The Baire Category Theorem and choice

Similar documents
ON PRELINDELÖF METRIC SPACES AND THE AXIOM OF CHOICE GONÇALO GUTIERRES

Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

COMPACTNESS IN COUNTABLE TYCHONOFF PRODUCTS AND CHOICE. Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis, Jean E. Rubin and Adrienne Stanley January 11, 1999

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

int cl int cl A = int cl A.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

Uniquely Universal Sets

4 Countability axioms

GENERALIZED CANTOR SETS AND SETS OF SUMS OF CONVERGENT ALTERNATING SERIES

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

Filters in Analysis and Topology

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras

7 Complete metric spaces and function spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Axioms for Set Theory

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

POINT SET TOPOLOGY. Definition 2 A set with a topological structure is a topological space (X, O)

Neighborhood spaces and convergence

Continuous functions that are nowhere differentiable

Continuous functions with compact support

ČECH-COMPLETE MAPS. Yun-Feng Bai and Takuo Miwa Shimane University, Japan

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Properties of the real line and weak forms of the Axiom of Choice

Sequences of height 1 primes in Z[X]

MATH 614 Dynamical Systems and Chaos Lecture 6: Symbolic dynamics.

A new proof of the 2-dimensional Halpern Läuchli Theorem

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.ho] 2 Feb 2005

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c

Product metrics and boundedness

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

Section 31. The Separation Axioms

DEFINITIONS OF FINITENESS BASED ON ORDER PROPERTIES

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

Axioms of separation

Topological vectorspaces

DEFINITIONS OF COMPACTNESS AND THE AXIOM OF CHOICE. Omar De la Cruz, Eric Hall, Paul Howard, Jean E. Rubin, and Adrienne Stanley, April 17, 2001

CLASS NOTES FOR APRIL 14, 2000

Notes on nets and convergence in topology

MH 7500 THEOREMS. (iii) A = A; (iv) A B = A B. Theorem 5. If {A α : α Λ} is any collection of subsets of a space X, then

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

Unions and the axiom of choice

Chapter 2 Axiomatic Set Theory

Spaces of continuous functions

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Russell Sets, Topology, and Cardinals

Permutation models, topological groups and Ramsey actions

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

01. Review of metric spaces and point-set topology. 1. Euclidean spaces

On sums of Darboux and nowhere constant continuous functions

arxiv: v2 [math.gn] 27 Sep 2010

E.7 Alaoglu s Theorem

COUNTABLY S-CLOSED SPACES

CERTAIN WEAKLY GENERATED NONCOMPACT, PSEUDO-COMPACT TOPOLOGIES ON TYCHONOFF CUBES. Leonard R. Rubin University of Oklahoma, USA

On Uniform Spaces with Invariant Nonstandard Hulls

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Essential equilibria in normal-form games

Math 117: Topology of the Real Numbers

Contents. Index... 15

COUNTABLE PARACOMPACTNESS AND WEAK NORMALITY PROPERTIES

Meta-logic derivation rules

A PROOF OF A CONVEX-VALUED SELECTION THEOREM WITH THE CODOMAIN OF A FRÉCHET SPACE. Myung-Hyun Cho and Jun-Hui Kim. 1. Introduction

Your first day at work MATH 806 (Fall 2015)

ALMOST DISJOINT AND INDEPENDENT FAMILIES. 1. introduction. is infinite. Fichtenholz and Kantorovich showed that there is an independent family

VALUATION THEORY, GENERALIZED IFS ATTRACTORS AND FRACTALS

Fragmentability and σ-fragmentability

Chapter 1: Banach Spaces

7. Quotient and Bi.quotient Spaces o M.spaces

Compactifications of Discrete Spaces

SPACES WHOSE PSEUDOCOMPACT SUBSPACES ARE CLOSED SUBSETS. Alan Dow, Jack R. Porter, R.M. Stephenson, Jr., and R. Grant Woods

Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of β N

On a Question of Maarten Maurice

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp.

SOME BANACH SPACE GEOMETRY

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

Topological properties

MA651 Topology. Lecture 10. Metric Spaces.

Description of the book Set Theory

A Note on Superamorphous Sets and Dual Dedekind-Infinity

Zornian Functional Analysis or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Axiom of Choice

The Space of Minimal Prime Ideals of C(x) Need not be Basically Disconnected

ANALYSIS WORKSHEET II: METRIC SPACES

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

D-MINIMAL EXPANSIONS OF THE REAL FIELD HAVE THE C p ZERO SET PROPERTY

Measure and Category. Marianna Csörnyei. ucahmcs

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

A NUMBER-THEORETIC CONJECTURE AND ITS IMPLICATION FOR SET THEORY. 1. Motivation

8 Complete fields and valuation rings

An introduction to OCA

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Topological automorphisms of modified Sierpiński gaskets realize arbitrary finite permutation groups

Topology, Math 581, Fall 2017 last updated: November 24, Topology 1, Math 581, Fall 2017: Notes and homework Krzysztof Chris Ciesielski

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

Transcription:

Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 The Baire Category Theorem and choice Horst Herrlich a,, Kyriakos Keremedis b a Department of Mathematics, University of Bremen, Postfach 330440, 28334 Bremen, Germany b Department of Mathematics, University of the Aegean, Karlovasi, 83200 Samos, Greece Received 27 July 1998; received in revised form 10 March 1999 Abstract The status of the Baire Category Theorem in ZF (i.e., Zermelo Fraenkel set theory without the Axiom of Choice) is investigated. Typical results: 1. The Baire Category Theorem holds for compact pseudometric spaces. 2. The Axiom of Countable Choice is equivalent to the Baire Category Theorem for countable products of compact pseudometric spaces. 3. The Axiom of Dependent Choice is equivalent to the Baire Category Theorem for countable products of compact Hausdorff spaces. 4. The Baire Category Theorem for B-compact regular spaces is equivalent to the conjunction of the Axiom of Dependent Choice and the Weak Ultrafilter Theorem. 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Axiom of Dependent Choice; Weak Ultrafilter Theorem; Axiom of Countable Choice; Baire Category Theorem; Countable Tychonoff Theorem; Compact topological space; Complete (pseudo) metric space AMS classification: 03E25; 54A35; 54D30; 54E52 Introduction The purpose of this note is to investigate how much choice is needed for the various forms of the Baire Category Theorem to hold in ZF (i.e., in Zermelo Fraenkel set theory without the Axiom of Choice). For investigations with similar scope see [2,7], and particularly [4]. First, we list some definitions and known results. Corresponding author. E-mail addresses: herrlich@math.uni-bremen.de (H. Herrlich), kker@aegean.gr (K. Keremedis). 0166-8641/00/$ see front matter 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. PII: S0166-8641(99)00132-7

158 H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 Definition 0.1. N is the set of positive integers. Definition 0.2 (Axiom of Choice; AC). For each family (X i ) i I of non-empty sets, the product set i I X i is non-empty. Definition 0.3 (Axiom of Countable Choice; CC). For each sequence (X n ) n N of nonempty sets, the product set n N X n is non-empty. Definition 0.4 (Axiom of Dependent Choice; DC). If φ is a (binary) relation on a nonempty set such that then x X y X xφy, (x n ) X N n N x n φx n+1. Definition 0.5 (Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice; CMC). For each sequence (X n ) n N of non-empty sets, there exists a sequence (Y n ) n N of non-empty, finite sets with Y n X n for each n. Definition 0.6 (Axiom of Dependent Multiple Choice; DMC). If φ is a (binary) relation on a non-empty set, such that x X y Xxφy, then there exists a sequence (X n ) of finite, non-empty subsets of X, such that n N x X n y X n+1 xφy. Definition 0.7 (Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem; PIT). Every non-trivial Boolean algebra has a prime ideal; equivalently: every filter on a set can be extended to an ultrafilter. Definition 0.8 (Countable Ultrafilter Theorem; CUT). On each set, every filter with a countable base can be extended to an ultrafilter. Definition 0.9 (Weak Ultrafilter Theorem; WUT). ultrafilter (i.e., an ultrafilter U with U = ). Every infinite set contains a free Definition 0.10. Let (X, d) be a pseudometric space. (1) For x X and r a positive real, S(x,r) ={y X d(x,y) < r} is the open ball with center x and radius r. (2) (X, d) is complete provided every Cauchy-sequence converges in (X, d). (3) (X, d) is called totally bounded providedforeach positivereal r there exists a finite subset Y of X with X = { S(y,r) y Y }. Definition 0.11. A grill on a set X is a collection of subsets of X satisfying the following conditions:

H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 159 (1) X G and / G, (2) (A B) G (A G or B G). A grill G converges to x in a space X provided that G contains all neighborhoods of x as members. Definition 0.12. A topological (or pseudometric) space X is called (1) compact provided that every open cover of X contains a finite cover; equivalently: every filter has an accumulation point in X; equivalently: every grill converges in X (cf. [10]), (2) countably compact, provided that every countable open cover of X contains a finite cover; equivalently: every filter with a countable base has an accumulation point in X, (3) sequentially compact provided that every sequence in X has a convergent subsequence, (4) Baire provided that X is either empty or satisfies the following equivalent conditions: (a) X is not the union of a sequence (A n ) of nowhere dense sets in X, (b) the intersection of any sequence (D n ) of dense, open subsets of X is non-empty. Theorem 0.13 (Baire Category Theorem). In ZFC, i.e., ZF with the Axiom of Choice: (1) every complete pseudometric space is Baire; (2) every compact Hausdorff space is Baire. From now on we will work in ZF. The following results are known: Theorem 0.14 [4]. Every separable complete pseudometric space is Baire. Theorem 0.15 [1]. Equivalent are: (1) every totally bounded complete pseudometric space is Baire, (2) every second countable complete pseudometric space is Baire, (3) the Axiom of Countable Choice. Theorem 0.16 [2,8]. Equivalent are: (1) every complete pseudometric space is Baire, (2) every complete metric space is Baire, (3) for every discrete space X the space X N is Baire, (4) the Axiom of Dependent Choice. Theorem 0.17 [7]. Equivalent are: (1) every compact Hausdorff space is Baire, (2) the Axiom of Dependent Multiple Choice.

160 H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 1. Results Our first result provides a positive answer to a question posed by Brunner [4]. Theorem 1.1. Countably compact pseudometric spaces are Baire. Proof. Let (D n ) be a sequence of dense, open subsets of a non-empty, countably compact pseudometric space. Construct, via induction, a sequence of pairs (m n,a n ), consisting of positive integers m n and non-empty open subsets A n of X, as follows: m 0 = min { k N x D 0, dist(x, X\D 0 )> 1 } k, (1) A 0 = { x D 0 dist(x, X\D 0 )> m 1 } 0. m n+1 = min { k N x (D n+1 A n ), dist ( x,x\(d n+1 A n ) ) > k 1 }, (2) A n+1 = { x D n+1 A n dist ( x,x\(d n+1 A n ) ) > m 1 } n+1. Then A n+1 cl A n+1 (A n D n ). Thus, by countable compactness, A n = cl An D n. Hence D n. Theorem 1.2. Equivalent are: (1) countable products of compact pseudometric spaces are Baire, (2) countable products of compact pseudometric spaces are compact, (3) for each compact pseudometric space X, the space X N is Baire, (4) for each compact pseudometric space X, the space X N is compact, (5) the Axiom of Countable Choice. Proof. (5) (2) Let ((X n,d n )) be a sequence of compact pseudometric spaces. Then d ( (x n ), (y n ) ) = max { min { d n (x n,y n ), n 1 } } n N defines a pseudometric on the product X = X n that induces the product topology. Since each (X n,d n ) is complete and totally bounded so is (X, d). Thus (5) implies (see [1, Corollary 4.5]) that (X, d) is compact. (2) (1) and (4) (3) Immediate from Theorem 1.1. (1) (3) and (2) (4) Obvious. (3) (5) Let (X n ) be a sequence of non-empty sets X n. Define a compact pseudometric space (X, d) by X = { (0, 0) } n N( Xn {n} ) and d ( (x, n), (y, n) ) 0, if n + m = 0, 1 = n + m 1, if n m = 0andn + m 0, 1 n m 1, if n m 0. In the product space (X, d) N, for each n N the set D n = π 1 [ m Xn {n} ] m N

H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 161 is open and dense. Thus, by (3), D = n N D n. Let(d n ) = ((y n,m n )) be an element of D. Then the sequence (d n ) meets each X m {m}, thus the sequence (y n ) meets each X m. Hence the sequence (x n ),definedbyx n = y min{m N ym X n }, is an element of n N X n. Proposition 1.3. The Axiom of Dependent Choice implies that countable products of compact spaces are compact. Proof. Immediate from the following lemma. (Cf. also [4,9,13].) Lemma 1.4. If G is a grill in X Y, π X [G] converges to x in X, and Y is compact, then there exists y Y such that G converges to (x, y) in X Y. Proof. Assume that no such y exists. Then the collection A of all open sets A of Y for whom there exists a neighborhood U of x in X with (U A) / G, is an open cover of Y. By compactness there exists a finite subset B of A that covers Y. Select for each B B a neighborhood U B of x in X with (U B B) / G Then U = {U B B B} is a neighborhood of x in X with (U B) / G for each B B. SinceG is a grill this implies πx 1 [U]=U Y = U B = {U B B B} / G; a contradiction, since π X [G] converges to x in X. Definition 1.5. For every set X we denote by αx the Alexandroff-one-point-compactification of the discrete space X. Theorem 1.6 (cf. [4]). Equivalent are: (1) Countable products of compact Hausdorff spaces are Baire, (2) (a) countable products of compact (Hausdorff ) spaces are compact and (b) each compact Hausdorff space is Baire, (3) for each set X, the space (αx) N is Baire. (4) the Axiom of Dependent Choice. Proof. (1) (3) Immediate since each space αx is compact Hausdorff. (3) (4) As a ready adaption of the corresponding proof in [2] we get the following: Let X be a non-empty set and ϱ a relation on X such that for each x X there exists a y in X with xϱy. Form the space Y = (αx) N. For each n N the set B n of all (x n ) X N with the property m n k m x m ϱx k is dense and open in Y. Thus (3) implies n B n. Pick a point (x n ) in n B n and define a sequence (a n ) by induction: a 0 = x 0, a n+1 = x min{m an ϱx m }.

162 H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 Thus a n ϱa n+1 for each n. Hence (4) holds. (4) (2) By Proposition 1.3, (4) (2a). That (4) (2b) is straightforward. (2) (1) Immediate. Remarks 1.7. (1) (2a) does not imply (2b): There are models (see [14]) that satisfy the Axiom of Countable Choice and the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem, hence (2a); but not (4), hence not (2b). (2) The question whether (2b) implies (2a) equivalently, whether the Axioms of Dependent Multiple Choice and of Dependent Choice are equivalent remains open. However, there are models in ZF 0 (Zermelo Fraenkel with atoms) that satisfy (2b) but not (4), hence not (2a). See [3,15]. (3) As is well known (2a) (without Hausdorff) implies the Axiom of Countable Choice (whether the converse holds is still unknown, see [13]), and (2a) (including Hausdorff) implies the Axiom of Countable Choice for finite sets. (4) The preceding observations connect Theorem 1.6 with the fact (see [3]) that the Axiom of Dependent Choice (= (4)) is equivalent to the conjunction of the Axiom of Dependent Multiple Choice ( = (2b) via Theorem 0.17) and the Axiom of Countable Choice for finite sets. 2. Variations In the above the terms complete and compact have their familiar meanings. What happens if we replace these concepts by different ones that are equivalent to the familiar ones in the presence of the Axiom of Choice? Consider the following concepts: Definition 2.1. (1) A pseudometric space X is called filter-complete, provided that each Cauchy filter in X converges. (2) A topological space X is called B-compact provided that each ultrafilter in X converges. Proposition 2.2. Equivalent are: (1) filter-complete = complete, (2) the Axiom of Countable Choice. Proof. (1) (2) If (2) fails there exists a sequence (X n ) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets such that each sequence in n X n meets only finitely many members X n (see [12]). Thus the pseudometric space (X, d),definedby X = n ( Xn {n} ) and

H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 163 d ( (x, n), (y, m) ) { 1 = n m 1, if n m, 0, if n = m, is complete, but not filter-complete since the filter F = { F X n m n(x m {m}) F } is a Cauchy filter on (X, d) (i.e., for every ε>0 there exists an F in F whose diameter is smaller than ε) that fails to converge in (X, d). Hence (1) fails. (2) (1) Let F be a Cauchy filter in X. By (2) there is a sequence (F n ) of members of F with diam F n < 2 n. Again by (2) there exists an element (x n ) in n F n. By construction (x n ) is a Cauchy-sequence in X. If(x n ) x,thenf x. Proposition 2.3. Each filter-complete, second countable pseudometric space is Baire. Proof. Straightforward. Remark 2.4. The precise set-theoretic status of the statement that filter-complete, totally bounded pseudometric spaces are Baire still eludes us. We have partial results only. If, however, total boundedness would be replaced by filter-total-boundedness (meaning that each filter can be extended to a Cauchy filter), then filter-complete, filter-totally-bounded pseudometric spaces would be compact, thus by Theorem 1.1 Baire. Lemma 2.5. Every filter-complete, totally bounded pseudometric space is B-compact. Proof. Let U be an ultrafilter in a pseudometric space X. IfX is totally bounded then U, being a grill, is a Cauchy filter. Thus, if X is complete, U converges. Proposition 2.6. Consider the conditions (1) (4) below. Then (1) (2) (3) (4). (1) The Countable Ultrafilter Theorem. (2) Every B-compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire. (3) Every filter-complete, totally bounded (pseudo)metric space is Baire. (4) The Axiom of Countable Choice for finite sets. Proof. (1) (2) In view of Theorem 1.1 it suffices to show that every B-compact pseudometric space X is countably compact, i.e., that in X each filter F with a countable base has an accumulation point. By (1), F is contained in some ultrafilter U. By B- compactness, U converges to some x. Thus x is an accumulation point of F. (2) (3) Immediate from Lemma 2.5. (3) (4) If (4) fails, then there exists a sequence (X n ) of finite non-empty sets such that each countable set meets only finitely many X n s. (Cf. [12].) Let be an element not contained in n N X n. Consider for each n N the metric space (Y n,d n ) with Y n = X n { } and { 0, if x = y, d n (x, y) = 1 n, if x y.

164 H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 Then the metric space (X, d),definedby X = Y n and d ( (x n ), (y n ) ) = max { d n (x n,y n ) n N } n N is non-empty, filter-complete and totally bounded. Moreover, for each n N the set D n = n m π m 1[X m] is open and dense in (X, d). Thus, by (3), D = n N D n. But for each element (d n ) of D the countable set {d n n N} meets infinitely many of the set X n, contradicting the assumption. Remark 2.7. (1) The conditions (1) and (4) of the above proposition are not equivalent. Indeed, in Feferman s Model, model M 2 in [15], CUT fails but the Axiom of Countable Choice for finite sets is true. (2) The conditions (2) and (3) of the above proposition are independent of the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice, since there are models of ZF that respectively (a) satisfy the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem, hence (2) and (3), but not the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice. In Mostowski s Linearly Ordered Model, see [15], Model N 3, the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem holds but the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice fails; (b) satisfy the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice, but not the Axiom of Countable Choice, hence neither (2) nor (3). In the Second Fraenkel Model, see [15], Model N 2, the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice is true but the Axiom of Countable choice fails. (3) The condition that complete, totally bounded pseudometric spaces are Baire is properly stronger than the condition that filter-complete, totally bounded pseudometric spaces are Baire, since there are models of ZF that satisfy the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem but not the Axiom of Countable Choice. As we have seen in 2(a), in N 3, the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem holds but the Axiom of Countable Multiple Choice fails and consequently the Axiom of Countable Choice fails also. (4) Condition (2) implies that there exists a free ultrafilter on N (see the proof of Theorem 2.10 below). Proposition 2.8. Equivalent are: (1) every sequentially compact pseudometric space is Baire, (2) every sequentially compact, totally bounded pseudometric space is Baire, (3) the Axiom of Countable Choice. Proof. (1) (2) Obvious. (2) (3) Assume that (3) fails. Then (see [12]) there exists a sequence (X n ) of non-empty sets such that each countable set meets only finitely many X n s. Construct a

H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 165 sequentially compact, totally bounded pseudometric space (X, d) as follows: Let φ : N {r Q 0 r 1} be a bijection, and define: X = n N( Xn {n} ), d ( (x, n), (y, m) ) = φ(n) φ(m). Since each X n {n} is nowhere dense in the space (X, d), the latter is not Baire; contradicting (2). (3) (1) Immediate in view of Theorem 1.1 and the fact that (3) implies that every sequentially compact pseudometric space is compact. Proposition 2.9 [11]. Equivalent are: (1) B-compact = compact, (2) the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem. Theorem 2.10. Equivalent are: (1) every B-compact regular space is Baire, (2) (a) the Axiom of Dependent Choice and (b) the Weak Ultrafilter Theorem, (3) (a) the Axiom of Dependent Choice and (b) N has a free ultrafilter, (4) (a) the Axiom of Dependent Choice and (b) the Countable Ultrafilter Theorem. Proof. (1) (3) Since, for each set X, the space (αx) N is B-compact and regular, (1) implies, via Theorem 1.6, that (3a) holds. If (3b) would fail, then there would be no free ultrafilter on Q. Thus Q, supplied with its standardtopology, would be a B-compactregular space that fails to be Baire, contradicting (1). (3) (4) Let F be a filter on X with a base (F n ) n N.DefineG n = n i=1 F i.if n G n, there is a fixed ultrafilter containing F. Otherwise we may assume without loss of generality that H n = G n \G n+1 for each n. By (a) there exists an element (x n ) n H n.ifu is a free ultrafilter on N,then G = { G X {n x n G} U } is an ultrafilter on X with F G. (4) (1) Let X be a non-empty B-compact regular space, and let (A n ) be a sequence of nowhere dense subsets of X. By means of (4a) and regularity of X one obtains a sequence (F n ) of open subsets of X satisfying (a) A n cl F n = for each n, (b) F 0 cl F 1 F 1 cl F 2 F 2. By (4b) the filter, generated by {F n n N} is contained in some ultrafilter U. ByBcompactness of X, U converges to some point x X. Consequently x n cl F n thus x/ n A n.

166 H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 (3) (2) Let X be an infinite set. By (3a), X is Dedekind-infinite, i.e., there exists an injection ϕ : N X. IfU is a free ultrafilter on N, then{v X ϕ 1 [V ] U} is a free ultrafilter on X. (2) (3) Obvious. Remarks 2.11. (1) The conditions (2b), (3b), and (4b) together do not imply condition (2a), since there are models (see [14]) that satisfy the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem but no the Axiom of Dependent Choice. (2) The Weak Ultrafilter theorem is strictly weaker than the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem. See, e.g., [15]. (3) The Axiom of Dependent Choice does not imply the Weak Ultrafilter Theorem. See [6] and [17]. (4) Condition (4a) can be replaced by the Axiom of Dependent Multiple Choice. Thus, in the presence of the Countable Ultrafilter Theorem, the Axiom of Dependent Choice is equivalent to the Axiom of Dependent Multiple Choice. It is an open problem whether this equivalence holds without any restrictions. Acknowledgement The authors acknowledge a suggestion by the referee that helped to simplify the proof of Theorem 1.2. References [1] H.L. Bentley, H. Herrlich, Countable choice and pseudometric spaces, Topology Appl. 85 (1998) 153 164. [2] C.E. Blair, The Baire category theorem implies the principle of dependent choices, Bull. Acad. Polon. Sci. 25 (1977) 933 934. [3] A. Blass, Injectivity, projectivity, and the axiom of choice, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 225 (1979) 31 59. [4] N. Brunner, Kategoriensätze und Multiples Auswahlaxiom, Z. Math. Logik Grundlag. Math. 29 (1983) 435 443. [5] N. Brunner, 75 years of independence proofs by Fraenkel Mostowski permutation models, Math. Japonica 43 (1996) 177 199. [6] S. Feferman, Applications of the notions of forcing and generic sets, Fund. Math. 56 (1965) 325 345. [7] J. Fossy, M. Morillon, The Baire category property and some notions of compactness, J. London Math. Soc., to appear. [8] R. Goldblatt, On the role of the Baire category theorem and dependent choice in the foundations of logic, J. Symbolic Logic 50 (1985) 412 422. [9] C. Good, I.J. Tree, Continuing horrors of topology without choice, Topology Appl. 63 (1995) 79 90. [10] H. Herrlich, Topologie I: Topologische Räume, Heldermann, Berlin, 1986. [11] H. Herrlich, Compactness and the axiom of choice, Appl. Cat. Str. 4 (1996) 1 14.

H. Herrlich, K. Keremedis / Topology and its Applications 108 (2000) 157 167 167 [12] H. Herrlich, J. Steprāns, Maximal filters, continuity and choice principles, Quaestiones Math. 20 (1997) 697 706. [13] P. Howard, K. Keremedis, J. Rubin, A. Stanley, Compactness in Tychonoff products and choice, Preprint, 1998. [14] P. Howard, J.E. Rubin, The Boolean prime ideal theorem plus countable choice do not imply dependent choice, Math. Log. Quart. 42 (1996) 410 420. [15] P. Howard, J.E. Rubin, Consequences of the Axiom of Choice, AMS Math. Surveys and Monographs 59, AMS, Providence, RI, 1998. [16] K. Keremedis, Disasters in topology without the axiom of choice, Preprint, 1995. [17] J. Truss, The axiom of choice for linearly ordered families, Fund. Math. 99 (1978) 133 139.