ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N

Similar documents
Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

TIE-POINTS, REGULAR CLOSED SETS, AND COPIES OF N

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

ON THE COFINALITY OF THE SPLITTING NUMBER

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

CARDINAL RESTRICTIONS ON SOME HOMOGENEOUS COMPACTA. István Juhász*, Peter Nyikos**, and Zoltán Szentmiklóssy*

ON VAN DOUWEN SPACES AND RETRACTS OF βn

Distributivity of the algebra of regular open subsets of βr \ R

COMPACT SPACES WITH HEREDITARILY NORMAL SQUARES

PFA(S)[S] and the Arhangel skiĭ-tall Problem

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

EFIMOV S PROBLEM AND BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

HEREDITARILY NORMAL MANIFOLDS OF DIMENSION > 1 MAY ALL BE METRIZABLE

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

INSTITUTE of MATHEMATICS. ACADEMY of SCIENCES of the CZECH REPUBLIC. The Katowice problem and autohomeomorphisms of ω 0

TWO TO ONE IMAGES AND PFA

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

APPLICATIONS OF ANOTHER CHARACTERIZATION OF βn \ N

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Embeddings into P(N)/fin and extension of automorphisms

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

P-FILTERS AND COHEN, RANDOM, AND LAVER FORCING

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

Reversible spaces STDC, Baylor University. Rodrigo Hernández-Gutiérrez Nipissing University Joint work with Alan Dow

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

ALAN DOW AND ILIJAS FARAH

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

TUKEY QUOTIENTS, PRE-IDEALS, AND NEIGHBORHOOD FILTERS WITH CALIBRE (OMEGA 1, OMEGA) by Jeremiah Morgan BS, York College of Pennsylvania, 2010

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

INCREASING THE GROUPWISE DENSITY NUMBER BY C.C.C. FORCING HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH

PFA and complemented subspaces of l /c 0

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

with the topology generated by all boxes that are determined by countably many coordinates. Then G is a topological group,

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

TOPOLOGIES GENERATED BY CLOSED INTERVALS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 1, 2005,

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos

PFA(S)[S] and countably compact spaces

THE NON-URYSOHN NUMBER OF A TOPOLOGICAL SPACE

Topological Problems for Set Theorists, II

A FIVE ELEMENT BASIS FOR THE UNCOUNTABLE LINEAR ORDERS

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

Souslin s Hypothesis


THE FOURTH HEAD OF βn

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS. Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

Irredundant Generators

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

An introduction to OCA

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Axioms of separation

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

Topological homogeneity and infinite powers

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

Spectra of Tukey types of ultrafilters on Boolean algebras

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp.

Homeomorphism groups of Sierpiński carpets and Erdős space

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

1. Introduction. 2. Definitions and Notation

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

Almost disjoint families and topology

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

TWO MORE PERFECTLY NORMAL NON-METRIZABLE MANIFOLDS. Zoltan Balogh and Gary Gruenhage

arxiv: v3 [math.gn] 8 Aug 2016

Homogeneity and rigidity in Erdős spaces

by Harold R. Bennett, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX and David J. Lutzer, College of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI

A CHARACTERIZATION OF POWER HOMOGENEITY G. J. RIDDERBOS

Transcription:

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N ALAN DOW AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. A tie-point of a compact space is analogous to a cutpoint: the complement of the point falls apart into two relatively clopen non-compact subsets. Set-theoretically, a tie-point of N is an ultrafilter whose dual maximal ideal can be generated by the union of two non-principal mod finite orthogonal ideals. We review some of the many consistency results that have depended on the construction of tie-points of N. One especially important application, due to Velickovic, was to the existence of non-trivial involutions on N. A tie-point of N has been called symmetric if it is the unique fixed point of an involution. We define the notion of an almost clopen set to be the closure of one of the proper relatively clopen subsets of the complement of a tie-point. We explore asymmetries of almost clopen subsets of N in the sense of how may an almost clopen set differ from its natural complementary almost clopen set. 1. Introduction In this introductory section we review some background to motivate our interest in further study of tie-points and almost clopen sets. The Stone-Čech compactification of the integers N, is denoted as βn and, as a set, is equal to N together with all the free ultrafilters on N. The remainder N = βn \ N can be topologized as a subspace of the Stone space of the power set of N as a Boolean algebra and, in particular, for a subset a of N, the set a of all free ultrafilters with a as an element, is a basic clopen subset of N. Set-theoretically it is sometimes more convenient to work with the set of ordinals ω in place of the natural numbers N, and the definitions of ω and a for a ω are analogous. Date: June 1, 2017. 1991 Mathematics Subject Classification. 54D80, 03E15. Key words and phrases. ultrafilters, cardinal invariants of continuum. The research of the first author was supported by the NSF grant No. NSF-DMS 1501506. The research of the second author was supported by the United States- Israel Binational Science Foundation (BSF Grant no. 2010405), and by the NSF grants No. NSF-DMS 1101597 and 136974. 1

2 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH A point x of a space X is a butterfly point (or b-point [23]) if there are sets D, E X \ {x} such that {x} = D E. In [5], the authors introduced the tie-point terminology. Definition 1.1. A point x is a tie-point of a space X if there are closed sets A, B of X such that X = A B, {x} = A B and x is a limit point of each of A and B. We picture (and denote) this as X = A x B where A, B are the closed sets which have a unique common accumulation point x and say that x is a tie-point as witnessed by A, B. In this note the focus is on the local properties of x with respect to each of the closed sets A and B such that A x B in the case when A, B witness that x is a tie-point. For this reason we introduce the notion of an almost clopen subset of N. Definition 1.2. A set A N is almost clopen if A is the closure of an open subset of N and has a unique boundary point, which we denote x A. Proposition 1.3. If A is an almost clopen subset of N, then B = {x A } (N \ A) is almost clopen and x B = x A. In addition x A is a tie-point as witnessed by A, B. Definition 1.4. [5] A tie-point x is a symmetric tie-point of N if there is a pair A, B witnessing that x is a tie-point and if there is a homeomorphism h : A B satisfying that h(x) = x. If A is almost clopen, then we refer to B = {x A } (N \ A) as the almost clopen complement of A. A more set-theoretically inclined reader would surely prefer a staightforward translation of almost clopen to properties of ideals of subsets of N and the usual mod finite ordering. Definition 1.5. If A is any subset of N, then I A is defined as the set {a N : a A}. For any family A of subsets of N (or ω), we define A to be the orthogonal ideal {b N : ( a A) b a = }. Let us note that if I is an ideal that has no -maximal element, then the ideal generated by I I is a proper ideal. Lemma 1.6. If A is an almost clopen subset of N with almost clopen complement B, then I A I B is the Frechet ideal [N] <ℵ 0, I B = I A, and x A is the unique ultrafilter that is disjoint from I A I B.

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 3 Almost clopen sets (and tie-points) first arose implicitly in the work of Fine and Gillman [11] in the investigation of extending continuous functions on dense subsets of N. A subset Y of a space X is C - embedded if every bounded continuous real-valued function on Y can be continuously extended to all of X. The character of a point x N is the minimal cardinality of a filter base for x as an ultrafilter on N. Proposition 1.7. ([11]) If x is a tie-point of N, then N \ {x} is not C -embedded in N. Every point of character ℵ 1 is a tie-point of N. It was shown [4] to be consistent with ZFC that N \ {x} is C - embedded for all x N. It was also shown by Baumgartner [1] that their result holds in models of the Proper Forcing Axiom (PFA). Proposition 1.8. ([1, 4]) The proper forcing axiom implies N \ {x} is C -embedded in N for all x N Corollary 1.9. PFA implies that there are no almost clopen sets and no tie-points in N. Almost clopen sets arise in the study of minimal extensions of Boolean algebras ([16]) and in the application of this method of construction for building a variety of counterexamples (e.g. [7, 13, 17, 22]). The next application of almost clopen subsets of N were to the study of non-trivial automorphisms of P(N)/f in, or non-trivial autohomeomorphisms of N. Katětov [15] proved that the set of fixed points of an autohomeomorphism of βn will be a clopen set. It is immediate from Fine and Gillman s work in [11] that every P -point of character of ℵ 1 is a fixed point of a non-trivial autohomeomorphism of N. Definition 1.10. A point x of N is a P -point if the ultrafilter x is countably complete mod finite. For a cardinal κ, an ultrafilter x on N is a simple P κ -point if x has a base well-ordered by mod finite inclusion of order type κ. Proposition 1.11. [11] If A is an almost clopen subset of N and x A is a simple P ℵ1 -point of N, then (1) A is homeomorphic to N, (2) x A is a symmetric tie-point, (3) there is an autohomeomorphism f on N such that {x} is the only fixed point of f. As we have seen above, PFA implies that there are no almost clopen subsets of N, and of course, PFA also implies that all autohomeomorphisms of N are trivial [24]. However Velickovic utilized the simple P -point trick (motivating our definition of symmetric tie-point) in order to prove that this is not a consequence of Martin s Axiom (MA).

4 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH Proposition 1.12. [27] It is consistent with MA and c = ℵ 2 that there is an almost clopen set A of N such that x A is a simple P ℵ2 -point and, (1) x A is a symmetric tie-point, (2) there is an autohomeomorphism f on N such that {x} is the only fixed point of f. Velickovic s result and approach was further generalized in [25, 26]. It is very interesting to know if an almost clopen subset of N is itself homeomorphic to N ([9, 14]). This question also arose in the authors work on two-to-one images of N [6]. Velickovic s method was slightly modified in [6] to produce a complementary pair of almost clopen sets so that neither is homeomorphic to N, but it is not known if there is a symmetric tie-point A x B where A is not a copy of N. Our final mention of recent interest in almost clopen subsets of N is in connection to the question [8, 19] of whether the Banach space l /c 0 is necessarily primary. It was noted by Koszmider [20, p577] that a special almost clopen subset of N could possibly resolve the problem. For a compact space K, we let C(K) denote the Banach space of continuous real-valued functions on K with the supremum norm. It is well-known that C(N ) is isomorphic (as a Banach space) to l /c 0. Naturally if a space A is homeomorphic to N, then C(A) is isomorphic to C(N ). Proposition 1.13. [20, p577] Suppose that A is an almost clopen subset of N and that B is its almost clopen complement. If C(N ) is not homeomorphic to either of C(A) or C(B), then l /c 0 is not primary. 2. Asymmetric tie-points In many of the applications mentioned in the introductory section, the tie-points utilized were symmetric tie-points. In other applications, for example the primariness of l /c 0, it may be useful to find examples where the witnessing sets A, B for a tie-point are quite different. There are any number of local topological properties that x A may enjoy as a point in A that it may not share as a point in B. We make the following definition in connection with simple P κ -points. Definition 2.1. Let κ be a regular cardinal. An almost clopen set A is simple of type κ if I A has a -cofinal -increasing chain {a α : α κ} of type κ. If {a α : α κ} is strictly -increasing and -cofinal in I A for an almost clopen set A, then the family {a α+1 \ a α : α κ} can not be reaped. A family A [N] ℵ 0 is reaped by a set c N if a\c = a c for

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 5 all a A. The reaping number r is the minimum cardinal of a family that can not be reaped [12]. For any infinite set a N, let next(a, ) be the function in N N defined by next(a, k) = min(a \ {1,..., k}). As usual, for f, g N N, we say that f < g if {k : g(k) f(k)} is finite. Proposition 2.2. [12] If A [N] ℵ 0 and if there is some g N N such that next(a, ) < g for all a A, then A can be reaped. In particular, b r. Again, if {a α : α κ} is strictly -increasing and -cofinal in I A for an almost clopen set A, then the family {a α+1 \ a α : α κ} is an example of a converging family of infinite sets. Definition 2.3. Let A be a family of infinite subsets of N. We say that A converges if there is an ultrafilter x on N such that for each U x, the set {a A : a \ U } has cardinality less than that of A. We say that A is hereditarily unreapable if each reapable subfamily of A has cardinality less than that of A. An ultrafilter x of N is said to be an almost P κ -point if each set of fewer than κ many members of x has a pseudointersection (an infinite set mod finite contained in each of them). Certainly a converging family is hereditarily unreapable and converges to a point that is an almost P κ -point where κ is the cardinality of the family. Clearly the cardinality of any hereditarily unreapable family will have cofinality less than the splitting number s. First we recall that a family A [N] ℵ 0 is a splitting family if for all infinite b N, there is an a A such that b a = b \ a. We say that b is split by a. The splitting number, s, is the least cardinality of a splitting family and s d ([12]). Therefore if, for example, s = ℵ 1 and r = c = ℵ 2, there will be no hereditarily unreapable family. If s = c, then there is a hereditarily unreapable family of cardinality s. In the Mathias model, of s = c = b = ℵ 2, there is no converging unreapable family because there is no almost P ℵ2 -point. In the Goldstern-Shelah model [12] of r = s = ℵ 1 < u, there is (easily checked) no converging family of cardinality r. It might be interesting to determine if there is a hereditarily unreapable family in this model because that would imply there was a stronger preservation result for the posets used. If there is a simple almost clopen set of type κ, are there restrictions on the behavior of its almost clopen complement and can there be simple almost clopen sets of different types (including the complement)? These are the types of questions that stimulated this study. The most compelling of these has been answered.

6 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH Theorem 2.4. If A is a simple almost clopen set of type κ and if the complementary almost clopen set B is simple, then it also has type κ. Similarly, there is a restriction on what the type of a simple almost clopen set can be that is shared by simple P κ -points (as shown by Nyikos (unpublished) see [2]). Theorem 2.5. If A is a simple almost clopen set of type κ, then κ is one of {b, d}. Now that we understand the limits on the behavior of a complementary pair of simple almost clopen sets, we look to the properties of the complement B when it is not assumed to be simple. The topological properties of character and tightness of x B in B are natural cardinal invariants to examine. These correspond to natural properties of I B as well. An indexed subset {y β : β < λ} of a space X is said to be a free sequence if the closure of each initial segment is disjoint from the closure of its complementary final segment. A λ-sequence {y β : β < λ} is converging if there is a point y such that every neighborhood of y contains a final segment of {y β : β < λ}. A subset D of N is said to be strongly discrete [10, 21] if there is a family of pairwise disjoint clopen subsets of N each containing a single point of D. Theorem 2.6. If κ < λ are uncountable regular cardinals with c λ, then there is a ccc forcing extension in which there is a simple almost clopen set A of type κ such that the almost clopen complement B contains a free λ-sequence {y β : β < λ} that converges to x A. We prove these theorems in the next section. We finish this section by formulating some open problems about almost clopen sets and possible asymmetries. Question 2.1. Can there exist simple almost clopen sets of different types? Question 2.2. If there is a simple almost clopen set of type κ is there a point of N of character κ? Is there a simple P κ -point? The next question is simply a special case of the previous. Question 2.3. Is a simple almost clopen set of type ℵ 1 necessarily homeomorphic to N? Question 2.4. If A is a simple almost clopen set of type κ, is there a simple almost clopen set B contained in the almost clopen complement B of A such that x A B? Is there a family of κ-many members of I B that converges to x A? Let us note that Theorem 3.6 is pertinent to this question.

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 7 3. Proofs Our analysis of simple almost clopen sets depends on the connection between the type of the clopen set and the ultrafilter ordering of functions from N to N. For an ultrafilter x on N the ordering < x is defined on N N by the condition that f < x g if {n N : f(n) < g(n)} x. Since x is an ultrafilter, a set F N N is cofinal in (N N, < x ) if it is not bounded. Of course a subset of N N that is unbounded with respect to the < x -ordering is also unbounded with respect to the mod finite ordering <. Fix a < -unbounded family {f ξ : ξ < b} N N such that each f ξ is strictly increasing and such that f η < f ξ for all η < ξ < b. The following well-known fact will be useful. Proposition 3.1. For each infinite b N and each unbounded Γ b, the family {f ξ b : ξ Γ} is < -unbounded in N b. Proof. For each η < b, there is a ξ Γ \ η such that f η < f ξ, hence {f ξ : ξ Γ} is < -unbounded. If g N b, then g next(b, ) N N. So there is a ξ Γ such that f ξ g next(b, ). Since f ξ is strictly increasing, f ξ b g. Lemma 3.2. If a family A [N] ℵ 0 converges to an ultrafilter x and if {f ξ : ξ b} is bounded mod < x, then A has cardinality b. Proof. Choose g N N so that f ξ < x g for all ξ < b. Since A can not be reaped, Proposition 2.2 implies that b A. For each ξ, let U ξ = {n N : f ξ (n) < g(n)} x. If b < A, then there is a b A such that b U ξ for all ξ < b (i.e. x is an almost P b +-point). However we would then have that f ξ b < g b for all ξ < b, and by Proposition 3.1, there is no such set b. This completes the proof. Lemma 3.3. If a family A [N] ℵ 0 converges to an ultrafilter x and if {f ξ : ξ b} is unbounded mod < x, then if A has regular cardinality, that cardinal is equal to d. Proof. Since we are assuming that {f ξ : ξ b} is < x -unbounded, it is actually < x -cofinal. We check that the family {f ξ next(a, ) : ξ < b, a A} is a < -dominating family. Take any strictly increasing g N N and choose ξ < b such that U = {n : g(n) < f ξ (n)} x. Since A converges to x, there is an a A such that a U. Since g is strictly increasing, it is clear that g < f ξ next(u, ) < f ξ next(a, ). Again, since A can not be reaped, we have b A and this implies that d A. Assume that {g β : β < d} N N is a < -dominating family. For each a A, there is a β a < d such that next(a, ) < g βa.

8 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH Now since A is hereditarily unreapable, Proposition 2.2 implies that if A has regular cardinality, the mapping a β a is < A -to-1. This implies that A d. Corollary 3.4. Suppose that A is a simple almost clopen subset of N of type κ. If {f ξ : ξ < b} is < xa -bounded, then κ = b; otherwise κ = d. Proof. Let {a α : α κ} be the family contained in I A witnessing that A has type κ. Set A equal to the family {a α+1 \ a α : α κ} which converges to x A. If {f ξ : ξ < b} is < xa -bounded, then by Lemma 3.2, κ = b. Otherwise, since κ is a regular cardinal, we have by Lemma 3.3, κ = d. Proof of Theorem 2.4. Assume that A and its complementary almost clopen set B are both simple and let x = x A. If {f ξ : ξ < b} is < x - bounded then, by Corollary 3.4 they both have type b; otherwise they both have type d. Proof of Theorem 2.5. Immediate from Corollary 3.4. We can improve Theorem 2.4. Proposition 3.5. There is no almost P s +-point in N. Proof. Let A be a splitting family of cardinality s. We may assume that A is closed under complements. Let x be any point of N. It is easily seen that any pseudointersection of x A is not split by any member of A. Since A is splitting, x A has no pseudointersection, and so x is not an almost P s +-point. Now we improve Theorem 2.4. Theorem 3.6. If A is a simple almost clopen set of type κ then x A is not an almost P κ +-point. Proof. We first note that by Proposition 3.5 we must have that κ < d. Therefore, by Lemma 3.3, {f ξ : ξ < b} is < xa -bounded. Choose any g N N so that f ξ < xa g for all ξ < b. For each ξ, let U ξ = {n N : f ξ (n) < g(n)}. By Proposition 3.1, we have that the collection {U ξ : ξ < b} x has no pseudointersection. By Theorem 2.4, b κ and this proves the theorem. Now we prove Theorem 2.6. We first prove the easier special case when κ = ℵ 1. An α-length finite support iteration sequence of posets, denoted ( P β : β α, Q β : β < α ), will mean that P β : β α is an increasing chain of posets, Q β is a P β -name of a poset for each β < α, and members p of P α will be functions with domain a finite

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 9 subset, supp(p), of α satisfying that p β P β forces that p(β) Q β for β supp(p). As usual, p 2 < p 1 providing p 2 β Pβ p 2 (β) < p 1 (β) for all β supp(p 1 ). Since P 0 is the trivial poset, we will allow ourselves to simply specify a poset Q 0 in such an iteration sequence rather than the P 0 -name of that poset. Definition 3.7. Let A = {a β : β < α} be a -increasing chain of subsets of ω, and let I be an ideal contained in A. We define the poset Q = Q(A; I) where q Q if q = (F q, σ q, b q ) where (1) F q [ω] <ℵ 0, (2) b q I is disjoint from b q, (3) σ q : H q ω and H q [α] <ℵ 0, (4) for each β H q, a β \ σ q (β) is disjoint from b q. For r, q Q we define r < q providing F r F q, σ r σ q, and b r b q. Lemma 3.8. If A = {a β : β < α} is a -increasing chain of subsets of ω and if I is an ideal contained in A, then Q(A; I) is ccc whenever cf(α) is not equal to ω 1. In addition, Q(A; [ω] <ω ) is ccc for any infinite -increasing chain A. Proof. The proofs are standard. The first statement is basically the same as Theorem 4.2 of [1]. For the last, Q(A; [ω] <ω ) is ccc since conditions p, q Q(A; [ω] <ω ) are compatible so long as F p = F q, b p = b q, and σ p σ q is a function. Definition 3.9. If Q is Q(A; I) for some -increasing chain of subsets of ω, and I A is an ideal, then the Q-generic set ȧ Q is defined as the natural name {( ˇF q, q) : q Q}, i.e. for each Q-generic filter G, val G (ȧ Q ) is equal to the union of the family {F q : q G}. Lemma 3.10. If λ is a regular cardinal with c λ, then there is a ccc forcing extension in which there is a simple almost clopen set A of type ω 1 such that there is a strongly discrete free λ-sequence converging to x A. Proof. There are ccc posets of cardinality λ that add a strictly - increasing sequence {b ζ : ζ < λ} of infinite subset of ω (e.g. [18, II Ex. 22]). Alternatively, by Definition 3.7 and Lemma 3.8, we could let Q 0 be a λ-length finite support sequence of posets of the form Q({b β : β < ζ}; [ω] <ω ) and recursively let b ζ be the resulting ȧ Q as in Definition 3.9. For convenience we now work in such a ccc forcing extension and we construct a finite support ccc iteration sequence of cardinality λ and length ω 1 that will add a strictly -increasing sequence {a α : α ω 1 } of infinite subsets of ω so that the closure, A, of {a α : α ω 1 } is

10 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH almost clopen. Suppose that we do this in such a way that {b ζ : ζ < λ} is contained in {a α : α ω 1 } and, for all U x A, and all ζ < λ, there is an η < λ such that U (b η \ b ζ ) is infinite. We check that there is then a strongly discrete free λ-sequence converging to x A. Let {U ζ : ζ < λ} enumerate the members of x A. There is a cub C λ satisfying that for each δ C, the family {U ξ : ξ < δ} is closed under finite intersections. Recursively define a strictly increasing function g from C into λ satisfying that U ζ (b g(δ) \b δ ) is infinite for all ζ < δ C. Now, for each δ C, let x δ be an ultrafilter extending the family {U ζ (b g(δ) \ b δ ) : ζ < δ}. Pass to a cub subset C 1 C satisfying that g(η) < δ for all δ C and η δ C. It follows immediately that {x δ : δ C 1 } is strongly discrete and free. Similarly, the sequence converges to x A since U ζ x δ for all ζ < δ C 1. Now we construct the iteration sequence to define the -increasing chain {a α : α ω 1 } that will be cofinal in I A. We will use iterands of the form Q α = Q({ȧ β : β < α}; İα) for 0 < α < ω 1, and will recursively let ȧ α be the standard P α+1 -name for a Q α (as in Definition 3.9). Clearly the only choices we have for the construction are the definition of a 0 and, by recursion, the definition of İ α. We will recursively ensure that Pα {ȧ β : β < α} {b ζ : ζ < λ} simply by ensuring that Pα {b ζ : ζ < λ} İα. To start the process, we let I 1 be any maximal ideal extending the ideal generated by {b ζ : ζ < λ} {b ζ : ζ < λ}. Very likely {b ζ : ζ < λ} is simply [ω] <ω, so we let a 0 be exceptional and equal the emptyset. We now have our definition (working in the extension by Q 0 ) of Q 1 = Q({a 0 }; I 1 ) and the generic set ȧ 1 = ȧ Q1 is forced to be almost disjoint from every member of I 1 (it is a pseudointersection of the ultrafilter dual to I 1 ). Now assume that α < ω 1 and that we have defined İβ for all β < α. We recursively also ensure that, for β < γ < α, the P β -name İβ+1 is a subset of the P γ -name İγ, and that P γ forces İγ is contained in {ȧ β : β < γ}. For the definition of İ α we break into three cases. If α is a limit ordinal, then we define İα to be the P α -name of the ideal {ȧ β : β < α}. By induction, we have, for γ < α, that Pα İγ+1 {ȧ β : β < α} = İα, as required. In the case that α = β + 1 for a successor β, we note that P β+1 forces that (by the genericity of ȧ β ) the family {ȧ β } İβ generates a proper ideal J α. In the case that β is a limit and α = β + 1, we note that P β+1 forces that the family {ȧ β } {İγ+1 : γ < β} also generates a proper ideal J α. Then, in either case where α = β + 1, we let J α be the P α -name of any maximal ideal that contains J α ( J α ). The

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 11 definition of İα is then the P α -name of J α {ȧ β }. For convenience, let ẏ β+1 denote the P β+1 -name of this ultrafilter, and let us notice that {ω \(ȧ β b) : b İβ+1} is forced to be a base for ẏ β+1. The set ȧ β+1 \ȧ β will be a pseudointersection of ẏ β+1. This completes the definition of the poset P ω1. Now we establish some properties. Let A denote P ω1 -name of the closure in ω of the open set {ȧ α : α ω 1 }. Claim 1. For each β < α < ω 1, P α+1 forces that ȧ α \ ȧ β is a pseudointersection of the filter ẏ β+1. Proof of Claim: We proceed by induction on α β +1. For α = β +1, ȧ α is almost disjoint from each member of İα, and so ȧ α \ ȧ β is almost disjoint from every member of J α. Thus ȧ α \ȧ β is forced to be mod finite contained in every member of the dual filter, namely ẏ β+1. Similarly, for α > β + 1, ȧ α is forced to be almost disjoint from each member of İ α. This means that ȧ α is almost disjoint from each member of İβ+1, and so ȧ α \ȧ β+1 is also almost disjoint from every member of J β+1. Claim 2. The family {ẏ β+1 : β < ω 1 } is a family of P ω1 -names and the union is forced to generate an ultrafilter ẋȧ that is indeed the unique boundary point of A. Proof of Claim: Since İβ+1 is contained in İα+1, and P ω1 forces that ȧ β ȧ γ, we have that P ω1 forces that {ẏ β+1 : β < ω 1 } is a filter. Furthermore, since P ω1 is ccc, every P ω1 -name of a subset of ω is equal to a P β -name for some β < ω 1. The fact that, for each β < ω 1, P β+1 forces that ẏ β+1 is an ultrafilter implies that P ω1 forces that ẋȧ is an ultrafilter. Finally, it follows immediately from the previous claim that ẋȧ is the unique boundary point of A. Claim 3. For each 0 < α < ω 1, P α+1 forces that {b ζ -unbounded in İα+1. : ζ < λ} is Proof of Claim: We prove this by induction on α. We know that P α+1 forces that ȧ α is almost disjoint from every member of {b ζ : ζ < λ}. Therefore, if P β+1 forces that {b ζ : ζ < λ} is -unbounded in İβ+1 for each β < α, it follows that {b ζ : ζ < λ} is -unbounded in what we called J α+1 above. In addition, we have that J α+1 {b ζ : ζ < λ}, so we have that P α+1 forces that {b ζ : ζ < λ} is -unbounded in İ α+1. To finish the proof of the Lemma, we have to verify that P ω1 forces that for all U ẋȧ, and all ζ < λ, there is an η < λ such that

12 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH U (b η \ b ζ ) is infinite. Let ζ < λ be given and suppose that U is a P α -name of a member of ẋȧ for some α < ω 1. Of course this means that ( U is a member of ẏ α+1. Now consider the P α+1 -name, ḃ, of the set b ζ ω \ ( U ) ȧ α+1 ). Evidently, ḃ is forced to be disjoint from ȧ α+1 and also is forced to not be in ẏ α+2. It follows that ḃ is an element of İ α+2. By Claim 3, there is an η and a condition p P α+2 such that p forces that b η \ḃ is infinite. Since b η \ḃ is mod finite equal to (b η \b ζ ) U, this completes the proof. To prove Theorem 2.6, we want to continue the recursive construction of Lemma 3.10 to a κ-length iteration of posets of the same form, namely Q({ȧ β : β < α}; İα). It turns out that with the exact construction of Lemma 3.10, P ω1 forces that Q({ȧ β : β < ω 1 }; {ȧ β : β < ω 1 } ) is not ccc. For limit ordinals α of uncountable cofinality, it is likely that we have to use {ȧ β : β < α} as our choice for İα. However, we do have more flexibility at limits of countable cofinality and this is critical for extending the construction to any length κ. Definition 3.11. We say that A is a pre-ccc sequence if (1) A = {a β : β < α} for some increasing -chain of subsets of ω with cf(α) = ω 1, (2) for each increasing sequence {γ ξ : ξ ω 1 } cofinal in α, and each sequence {b ξ : ξ ω 1 } A, such that a γξ b ξ = for all ξ, there are ξ < η such that a γξ a γη and b ξ a γη is empty. Lemma 3.12. If A is a pre-ccc sequence, then Q(A; I) is ccc for any ideal I A. Proof. Let A = {a β : β < α}. Let {q ξ : ξ ω 1 } Q = Q(A; I). By passing to a subcollection we can suppose there is a single F [ω] <ℵ 0 such that F qξ = F for all ξ. For each ξ, let b ξ = b qξ, σ ξ = σ qξ, and H ξ = dom(σ ξ ). By the standard -system lemma argument, we may assume that σ ξ σ η is a function for all ξ, η ω 1. For each ξ, let γ ξ be the maximum element of H ξ. By a trivial density argument we can assume that {γ ξ : ξ ω 1 } is a strictly increasing sequence that is cofinal in α. Next, we choose an integer m sufficiently large so that there is again an countable I ω 1 and a subset b of m such that, for all ξ I and all β H ξ (1) σ ξ (β) < m, (2) a β \ m a γξ, (3) b ξ m = b,

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 13 Now we apply the pre-ccc property for the family {γ ξ : ξ I} and the sequence {b ξ \ m : ξ I}. Thus, we may choose ξ < η from I so that a γξ a γη and b ξ \ m is disjoint from a γη. We claim that r = (F, σ ξ σ η, b ξ b η ) is in Q and is an extension of each of q ξ and q η. It suffices to prove that for β H ξ, a β \ σ ξ (β) is disjoint from b η, and similarly, that a β \ σ η (β) is disjoint from b ξ for β H η. Since b ξ m = b η m = b, it suffices to consider a β \ m in each case. For β H ξ, we have a β \ m a γξ a γη, and a γη is disjoint from b η \ m. For β H η, we have a β \ m a γη and a γη is disjoint from b ξ \ m. Definition 3.13. A is the class of triples (P, A, I) such that, there is an ordinal α, and the following holds for each β < α: (1) P = ( P β : β α, Q β : β < α ) is a finite support iteration sequence of ccc posets, (2) A is an α-sequence {ȧ β : β < α}, and Pβ+1 ȧ β ω, (3) I is an α-sequence {İβ : β < α}, (4) Pβ İβ {ȧ ξ : ξ < β} is an ideal (5) for β < γ < α, Pγ+1 ȧ β ȧ γ and Pγ İβ İγ (6) Pβ Q β = Q({ȧ ξ : ξ < β}; İβ), (7) ȧ β is the P β+1 -name for ȧ Q({ȧξ :ξ<β};iβ) (8) if cf(β) = ω, then there is a sequence {İβ,ξ : ξ < β} such that İ β,ξ is a P ξ -name and Pβ İβ = {İβ,ξ : ξ < β}. Lemma 3.14. If α is an ordinal with cofinality ω 1, and if ( P β : β α, Q β : β < α ), {ȧ β : β < α}, {İβ : β < α}) is in A then Pα {ȧ β : β < α} is a pre-ccc sequence. Proof. Let A denote the P α -name of the sequence {ȧ β : β < α}. Let { γ ξ : ξ ω 1 } and {ḃξ : ξ ω 1 } be sequences of P α -names such that there is some p 0 P α forcing that, for each ξ < ω 1, γ ξ α, ḃξ A and ḃξ ȧ γξ is empty. Suppose also that p 0 forces that { γ ξ : ξ ω 1 } is strictly increasing and cofinal in α. We may assume that p 0 decides the value, γ 0, of γ 0. For each ξ < ω 1, choose any p ξ < p 0 that decides a value, γ ξ, of γ ξ and that ḃξ is a P β -name for some β supp(p ξ ). Let g be a continuous strictly increasing function from ω 1 into α with cofinal range. Since P α is ccc we have, for each δ ω 1, the set {ξ : γ ξ < g(δ)} is countable. Therefore there is a cub C ω 1 such that g(δ) γ δ for all δ C. We may also arrange that, for each δ C and ξ < δ, supp(p ξ ) g(δ). For each δ C, we may extend p δ so as to ensure that each of g(δ) and γ δ are in supp(p δ ), and such that there is a β supp(p ξ ) such that ḃξ is a P β -name. We also extend each p δ so that we can arrange a

14 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH list of special properties (referred to as determined in many similar constructions). Specifically, for each β supp(p δ ), (1) there are F δ β [ω]<ℵ 0, H δ β [β]<ℵ 0, σ δ β : Hδ β ω, and a P β- name ḃδ β such that p δ β Pβ p δ (β) = (F δ β, σδ β, ḃδ β ), (2) if g(δ) < γ δ, then g(δ) H δ γ δ, (3) H δ β supp(p δ), (4) if β is a limit with countable cofinality, then there is a µ δ β < β such that ḃδ β is a P µ δ β -name and supp(p δ) β µ δ β, (5) if ι < β is in supp(p δ ), then H δ ι H δ β ι, By the pressing down lemma, there is a stationary set S C and a µ < α such that µ δ g(δ) < µ for all δ S. Now let G µ+1 be P µ+1 -generic filter satisfying that, in the extension, there is a stationary set S 1 S so that p ξ µ G µ+1 for all ξ S 1. We may also arrange that the values of the pair {F ξ g(ξ), F ξ γ ξ } is the same for all ξ S 1. For all β µ + 1, we let a β denote the valuation of ȧ β by G µ+1. By further shrinking S 1 we may suppose there is an m ω and a b m, satisfying that, for all δ S 1, (1) for all β supp(p δ ) Fβ δ m, and, for all ι Hδ β, σδ β (ι) < m, (2) for all β supp(p δ ) µ, a ι \ a µ m (3) b = m b δ g(δ), where bδ g(δ) is the valuation of ḃδ g(δ) by G µ+1, (4) b δ g(δ) a µ m. Fix any ξ < η from S 1. Define q ξ so that supp(q ξ ) = supp(p ξ ) \ µ + 1, and, for β supp(q ξ ), { (F ξ g(ξ) q ξ (β) =, σξ g(ξ) {(µ, m)}, ḃξ g(ξ) ḃη g(η) ) if β = g(ξ) (F ξ β, σξ β, ḃξ β bη g(η) \ m) if g(ξ) < β. We prove by induction on β supp(q ξ ), that there is a condition r ξ β G µ+1 such that r ξ β (q ξ (β + 1)) p ξ (β + 1). Evidently, for the case β = g(ξ), F ξ g(ξ) and m a ι are disjoint from b and so there is some condition in G µ+1 that forces that, they are disjoint from ḃη g(η). Similarly, for ι H ξ g(ξ), a ι \ m a µ, and since a µ \ m (b ξ g(ξ) bη g(η) ) is empty, there is a condition r in G µ+1 that forces that q ξ (g(ξ)) Q g(ξ) and that q ξ (g(ξ)) < p ξ (g(ξ)). In addition, r q ξ (g(ξ) + 1) forces that ȧ g(ξ) is disjoint from b η g(η) \ m. Now, suppose that g(ξ) < β supp(p ξ), and that r q β is a condition in P β that is below p ξ β. We recall that H ξ β supp(p ξ), and so it follows that r q ξ β forces that ȧ ι is disjoint

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 15 from b η g(η) \ m for all ι Hξ β. This is the only thing that needs verifying when checking that r q ξ (β + 1) < p ξ (β + 1). Now that we have that r q ξ forces that ȧ γξ is disjoint from b η g(η) \ m, we can add {(γ ξ, m)} to σ η g(η) and still have a condition. Similarly, for all ι supp(p η ) µ, a ι \ m is contained in a µ, and r q ξ forces that a µ \ m, being a subset of ȧ γξ, is disjoint from ḃξ. This implies that r q ξ forces that (F η g(η), ση g(η) {(γ ξ, m)}, b η g(η) (ḃξ \ m)) is a condition in Q g(η) and is less than p η (g(η)). Now we define a condition q η so that supp(q η ) = supp(p η ) \ µ + 1, and, for β supp(q η ), { (F η g(η) q η (β) =, ση g(η) {(γ ξ, m)}, ḃη g(η) ḃγ ξ ) if β = g(ξ) (F η β, ση β, ḃη β (ḃγ ξ \ m)) if g(η) < β. It again follows, by induction on β supp(q η ), that r q ξ forces that r q ξ (q η (β+1)) is a condition in P β+1 and is below p η (β+1). Finally, we observe that r q ξ q η forces that ȧ γξ ȧ γη because it forces that ȧ γξ m = ȧ γη m and that ȧ γξ \ m ȧ g(η) \ m ȧ γη. Similarly r q ξ q η forces that ȧ γη is disjoint from ḃξ because ḃξ m = b and ȧ γη is disjoint from ḃξ \ m. Corollary 3.15. If ( P β : β α, Q β : β < α ), {ȧ β : β < α}, {İβ : β < α}) is in A, then Pα Q({ȧ β : β < α}; İ) is ccc for each P α- name İ satisfying that P α İ {ȧ β : β < α} is an ideal. Proof of Theorem 2.6. We simply adapt the proof of Lemma 3.10 so as to ensure that, for each α < κ, ( P β : β α, Q β : β < α ), {ȧ β : β < α}, {İβ : β < α}) is in A. The only change to the proof is that when β < κ is a limit with countable cofinality, the definition of İ β is equal to the union of the sequence {İξ+1 : ξ < β}. With this change, we recursively have ensured that our iterations remain in A, and by Corollary 3.15, our iteration is ccc. All the details showing that the closure, A, of the union of the chain {ȧ α : α < κ} is forced to be almost clopen go through as in Lemma 3.10. Similarly, it follows by recursion that the initial family {b ζ : ζ < λ} is a -unbounded subfamily of the ideal {ȧ α : α < κ}. References [1] James E. Baumgartner, Applications of the proper forcing axiom, Handbook of set-theoretic topology, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1984, pp. 913 959. MR776640

16 A. DOW AND S. SHELAH [2] Andreas Blass and Saharon Shelah, There may be simple P ℵ1 - and P ℵ2 - points and the Rudin-Keisler ordering may be downward directed, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 33 (1987), no. 3, 213 243, DOI 10.1016/0168-0072(87)90082-0. MR879489 [3] Kenneth Kunen and Jerry E. Vaughan (eds.), Handbook of set-theoretic topology, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1984. MR776619 (85k:54001) [4] Eric K. van Douwen, Kenneth Kunen, and Jan van Mill, There can be C - embedded dense proper subspaces in βω ω, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 105 (1989), no. 2, 462 470, DOI 10.2307/2046965. MR977925 [5] Alan Dow and Saharon Shelah, Tie-points and fixed-points in N, Topology Appl. 155 (2008), no. 15, 1661 1671, DOI 10.1016/j.topol.2008.05.002. MR2437015 [6], More on tie-points and homeomorphism in N, Fund. Math. 203 (2009), no. 3, 191 210, DOI 10.4064/fm203-3-1. MR2506596 [7], An Efimov space from Martin s axiom, Houston J. Math. 39 (2013), no. 4, 1423 1435. MR3164725 [8] Lech Drewnowski and James W. Roberts, On the primariness of the Banach space l /C 0, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 112 (1991), no. 4, 949 957, DOI 10.2307/2048638. MR1004417 [9] Ilijas Farah, Analytic quotients: theory of liftings for quotients over analytic ideals on the integers, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 148 (2000), no. 702, xvi+177, DOI 10.1090/memo/0702. MR1711328 [10] R. Frankiewicz and P. Zbierski, Strongly discrete subsets in ω, Fund. Math. 129 (1988), no. 3, 173 180. MR962539 [11] N. J. Fine and L. Gillman, Extension of continuous functions in βn, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 66 (1960), 376 381, DOI 10.1090/S0002-9904-1960-10460-0. MR0123291 [12] M. Goldstern and S. Shelah, Ramsey ultrafilters and the reaping number Con(r < u), Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 49 (1990), no. 2, 121 142, DOI 10.1016/0168-0072(90)90063-8. MR1077075 [13] István Juhász, Piotr Koszmider, and Lajos Soukup, A first countable, initially ω 1 -compact but non-compact space, Topology Appl. 156 (2009), no. 10, 1863 1879, DOI 10.1016/j.topol.2009.04.004. MR2519221 [14] Winfried Just, Nowhere dense P -subsets of ω, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 106 (1989), no. 4, 1145 1146, DOI 10.2307/2047305. MR976360 [15] M. Katětov, A theorem on mappings, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolinae 8 (1967), 431 433. MR0229228 [16] Sabine Koppelberg, Minimally generated Boolean algebras, Order 5 (1989), no. 4, 393 406, DOI 10.1007/BF00353658. MR1010388 [17] Piotr Koszmider, Forcing minimal extensions of Boolean algebras, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 351 (1999), no. 8, 3073 3117, DOI 10.1090/S0002-9947- 99-02145-5. MR1467471 [18] Kenneth Kunen, Set theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 102, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam-New York, 1980. An introduction to independence proofs. MR597342 [19] I. E. Leonard and J. H. M. Whitfield, A classical Banach space: l /c 0, Rocky Mountain J. Math. 13 (1983), no. 3, 531 539, DOI 10.1216/RMJ-1983-13-3-531. MR715776

ASYMMETRIC TIE-POINTS AND ALMOST CLOPEN SUBSETS OF N 17 [20] Elliott Pearl (ed.), Open problems in topology. II, Elsevier B. V., Amsterdam, 2007. MR2367385 [21] Mariusz Rabus, On strongly discrete subsets of ω, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 118 (1993), no. 4, 1291 1300, DOI 10.2307/2160090. MR1181172 [22], An ω 2 -minimal Boolean algebra, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 348 (1996), no. 8, 3235 3244, DOI 10.1090/S0002-9947-96-01663-7. MR1357881 [23] B. È. Šapirovskiĭ, The imbedding of extremally disconnected spaces in bicompacta. b-points and weight of pointwise normal spaces, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 223 (1975), no. 5, 1083 1086 (Russian). MR0394609 [24] Saharon Shelah and Juris Steprāns, PFA implies all automorphisms are trivial, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 104 (1988), no. 4, 1220 1225, DOI 10.2307/2047617. MR935111 [25], Somewhere trivial autohomeomorphisms, J. London Math. Soc. (2) 49 (1994), no. 3, 569 580, DOI 10.1112/jlms/49.3.569. MR1271551 [26] Juris Steprāns, The autohomeomorphism group of the Čech-Stone compactification of the integers, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 355 (2003), no. 10, 4223 4240, DOI 10.1090/S0002-9947-03-03329-4. MR1990584 [27] Boban Veličković, OCA and automorphisms of P(ω)/fin, Topology Appl. 49 (1993), no. 1, 1 13, DOI 10.1016/0166-8641(93)90127-Y. MR1202874 Department of Mathematics, University of North Carolina at Charlotte, Charlotte, NC 28223 E-mail address: adow@uncc.edu Department of Mathematics, Rutgers University, Hill Center, Piscataway, New Jersey, U.S.A. 08854-8019 Current address: Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University, Givat Ram, Jerusalem 91904, Israel E-mail address: shelah@math.rutgers.edu