B will distinguish two forms of multiplicity, discrete and continuous.

Similar documents
NOTES ON BEING AND EVENT (PART 3)

Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles

Knowledge, Truth, and Mathematics

The Geometry of Consciousness

The central problem: what are the objects of geometry? Answer 1: Perceptible objects with shape. Answer 2: Abstractions, mere shapes.

In Being and Nothingness, Sartre identifies being-for-itself as consisting in the

SPACETIME HOLISM AND THE PASSAGE OF TIME

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

The Real, the Infinite, Categories, and Cardinal Numbers: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

Are Objects Ontologically Dependent on Processes?

Appendix 2. Leibniz's Predecessors on the Continuum. (a) Aristotle

STA Module 4 Probability Concepts. Rev.F08 1

An Analysis of Zeno s View Regarding Motion

Book 3: Truth 3 of 7

Dynamics of Ocean Structures Prof. Dr. Srinivasan Chandrasekaran Department of Ocean Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

On the Arbitrary Choice Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is "Stationary" and Which is "Moving" in the Special Theory of Relativity

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

Many philosophers accept a layered world view according to which the facts about

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS

LECTURE 10: REVIEW OF POWER SERIES. 1. Motivation

The Evolution and Discovery of the Species of Equality in Euclid s Elements

MA Lesson 25 Section 2.6

8.286 Lecture 6 September 24, 2018 THE DYNAMICS OF NEWTONIAN COSMOLOGY, PART 1

Distinction and the Foundations of Arithmetic

The Identity of One Conservation of the Circle Ilexa Yardley

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time

Infinity. Newton, Leibniz & the Calculus

Research & Reviews: Journal of Pure and Applied Physics

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

This chapter follows from the work done in Chapter 4 of the Core topics book involving quadratic equations.

Analyzing the Twin-Paradox

Chapter 19 Clifford and the Number of Holes

FACTORIZATION AND THE PRIMES

ALBERT EINSTEIN AND THE FABRIC OF TIME by Gevin Giorbran

Lecture 1: Introduction Introduction

The Traveler's Well Newsletter October 2014

2. FUNCTIONS AND ALGEBRA

Dick's PhAQs II: Philosopher-Asked Questions

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Alfred North Whitehead (English Mathematician and Philosopher; )

Communication Engineering Prof. Surendra Prasad Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Delhi

Zeno s Lack of Motion. some of his conclusions seem so extreme to most of us today. The real importance of

ter. on Can we get a still better result? Yes, by making the rectangles still smaller. As we make the rectangles smaller and smaller, the

06. The Aristotelian Tradition

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism

Reviews 341. r 2009 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Integration Made Easy

Vectors and Coordinate Systems

Name: Chris Arledge. School: Ohio University. Mailing Address: 36 Poston Rd, The Plains, OH Phone:

Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Problem Set #10 Due: 12/3/2013

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

The trick is to multiply the numerator and denominator of the big fraction by the least common denominator of every little fraction.

Quantum theory appendix 4: Three options for the future on quantum theory

Introduce complex-valued transcendental functions via the complex exponential defined as:

PREAMBLE (Revised) Why Einstein was Mistaken About the Velocity of Light.

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

Systematic Uncertainty Max Bean John Jay College of Criminal Justice, Physics Program

How does certainty enter into the mind?

Accelerated Observers

The descriptions below provide an overview of the concepts and skills that students explore throughout the 8 th grade.

Atemporality Relation between Time, Mind and Consciousness

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Special Theory Of Relativity Prof. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

Chapter 14. From Randomness to Probability. Copyright 2012, 2008, 2005 Pearson Education, Inc.

Flat Geometry. Spherical Geometry

That which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way stage before it arrives at the goal. as recounted by Aristotle, Physics VI:9, 239b10

ACTIVITY 5. Figure 5-1: Simulated electron interference pattern with your prediction for the next electron s position.

Abstract and Variable Sets in Category Theory 1

THE SIMPLE PROOF OF GOLDBACH'S CONJECTURE. by Miles Mathis

Summer MA Lesson 19 Section 2.6, Section 2.7 (part 1)

DISCRETE DIFFERENTIAL GEOMETRY: AN APPLIED INTRODUCTION Keenan Crane CMU /858B Fall 2017

(Refer Slide Time: 01:17)

The World According to Wolfram

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

Lecture notes on Turing machines

Modern Physics notes Paul Fendley Lecture 35. Born, chapter III (most of which should be review for you), chapter VII

CLASS NOTES: BUSINESS CALCULUS

a (b + c) = a b + a c

MATH 114 Calculus Notes on Chapter 2 (Limits) (pages 60-? in Stewart)

Computational Fluid Dynamics Prof. Dr. SumanChakraborty Department of Mechanical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

Lecture 5. Zeno s Four Paradoxes of Motion

Video Lecture on Engineering Fracture Mechanics, Prof. K. Ramesh, IIT Madras 1

Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism. David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3

Page 52. Lecture 3: Inner Product Spaces Dual Spaces, Dirac Notation, and Adjoints Date Revised: 2008/10/03 Date Given: 2008/10/03

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

Leibniz s Possible Worlds. Liu Jingxian Department of Philosophy Peking University

Journal of Theoretics Vol.5-3 Guest Commentary

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

Section - 9 GRAPHS. (a) y f x (b) y f x. (c) y f x (d) y f x. (e) y f x (f) y f x k. (g) y f x k (h) y kf x. (i) y f kx. [a] y f x to y f x

0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION

09. Kant and Logical Positivism Topics:

Some Thoughts on Computation and Simulation in Cognitive Science

Transcription:

Chapter 2 of Time and Free Will: On the Multiplicity of States of Consciousness: The Idea of Duration John Protevi / LSU French Studies / Lecture notes: DO NOT CITE protevi@lsu.edu / www.protevi.com/john/bergson/tfw2lecture.pdf INTRODUCTION: DELEUZE S READING OF TFW. Deleuze focuses on the notion of MULTIPLICITY in his reading of TFW in Bergsonism, barely mentioning Chs 1 and 3 (intensity and free will). B will distinguish two forms of multiplicity, discrete and continuous. D brings the notion of multiplicity back to Riemann in Bergsonism and in Smooth and Striated chapter of ATP. According to D, roughly speaking, a discrete multiplicity has an internal metric: that is, one of its units can serve as a measure for other units. For example, the first inch of a ruler can measure other parts of the ruler (this part is 1.5 inches long, this other one is 3.7 inches long, etc.) But a continuous multiplicity has to find its metrics (note the plural) elsewhere than in one of its [spatial] parts: for example, in the forces working within it. D finds the confrontation of B and Riemann as the key to rehabilitating Duration and Simultaneity: even if B failed to be able to do the math, the real issue is the nature of multiplicities: the qualitative multiplicity of duration has to be distinguished from the discrete multiplicity of space. (In TFW, this distinction is put in terms of inner psychological states vs. external space, but later in MM and CE the notion of ontological duration and multiple durations makes this more complicated: in a formula, space becomes dilated duration, while cness becomes concentrated duration.) For commentary on D and Riemann, see Plotnitsky in Between Deleuze and Derrida. See also Smith, Durie and Plotnitsky essays in Virtual Mathematics. Multiplicity is not the multiple as a predicate of the one (one thing considered as having multiple aspects), nor is it a synthesis of the one and the multiple, as we see in the first paragraph of Ch 2, where number is defined as synthesis of the one and the multiple, that is, a unification of a multiplicity of parts that can be considered in isolation. More precisely, discrete multiplicity is numerical, but continuous multiplicity is not. The key is that continuous multiplicities are both continuous and heterogeneous. That means they change their nature (their genus) when they divide. That means that each indivisible stage in their unfolding process needs its own measure. This will be key to D s notion of ethics vs morality. Morality has one (abstract) standard which is applied from above, crushing the singularity of concrete situations. [Just as psychoanalysis crushes the singularity of desiring-production by applying Oedipus.] In other words, it treats life as a discrete multiplicity: there

is one unit internal to the multiplicity that can measure all other parts of the multiplicity. The key is the spatial notion of part which ensures the homogeneity of the thing: moral situations differ only in degree. Ethics, OTOH, requires the concrete analysis of the affects generated in encounters of bodies. Thus its metrics are plural and generated on the spot, and must be evaluated on the spot in the full concrete singularity of the situation. In my Schiavo paper, I argue that this is what should ground the liberal notion of the right to privacy, rather than sovereignty-based notions. IOW, D is a full-fledged particularist in ethical theory. Here is a chart drawn from D s Bergsonism comparing the two multiplicities. Discrete multiplicity Space / impure, homogeneous time Exteriority Simultaneity Juxtaposition Order [Homogeneity] Quantitative differenciation Difference of degree Numerical Discontinuous Actual Continuous multiplicity Pure duration Interiority Succession Fusion Organization Heterogeneity Qualitative discrimination Difference of kind or nature Irreducible to number Continuous Virtual 1. NUMBER. B begins Ch 2 with a discussion of number as synthesis of one and multiple. A number is a unity grasped by a simple intuition, but it is also a gathering or summation of units. These units must be homogeneous: they have to be stripped of any qualitative difference. They are then laid out in an ideal space, even when we are retaining their images in counting them in what is falsely thought to be duration. After discussing provisional vs ultimate units and the discontinuity of number, B distinguishes process and product [62 / 83]. This is an important principle for B: you cannot use the properties of the product to think the process by which the product is generated. [Compare here Marx and the fetishism of commodities: we are fascinated by the properties of the product and cannot think the process of production.] Generating a number is a process of unification. As a process, it is indivisible. That is, if you interrupt the process, you change it qualitatively. The generation of a sum of these units proceeds by discontinuity, since the units must have an edge to them to indicate when they start and stop [note the spatial language here]. So the indivisible act of thinking of any one number is represented as a point in space separated by an interval from another point. But once the number has been formed into a product, the points seem to have blended into a line. Thus we look back and are able to decompose the number according to any metric we want, not necessarily the original unit. In other words, the properties of the product [continuity and

indefinite divisibility] are not the same as the properties of the process [discontinuity and indivisible units]. 2. This way of thinking about number leads us to distinguish TWO FORMS OF MULTIPLICITY: the discrete / numberical (space) and the continuous / qualitative (duration). It is important not to confuse the continuity of a line with the continuous nature of duration. The difference is this: in duration we can have continuity and heterogeneity: that is, there is otherness in the process, but this otherness is qualitative difference, not quantitative difference. For instance, the later segments of a melody feel different from the earlier segments: the impression of the whole melody changes as it unrolls. But if we want to count parts of the melody (e.g., as notes), then we have to strip them of their qualitative difference and separate them. This means that we can only count parts of our conscious life by means of symbolic representations (e.g., notes on a scale). This counting of states of our inner life (which is analogous to counting positions of motion) leads us to the notion of spatialized time time as a homogeneous medium, represented by a line. 3. The notion of spatialized, homogeneous time and its relation to duration takes us to KANT. In the Transcendental Aesthetic of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant distinguishes space as form of outer intuition (all appearances spread themselves around us) from time as form of inner intuition (all appearances occur in ordered series). Intuition for Kant = immediate relation to an object. K distinguishes empirical intuition as immediate relation to object via sensation from pure intuition = space and time as unlimited single intuitions. As the form of inner intuition, time is itself a pure intuition. They are pure because they abstract from sense; they thus remain as individual wholes. Now determinate spaces and times are only parts of these wholes. And in a very important move for B, Kant shows that his notion of time as homogeneous medium is modeled on space. Kant says that time is represented as a line: And just because this inner intuition yields no shape, we endeavor to make up for this want by analogies. We represent the time-sequence by a line progressing to infinity and we reason from the properties of this line to all the properties of time, with this one exception, that while all the parts of the line are simultaneous, the parts of time are always successive (A33 / B50). Homogeneous or spatialized time is thus only the condition of our experience for Kant: it has no reality in itself: if we abstract from the subjective conditions of sensible intuition, time is nothing (A 36 / B 52). We could say that for B, time (as concrete, real time, as duration) is not the condition of our experience, but the very being of our experience. And this holds not just our experience, for time as duration is reality itself for B, as we will see in MM Ch 4. We can note the analogy between B and Heidegger here. Both hold that the straightline model of time is an abstraction from concrete / primordial time, and that Kant was blocked from seeing this by his adherence to the straight-line model. The differ

in that H gives Kant more credit than B does. In Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, H will say that Kant has a more radical theory of time as pure autoaffection, via a reading of the schematism of the transcendental imagination. According to H, the three modes of synthesis of the transcendental imagination reproduction, recognition, and apprehension produce the three dimensions of time. No need to go into detail here; we may come back to this in discussing MM. 4. Let s talk about B s account of the GENESIS OF THE MISTAKEN IDEA OF HOMOGENEOUS TIME. First, we have to understand that space in TFW is pure exteriority, that is, a range of juxtaposed points existing in pure simultaneity. Thus space is nothing but a series of snap-shots; the whole universe displays a certain arrangement of points and then dies and is reborn an instant later with a different arrangement of points. This is because any and all retention of past moments, as in the recognition of motion, occurs via mental synthesis. But remember as well, that inner life is a continuous multiplicity of mutually interpenetrating phases, unrolling in a qualitatively changing process. So if we think that we count our mental states, it must mean that I have spatialized the states, separating them and placing them side-by-side in an ideal space that my mind s eye travels along. (At 79 / 107, B says that we have a hard time thinking like this, since external things seem to have their own duration. This is very important: B excludes this possibility here in TFW, but will affirm it in MM and CE.) Now we get to the notion of exchange. First, note that each of our phases of inner life correspond to the spatial position of a marker. We then get into the habit of distinguishing between the moments of our inner life, just as the strikes of a clock, or the footfalls of a passer-by, are distinguished. In other words, we refer to the external causes of a series of impressions, just as in Ch 1, B shows how we refer to the external cause of a single sensation (and falsely interpret as the change of a single state what is really the changing quality of our entire inner being). The exchange has a second step: the external phenomena benefit from this correspondence, as instead of merely being discontinuous snap-shots (we ll see this term in MM 1 s account of pure perception), they are retained and arranged in a series. Where are they retained and arranged? In an ideal space, that is, the homogeneous time we conceive of via our misinterpretation or symbolical representation of our inner duration. So we have three elements: real space w/o duration but only homogeneous juxtaposition; real duration w/o space but continuous interpenetrating heterogeneity; and finally, homogeneous time as the symbolic representation of duration. Thus homogeneous time is a mixture of duration and space, a product of exchange. An exchange between the act of moving and the space traversed by a completed motion sets up the paradoxes of Zeno and the Eleatics. Again, we see the theme of process and product, and not confusing the properties of each. The space traversed by a motion (the product ) is infinitely divisible, but the process is not: it is indivisible (that is, any division near a threshold would result in qualitative change).

The key is simultaneity, the intersection of time and space. What we measure in scientific measurement is the distance between simultaneities, or better, the distance between the point in ideal space / homogeneous time we determine as the correspondence of our recognition [a psychological act or phase of the flow of our inner life] and a marker at point A [in real space] and the point in ideal space / homogeneous time we determine as the correspondence of our recognition and the same marker at point B. 5. B gives us ANOTHER VERSION OF THE GENESIS OF ILLUSION OF HOMOGENEOUS TIME. Our sole reality is duration, so we can only arrive at homogeneous time through a process rooted in duration. Even such a misunderstood time is still a form of time, and can never arise from space, but only from our misunderstanding duration in terms of space. Let s look at counting again: we have to strip quality to get homogeneous units to count as juxtaposed in an ideal space. This is number as product, the result of the two-fold process of qualitative stripping and juxtaposition in an ideal space. But if we attend to the very process of counting, what do we see? We see the retention and addition of units, such that each added unit changes the quality of the retained whole, its rhythm. IOW, the process of adding three things feels qualitatively different from the process of adding two things: there s a different rhythm ( dum, dum, dum does not equal dum, dum ). THUS, there is a quality to quantity, which we can see if we pay attention to the very process of counting. BUT, the product, the number produced, is that of three homogeneous units, that is quantity without quality. THUS, if we transpose or exchange the properties of the product (discrete spatial homogeneity) with the properties of the process (continuous temporal heterogeneity) we get the hybrid of homogeneous time.