 52, 48, 52 or 48 units of the good 11 Clearly, when player 1 observes the event A 1, telling the truth reports A 1 gives her a lower bound payoff of v 1 A 1, A 2 ; a,v 1 A 1, b 2 ; a,v 1 A 1, A 2 ; b,v 1 A 1, b 2 ; b} } = 5, 48, 5, 48 = 48; lying reports c 1 gives her a lower bound payoff of v 1 c 1, A 2 ; a,v 1 c 1, b 2 ; a,v 1 c 1, A 2 ; b,v 1 c 1, b 2 ; b} } = 52, 48, 52, 48 = 48 So when she observes the event A 1, she has no incentive to lie, ie, s 1 A 1 = A 1 constitutes part of a maxi equilibrium of the game If player 1 is at I 1, then she must have seen the event c 1 from nature Figure 3b shows that telling the truth reports c 1 gives her a lower bound payoff of 12, } v 1 c 1, A 2 ; c,v 1 c 1, b 2 ; c} = 08 = 08; lying reports A 1 gives her a lower bound payoff of v 1 A 1, A 2 ; c,v 1 A 1, b 2 ; c} = 1, } 08 = 08 So when she observes the event c 1, she has no incentive to lie, ie, s 1 c 1 = c 1 constitutes part of a maxi equilibrium of the game Now, turn to player 2 He has two information sets also, I 2 and I 2 Fig 4 If player 2 is at I 2, then he must have seen the event A 2 from nature Figure 4a shows that, being truthful reports A 2, he may end up with, from the left to the right, 5, 48, 5 or 48 units of the good; and by lying reports b 2, he may end up with, from the left to the right, 52, 48, 52 or 48 units of the good Clearly, telling the truth reports A 2 gives him a lower bound payoff of v 2 A 1, A 2 ; a,v 2 c 1, A 2 ; a,v 2 A 1, A 2 ; c,v 2 c 1, A 2 ; c} } = 5, 48, 5, 48 = 48; lying reports b 2 gives him a lower bound payoff of v 2 A 1, b 2 ; a,v 2 c 1, b 2 ; a,v 2 A 1, b 2 ; c,v 2 c 1, b 2 ; c} } = 52, 48, 52, 48 = 48 So when he observes the event A 2, he has no incentive to lie, ie, s 2 A 2 = A 2 constitutes part of a maxi equilibrium of the game 11 Notice that both path ac 1 b 2 and path bc 1 b 2 lead to incompatible reports Therefore, the actual redistribution of player 1 is ω x1 ω e 1 ω } = 02

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 247 Fig 4 At player 2 s information sets If player 2 is at I 2, then he must have seen the event b 2 from nature Figure 4b shows that telling the truth reports b 2 gives him a lower bound payoff of v 2 A 1, b 2 ; b,v 2 c 1, b 2 ; b} = 08 = 08; lying 12, } reports A 2 gives him a lower bound payoff of v 2 A 1, A 2 ; b,v 2 c 1, A 2 ; b} = 1, } 08 = 08 So when he observes the event b 2, he has no incentive to lie, ie, s 2 b 2 = b 2 constitutes part of a maxi equilibrium of the game Now, put together, the strategy profile s = s 1 A 1 = A 1, s 1 c 1 = c 1 ; s 2 A 2 = A 2, s 2 b 2 = b 2 is a maxi equilibrium of the game It is, in fact, the only maxi equilibrium of the game 12 The equilibrium report paths are s a = s 1 A 1, s 2 A 2 = A 1, A 2, s b = s 1 A 1, s 2 b 2 = A 1, b 2 and s c = s 1 c 1, s 2 A 2 = c 1, A 2,asmarkedinFig2 It can be easily checked that the maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation x is implemented, since we have g 1 x e, s a, a = g 1 x e, A 1, A 2, a = 5 + 5 5 = 5 = x 1 a, and similarly, we have g 2 x e, s a, a = 5 = x 2 a, g 1 x e, s b, b = 48 = x 1 b, g 2 x e, s b, b = 12 = x 2 b, g 1 x e, s c, c = 12 = x 1 c, g 2 x e, s c, c = 48 = x 2 c These outcomes are illustrated in Fig 2, as pairs following the equilibrium paths 12 We assume that a player lies, only if he can benefit from doing so

248 L I de Castro et al 53 Proof of theorem 1 To ease the explanation, we introduce some notations We use F i = j =i F j to denote the action set of all the players except player i, and E F i = E F 1,, 1, +1,,E F N F i reports of all the players expect player i Furthermore, we write ω E F i or E F i ω, if the state ω belongs to each element in the list E F 1,, 1, +1,,E F N ; and we use E F i E F i = j I EF j to denote the information revealed by the reports of all the players Let x be a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation Suppose that the mechanism Ɣ does not have a truth telling maxi equilibrium Then, there must exist a player i, an event and a lie Ẽ F i F i clearly, Ẽ F i =, such that when the player i observes the event, he can ensure a better lower bound payoff by lying, ie, v i, E F i ; ω } < v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω } 5 E F i F i ; E F i F i ; We will show, in Steps 1 and 2, that 5 cannot hold, and therefore every game Ɣ has a truth telling maxi equilibrium To ease the explanation, denote the left-hand side of 5by v i, E i ; ω = E F i F i ; v i, E F i ; ω }, where E i F i and ω solve the imization problem above Step 1 We will show that if E i = ω} for some ω, and 5 holds, then x fails to be an ex ante maxi efficient allocation Clearly, ω, and we have v i, E i ; ω = u i ei ω + x i ω e i ω ; ω = u i xi ω ; ω = u i x i ω ; ω, as the initial endowment e i and the utility function u i are F i -measurable Notice that v i, E i ; ω = u i x i ω ; ω implies 13 v i, E i ; ω = v i, E F i ω ; ω } 6 13 Notice that ω,and v i, E i ; ω = v i, E F i ; ω } v i, E F i ω ; ω } E F i F i ; imply that we must have equality throughout v i, E F i ω ; ω = u i x i ω ; ω,

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 249 Also, 5 implies 14 v i, E i ; ω < v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω } 7 Now, 6 and 7 together imply v i, E F i ω ; ω } < v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω } 8 Finally, Lemma 1 see below shows that if 8 holds, then x fails to be an ex ante maxi efficient allocation, which is a contradiction Step 2 We will show that if E i =, then 5 cannot hold which is a contradiction Now we have v i, E i ; ω = u i ei ω + x i ˆω ei ˆω ; ω, where ˆω imizes x i e i WeshowbyLemma2 that E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω } = u i ei ω + x i ˆω ei ˆω ; ω, for every Ẽ F i = It follows that E F i F i ; v i, E F i ; ω } = E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω } for every Ẽ F i = Thatis,5 does not hold Therefore, we conclude that the mechanism Ɣ has a truth telling maxi equilibrium, ie, s T ME Ɣ We now show that the truth telling maxi equilibrium is the only maxi equilibrium of the mechanism Ɣ, ie, s T } = ME Ɣ So suppose otherwise, that is, suppose that both s T and s are maxi equilibria of the mechanism Ɣ, and s T = s The truth telling strategy profile s T is different from the strategy profile s, which implies that there must exist a player i and an event, such that s T i = = Ẽ F i = si 9 However, si = Ẽ F i = holds, only if lying makes player i strictly better off upon observing the event, ie, 14 Since by the definition of a imum, we have that v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω } E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω }

250 L I de Castro et al E F i F i ; v i, E F i ; ω } < E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω }, which contradicts to the fact that the truth telling strategy profile constitutes a maxi equilibrium of the mechanism Clearly, the maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation x is implemented Indeed, under the truth telling strategy profile s T, the list of reports associated to each state ω is s T ω = E F 1 ω,,e F N ω That is, the players always tell the truth As a consequence, we have g i x e, s T ω,ω = g i x e, E F 1 ω,,e F N ω = e i ω + D i x e, = e i ω + x i ω e i ω = x i ω,,ω E F 1 ω,,e F N ω for each ω and for each i I the requirement of Definition 11 Lemma 1 Given a direct revelation mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I,if the allocation x is maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient, then there do not exist a player i, an event and a lie Ẽ F i F i clearly, Ẽ F i =, such that 15 v i, E F i ω ; ω } < v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω } 10 That is, for all i, given that all the other players tell the truth, it is optimal for player i to tell the truth 16 Proof Suppose that there exist a player i, an event and a lie Ẽ F i =, such that 10 holds We will show that the feasible allocation x fails to be ex ante efficient under the maxi preferences The idea is similar to the one in theorem 41 of de Castro and Yannelis 2009 Notice that for each ω,wehave v i, E F i ω ; ω = u i xi ω ; ω, and therefore, the left-hand side of 10 can be rewritten as v i, E F i ω ; ω } = ui xi ω ; ω } 15 In words, 10 says that if all the other players are truthful, then player i can ensure a higher lower bound payoff by lying under the event 16 In other words, truth telling for all i turns out to be a fixed point

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 251 Define an i-allocation of player i, z i, such that for each ω, v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω = u i zi ω ; ω, and therefore, the right-hand side of 10 can be rewritten as v i ẼF i, E F i ω ; ω } = ui zi ω ; ω } It follows from 10 that ui xi ω ; ω } < ui zi ω ; ω }, 11 which then implies that for each ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, we have u i xi ω ; ω < u i zi ω ; ω 12 For 12 to hold, it must be the case that for each ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, there exists a state ω, such that 1 Ẽ F i E F i ω = ω}, 2 z i ω = e i ω + x i ω e i ω = x i ω Let ω, ω } denote a set, containing a state ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω } and its corresponding 17 ω It follows by 1 above that, for each ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, the set ω, ω } is a subset of E F i ω Now, we are ready to define an allocation y that Pareto improves x under the maxi preferences Define for each j I,the j-allocation y j by y j ω = z j ω = e j ω + x j ω e j ω x j ω if ω arg ω otherwise u i x i ω ; ω } Notice that the allocation y is feasible 17 To avoid confusion, it is worthwhile to re-emphasize that different ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω } may be matched with a different ω

252 L I de Castro et al Indeed, for a state ω / arg ω u i x i ω ; ω },wehave y j ω = x j ω = e j ω ; j I j I j I and for a state ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω },wehave y j ω = z j ω = e j ω + x j ω e j ω = e j ω j I j I j I j I j I j I recall that x is a feasible allocation at the state ω From 12 and the definition of y i,wehave ui yi ω ; ω } > ui xi ω ; ω } 13 under the event ; and for any other event Ê F i F i,wehave ω Ê F i ui yi ω ; ω } = ω Ê F i ui xi ω ; ω } Therefore, combined with the assumption on μ i Assumption 2, we conclude that, for the player i, E F i u i yi ω ; ω μ i E i > ω E i u i xi ω ; ω μ i E i ω E i E i F i 14 Here we abuse the notations in 14 slightly, in particular, E i denotes an arbitrary event in F i That is, player i strictly prefers the i-allocation y i to the i-allocation x i under the maxi preferences Now, it remains to show that for any other player k = i,we have y k is preferred to x k under the maxi preferences Fix an arbitrary player k = i, and an arbitrary event that player k may observe, E F k F k Notice that if the event E F k contains a state ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, then it contains the set ω, ω } So, by the F k -measurability of e k, we have z k ω = e k ω + x k ω e k ω = x k ω Now, for the event E F k, define X k = x k ω : ω E F } k and Y k = y k ω : ω E F } k WehaveY k X k Indeed, if ω E F k and ω arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, then y k ω = z k ω = x k ω X k ;

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 253 and if ω E F k and ω / arg ω u i x i ω ; ω }, then y k ω = x k ω X k Therefore, with Assumption 4, we have that ω E F k uk yk ω ; ω } ω E F k uk xk ω ; ω } Since the event E F k F k is arbitrary, we conclude that E F k F k E F k F k u k yk ω ; ω μ k E F k ω E F k u k xk ω ; ω μ k E F k ω E F k Also, since player k = i is arbitrary, we have for every player k = i, y k is preferred to x k under the maxi preferences Thus, the feasible allocation y Pareto improves the allocation x under the maxi preferences, ie, x fails to be an ex ante maxi efficient allocation This contradiction completes the proof of Lemma 1 Lemma 2 Let v i, E i ; ω = v i, E F i ; ω } E F i F i ; If E i =, then E F i F i ; for each Ẽ F i F i v i, E F i ; ω } = E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω }, 15 Proof By construction, a player anticipates the worst net transfer in the case of incompatible reports Since E i =,itfollowsthatv i, E i ; ω = u i ei ω + x i ˆω ei ˆω ; ω, where ˆω arg ω x i e i } Clearly, given a Ẽ F i F i and Ẽ F i =, if there exists a Ẽ F i F i such that Ẽ F i Ẽ F i =, then by Assumptions 3 and 4, wehave E F i F i ; v i ẼF i, E F i ; ω } = u i ei ω + x i ˆω ei ˆω ; ω

254 L I de Castro et al That is, 15 holds in this case Now, suppose that there exists Ẽ F i = such that Ẽ F i is compatible with all E F i F i We will show that arg ω x i e i } Ẽ F i is nonempty Then, since any state in Ẽ F i can be an agreed state, player i can end up with the same net transfer as when the reports are not compatible That is, 15 holds Assume otherwise, ie, assume that arg ω x i e i } Ẽ F i = Itfollows that arg ω x i e i } = Now define an allocation y For each ω arg ω x i e i },lety ω = e ω + x ω e ω, where ω} = E F i ω Ẽ F i Notice, ω is well defined, since by construction Ẽ F i is compatible with all E F i F i Also notice that, for each ω arg ω x i e i }, we have u i ei ω + x i ω e i ω ; ω < u i ei ω + x i ω e i ω ; ω for each ω, since ω Ẽ F i ie, ω / arg ω x i e i }, and u i is strictly monotone Now, for each ω / arg ω x i e i },lety ω = x ω Clearly, the allocation y is feasible Also, y Pareto improves x under the maxi preferences Indeed, at each ω arg ω x i e i },wehave u i yi ω ; ω > u i xi ω ; ω ω ω ω ω At each ω with ω arg ω x i e i } =,wehave u i yi ω ; ω = u i xi ω ; ω ω ω ω ω Combined with Assumption 2, y i gives player i a strictly higher ex ante maxi payoff, ie, player i strictly prefers y i to x i at ex ante under the maxi preferences Let j be an arbitrary player different from i By construction, for each ω arg ω x i e i }, its corresponding ω is in the set E F i ω That is, player j cannot distinguish ω and its corresponding ω By the same argument as in Lemma 1, at each ω arg ω x i e i },wehave u j y j ω ; ω u j x j ω ; ω ω E F j ω ω E F j ω At each ω with E F j ω arg ω x i e i } =,wehave u j y j ω ; ω = u j x j ω ; ω ω E F j ω ω E F j ω Combined with Assumption 2, player j prefers y j to x j at ex ante under the maxi preferences Therefore, the allocation x is not ex ante maxi efficient This contradiction completes the proof of Lemma 2

Ambiguous implementation: the partition model 255 6 Implementation in an economy with more than one good In an economy with more than one good, the actual redistribution Definition 13 of Sect 5 is not well defined We need a new payout rule Let x e denote a planned redistribution and E F 1,,E F N a list of reports Definition 14 The actual redistribution of player i is given by x i ω e i ω if j I E D i x F j = ω} e, E F 1,,E F N = x i ˆω ei ˆω for some ˆω, if j I E F j = Now, whenever the players reports are not compatible, the mechanism designer MD carries out a net transfers x ˆω e ˆω The ˆω is unknown to the players, when they report events Being maxi, the players anticipate the worst That is, for each i and ω, player i anticipates the payoff 18 u ω i ei ω + x i ω e i ω ; ω 16 in the case of incompatible reports Clearly, depending on the event player i observes, he may associate different worst case scenario in the case of incompatible reports As the proof of our implementation result will indicate, the condition 16 works as a threat which induces players not to deviate from reporting the true events 61 Implementation We show that each maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation is implementable as a maxi equilibrium, as long as one of the following three conditions holds Condition 1 The economy satisfies Assumption 5 This is the case studied by de Castro et al 2015 Condition 2 If incompatible reports can occur when a player tells the truth, then incompatible reports can occur when he tells a lie Formally, let ω be the realized state of nature If there exists E F i F i, such that ω E F i =, then for every Ẽ F i = ω, there exists Ẽ F i F i, such that Ẽ F i Ẽ F i = Condition 3 Allocation x is a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation For each i, the set M i is not empty, where M i = ω m : u i ei ω + x i ω m e i ω m,ω u i e i ω + x i ω e i ω,ω for all ω, ω } 18 Recall that both the initial endowment and the utility function are F i -measurable

256 L I de Castro et al Condition 3 ensures that each player has a least preferred planned redistribution Remark 6 In the single good case, Condition 3 is automatically satisfied Indeed, for each i, thesetm i = arg ω x i e i } which is not empty It follows that the implementation results of the single good case requires no additional condition Theorem 2 Denote by x a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation in an economy with more than one good Its corresponding direct revelation mechanism Ɣ = I, S, x e, g i } i I, v i } i I has a truth telling maxi equilibrium s T, which is the unique maxi equilibrium of the mechanism Ɣ, if one of the three conditions Conditions 1, 2 and 3 holds Proof Condition 1 rules out the case of Step 2 which is in the proof of Theorem 1 Therefore, the result follows from Step 1 and Lemma 1 See also de Castro et al 2015 If an economy satisfies condition 2, the result follows from the proof of Theorem 1 and Lemma 1 The case in Step 2 ie, E i = of the proof of Theorem 1 can occur, but condition 2 guarantees that in this case no lie can give the player a strictly higher maxi payoff Finally, if an economy satisfies condition 3, then we can replace the state ˆω in the Step 2 of the proof of Theorem 1 with an ω m M i, and replace the set arg ω x i e i } in Lemma 2 with the set M i Now, the implementation result follows from the proof of Theorem 1, Lemma 1 and Lemma 2 62 Counterexamples Example 3 below shows that if all three conditions of Theorem 2 fail, then a maxi individually rational and ex ante maxi efficient allocation may not be implementable in Ɣ Example 3 There are two agents, I = 1, 2}, two goods, and six states of nature = a, b, c, d, e, f } The ex post utility function of agent 1 is u 1 x1,1 ω, x 1,2 ω ; ω = x 1,1 ω + x 1,2 ω, ω a, b, c, d, e}, and u 1 x1,1 f, x 1,2 f ; f = 05 x 1,1 f + 2 x 1,2 f, where the second index refers to the good The ex post utility function of agent 2 is u 2 x2,1 ω, x 2,2 ω ; ω = x 2,1 ω + x 2,2 ω, ω a, c, e, f }, and u 2 x2,1 ω, x 2,2 ω ; ω = 101 x 2,1 ω + x 2,2 ω, ω b, d} The agents random initial endowments, information partitions and multi-prior sets are: e 1 ω = 10, 10 for all ω; e 2 ω = 10, 10 for ω a, b, c, d}; and e 2 ω = 11, 9 for ω e, f } F 1 = a, b}, c, d, e}, f }} ; F 2 = a, c}, b, d}, e, f }} P 1 = probability measure π 1 : 2 [0, 1] π 1 a, b} = π 1 c, d, e} = π 1 f } = 1 } 3 P 2 = probability measure π 2 : 2 [0, 1] π 2 a, c} = π 2 b, d} = π 2 e, f } = 1 } 3