Set-Monotonicity Implies Kelly-Strategyproofness

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Set-Monotonicity Implies Kelly-Strategyproofness"

Transcription

1 Set-Monotonicity Implies Kelly-Strategyproofness arxiv: v5 [cs.ma] 5 Feb 2015 Felix Brandt Technische Universität München Munich, Germany brandtf@in.tum.de This paper studies the strategic manipulation of set-valued social choice functions according to Kelly s preference extension, which prescribes that one set of alternatives is preferred to another if and only if all elements of the former are preferred to all elements of the latter. It is shown that set-monotonicity a new variant of Maskin-monotonicity implies Kellystrategyproofness in comprehensive subdomains of the linear domain. Interestingly, there are a handful of appealing Condorcet extensions such as the top cycle, the minimal covering set, and the bipartisan set that satisfy set-monotonicity even in the unrestricted linear domain, thereby answering questions raised independently by Barberà (1977a) and Kelly (1977). Keywords: Social Choice Theory, Strategyproofness, Kelly s Preference Extension JEL Classifications Codes: D71, C70 1. Introduction One of the central results in microeconomic theory states that every non-trivial social choice function (SCF) a function mapping individual preferences to a collective choice is susceptible to strategic manipulation (Gibbard, 1973; Satterthwaite, 1975). However, the classic theorem by Gibbard and Satterthwaite only applies to resolute, i.e., single-valued, SCFs. The notion of a resolute SCF is rather restricted and artificial. 1 For example, consider a situation with two agents and two alternatives such that each 1 For instance, Gärdenfors (1976) claims that [resoluteness] is a rather restrictive and unnatural assumption. In a similar vein, Kelly (1977) writes that the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem [...] uses an assumption of singlevaluedness which is unreasonable and Taylor (2005) that If there is a weakness to the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem, it is the assumption that winners are unique. This sentiment is echoed by various other authors (see, e.g., Barberà, 1977b; Feldman, 1979b; Bandyopadhyay, 1983a,b; Duggan and Schwartz, 2000; Nehring, 2000; Ching and Zhou, 2002). 1

2 agent prefers a different alternative. The problem is not that a resolute SCF has to pick a single alternative (which is a well-motivated practical requirement), but that it has to pick a single alternative based on the individual preferences alone (see also, Kelly, 1977). As a consequence, resoluteness is at variance with elementary notions of fairness such as neutrality and anonymity. In order to remedy this shortcoming, Gibbard (1977) went on to characterize the class of strategyproof social decision schemes (SDSs), i.e., aggregation functions that yield probability distributions over the set of alternatives rather than single alternatives (see also Gibbard, 1978; Barberà, 1979). This class consists of rather degenerate SDSs and Gibbard s characterization is therefore often interpreted as another impossibility result. However, Gibbard s theorem rests on unusually strong assumptions with respect to the agents preferences. In contrast to the traditional setup in social choice theory, which typically only involves ordinal preferences, his result relies on the expected utility axioms of von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947), and hence on the existence of linear utility functions, in order to compare lotteries over alternatives. The gap between Gibbard and Satterthwaite s theorem for resolute SCFs and Gibbard s theorem for SDSs has been filled by a number of impossibility results with varying underlying notions of how to compare sets of alternatives with each other (e.g., Gärdenfors, 1976; Barberà, 1977a,b; Kelly, 1977; Feldman, 1979a; MacIntyre and Pattanaik, 1981; Bandyopadhyay, 1982, 1983b; Duggan and Schwartz, 2000; Barberà et al., 2001; Ching and Zhou, 2002; Sato, 2008; Umezawa, 2009), many of which are surveyed by Taylor (2005) and Barberà (2010). In this paper, we will be concerned with the one of the weakest (and therefore least controversial) preference extensions from alternatives to sets due to Kelly (1977). According to this definition, a set of alternatives is weakly preferred to another set of alternatives if all elements of the former are weakly preferred to all elements of the latter. A nice aspect of Kelly s preference extension is that its underlying behavioral assumptions are quite minimalistic (which strengthens impossibility results), yet reasonable enough to motivate meaningful positive results. Kelly s extension models that the agents are complete unaware of the tie-breaking mechanism that is used to eventually pick a single alternative. The question pursued in this paper is whether this uncertainty can be exploited to achieve strategyproofness. Barberà (1977a) and Kelly (1977) have shown independently that all non-trivial SCFs that are rationalizable via a quasi-transitive relation are manipulable according to Kelly s extension. 2 However, it is it well-known that (quasi-transitive) rationalizability by itself is unduly restrictive (see, e.g., Mas-Colell and Sonnenschein, 1972). As a consequence, Kelly (1977) concludes his paper by contemplating that one plausible interpretation of such a theorem is that, rather than demonstrating the impossibility of reasonable strategy-proof social choice functions, it is part of a critique of the regularity [rationalizability] conditions and Barberà (1977a) states that whether a nonrationalizable collective choice rule exists which is not manipulable and always leads to nonempty choices for nonempty finite issues is an open question. Also referring to nonrationaliz- 2 Barberà (1977a) actually uses an extension that is even weaker than that of Kelly (1977). 2

3 able choice functions, Kelly(1977) writes: it is an open question how far nondictatorship can be strengthened in this sort of direction and still avoid impossibility results. The condition of rationalizability has been significantly weakened in subsequent impossibility results (MacIntyre and Pattanaik, 1981; Bandyopadhyay, 1982, 1983b). At the same time, it has been noted that more positive results can be obtained for antisymmetric (i.e., linear) individual preferences. In particular, it was shown that the omninomination rule (Gärdenfors, 1976), the Pareto rule (Feldman, 1979a,b), the Condorcet rule (Gärdenfors, 1976; Nehring, 2000), and the top cycle (MacIntyre and Pattanaik, 1981; Bandyopadhyay, 1983a; Sanver and Zwicker, 2012) are strategyproof when preference are linear (see Remark 1 for more details about these SCFs). However, all these rules are very indecisive and the latter two may even return Pareto-dominated alternatives. In this paper, we propose a new variant of Maskin-monotonicity for set-valued SCFs called set-monotonicity and show that all set-monotonic SCFs are strategyproof in sufficiently rich subdomains of the linear domain. This covers all of the positive results mentioned above and proves that some much more discriminating SCFs are strategyproof. Set-monotonicity requires the invariance of choice sets under the weakening of unchosen alternatives and is satisfied by the omninomination rule, the Pareto rule, the Condorcet rule, and a handful of appealing Condorcet extensions such as top cycle, the minimal covering set, and the bipartisan set. Since set-monotonicity coincides with Maskin-monotonicity in the context of resolute SCFs, this characterization can be seen as a set-valued generalization of the Muller and Satterthwaite (1977) theorem. Nehring (2000) has proved a similar extension of the Muller-Sattherthwaite theorem by showing that Maskin-monotonicity implies strategyproofness of set-valued SCFs in a sense marginally weaker than that of Kelly (see also Remark 6). 3 However, while Maskin-monotonicity is prohibitive in the general domain, set-monotonicity is not. The conditions themselves are independent, but we show that Maskin-montonicity implies set-monotonicity when assuming independence of unchosen alternatives. We conclude the paper with a number of remarks concerning group-strategyproofness, stronger preference extensions, weak preferences, weaker domain conditions, and strategic abstention. 2. Preliminaries Let N = {1,...,n} be a finite set of agents, A a finite and nonempty set of alternatives, and L the set of all linear (i.e., complete, transitive, and antisymmetric) preference relations over A. For R i L, x R i y denotes that agent i values alternative x at least as much as alternative y. We write P i for the strict part of R i, i.e., x P i y if x R i y but not y R i x. The (strict) lower contour set of alternative x with respect to P i is denoted by L(x,R i ) = {y A: x P i y}. For convenience, we will represent preference relations 3 According to Nehring s definition, a manipulator is only better off if he strictly prefers all alternatives in the new choice set to all alternatives in the original choice set. For linear preferences, the two definitions only differ in whether there can be a single alternative at the intersection of both choice sets or not. 3

4 as comma-separated lists. For example, a P i b P i c will be written as R i : a,b,c. Two distinct alternatives x and y are adjacent in R i if there is no z with x P i z P i y. A (Cartesian) domain of preference profiles D is defined as D = i N D i L N. The maximal domain L N will be referred to as the general domain. We say that R lies in the comprehensive closure of R and R if for all i N, R i R i R i. A domain D is comprehensive if for all R,R D and R L N such that R lies in the comprehensive closure of R and R, R D (Nehring, 2000). For example, the domain of all linear extensions of a fixed partial order is comprehensive. For a given preference profile R D, R i = (R 1,...,R i 1,R i+1,...,r n ) denotes the vector of all preference relations except that of agent i. An alternative x A is called a Condorcet winner if {i N: x P i y} > n/2 for all y A\{x}. Our central object of study are social choice functions. A social choice function (SCF) is a function f that maps a preferenceprofile R D to a nonempty subsetof alternatives f(r). f is resolute if f(r) = 1 for all R D. A Condorcet extension is an SCF that uniquely selects a Condorcet winner whenever one exists Monotonicity We will consider three variants of monotonicity: a weak standard notion and two strengthenings, one of which was proposed by Maskin (1999) and one of which is new to this paper. For a given preference profile R, an agent i, and two adjacent alternatives x,y such that y P i x, R i:(x,y) denotes the preference profile in which agent i swapped alternatives x and y and that is otherwise identical to R. Definition 1. Let R,R D, i N, and x,y A such that R = R i:(x,y). Then, SCF f satisfies monotonicity, Maskin-monotonicity, or set-monotonicity, if x f(r) implies x f(r ), z f(r) and y A\{z} implies z f(r ), or Z = f(r) and y A\Z implies Z = f(r ), respectively. (monotonicity) (Maskin-monotonicity) (set-monotonicity) The intuitive meaning of these definitions is as follows. An SCF satisfies monotonicity if a chosen alternative remains in the choice set when it is strengthened with respect to another alternative; it satisfies Maskin-monotonicity if a chosen alternative remains in the choice set when weakening another alternative; and it satisfies set-monotonicity if the choice set is invariant under the weakening of unchosen alternatives. 45 Clearly, Maskin-monotonicity implies monotonicity and, as will be shown in Proposition 2, set-monotonicity also implies monotonicity. Despite the similar appearance, set-monotonicity is logically independent of Maskin-monotonicity. Set-monotonicity has 4 Sanver and Zwicker (2012) study monotonicity properties for set-valued SCFs in general. None of the properties they consider is equivalent to set-monotonicity. 5 Note that set-monotonicity is in conflict with decisiveness. For instance, non-trivial set-monotonic SCFs cannot satisfy the (rather strong) positive responsiveness condition introduced by Barberà (1977b). 4

5 a stronger antecedent and a stronger consequence. For example, consider a comprehensive single-agent domain consisting of the relations R 1 and R 1 given by R 1 : a,b,c, and R 1 : b,a,c. If we define SCF f by letting f((r 1 )) = {c} and f((r 1 )) = {b,c}, f satisfies Maskinmonotonicity, but violates set-monotonicity. If, on the other hand, we define f by letting f((r 1 )) = {a,b,c} and f((r 1 )) = {b,a}, f satisfies set-monotonicity, but violates Maskin-monotonicity. Set-monotonicity coincides with Maskin-monotonicity in the context of resolute SCFs. Under the condition of independence of unchosen alternatives which is satisfied by various set-valued SCFs, set-monotonicity is weaker than Maskin-monotonicity. Moreover, set-monotonicity implies independence of unchosen alternatives. Independence of unchosen alternatives was introduced by Laslier (1997) in the context of tournament solutions (as independence of the losers ) and requires that the choice set is invariant under modifications of the preference profile with respect to unchosen alternatives. Definition 2. An SCF f satisfies independence of unchosen alternatives (IUA) if for all R,R D such that R i {x,y} = R i {x,y} for all x f(r), y A, and i N, f(r) = f(r ). Proposition 1. Maskin-monotonicity and IUA imply set-monotonicity. Proof. Let f be an SCF, R D, i N, x A, y A \ f(r), and R = R i:(x,y). Maskin-monotonicity implies that f(r) f(r ). Now, assume for contradiction that there is some x f(r ) \f(r). Since x f(r), it follows from Maskin-monotonicity that there is some y A that is strengthened with respect to x when moving from R to R. Hence, R = R i:(x,y ), x = x, and y = y. Since x = x f(r) and y f(r) by assumption, IUA implies that f(r) = f(r ), a contradiction. Proposition 2. Set-monotonicity implies monotonicity and IUA. Proof. We first show that set-monotonicity implies monotonicity. Let f be a setmonotonic SCF, R D, i N, x f(r), y A, and R R i:(x,y). Clearly, in case y f(r), set-monotonicity implies that f(r ) = f(r) and thus x f(r ). If, on the other hand, y f(r), assume for contradiction that x f(r ). When moving from R to R, y is strengthened with respect to outside alternative x, and set-monotonicity again implies that f(r) = f(r ), a contradiction. The fact that set-monotonicity implies IUA is straightforward from the definitions Strategyproofness An SCF is manipulable if an agent can misrepresent his preferences in order to obtain a more preferred outcome. Whether one choice set is preferred to another depends on how the preferences over individual alternatives are to be extended to sets of alternatives. 5

6 In the absence of information about the tie-breaking mechanism that eventually picks a single alternative from any choice set, preferences over choice sets are obtained by the conservative extension R i (Kelly, 1977), where for any pair of nonempty sets X,Y A and preference relation R i, X R i Y if and only if x R i y for all x X and y Y. Clearly, in all but the simplest cases, R i is incomplete, i.e., many pairs of choice sets are incomparable. The strict part of R i is denoted by P i, i.e., X P i Y if and only if X R i Y and x P i y for at least one pair of x X and y Y. For linear preferences, X P i Y if and only if x P i y for all x X and y Y with x y. Hence, X Y 1. Definition 3. An SCF is Kelly-strategyproof if there exist no R,R D and i N with R i = R i such that f(r ) P i f(r). Kelly-strategyproofness is a very weak notion of strategyproofness. Nevertheless, most well-known SCFs such as plurality, Borda s rule, Copeland s rule, Slater s rule, or plurality with runoff fail to be Kelly-strategyproof in the general domain (see, e.g., Taylor, 2005, Theorem 2.2.2). Muller and Satterthwaite (1977) have shown that, in the general domain, a resolute SCF is strategyproof if and only if it satisfies Maskin-monotonicity. Unfortunately, as famously shown by Gibbard (1973) and Satterthwaite (1975), only dictatorial or imposing resolute SCFs satisfy Maskin-monotonicity in the general domain. However, Maskin-monotonicity still implies strategyproofness of resolute SCFs in many restricted domains of interest (see, e.g., Klaus and Bochet, 2013), including the class of comprehensive domains considered in this paper (Nehring, 2000). 3. The Result Theorem 1. Every set-monotonic SCF on a comprehensive domain is Kellystrategyproof. Proof. Let f be a set-monotonic SCF and D a comprehensive domain. We first show that set-monotonicity is equivalent to a version of set-monotonicity that is not restricted to pairwise swaps of adjacent alternatives. Rather, we require that choice sets may only change if an alternative is removed from a lower contour set of a chosen alternative. For R,R D and i N with R i = R i, we say that R is an f-improvement over R if for all x f(r), L(x,P i ) L(x,P i ). We claim that if R is an f-improvement over R, then f(r ) = f(r). The statement can be shown by induction on d(r,r ) = R i \R i. The induction basis is trivially satisfied because R = R if d(r,r ) = 0. Assume the statement is true for all R and R with d(r,r ) < k and consider R and R such that d(r,r ) = k. Since R R, there have to be two alternatives x,y A such that x P i y and y P i x. Due to the transitivity of R i and R i, we may furthermore assume that x and y are adjacent in R i. (However, x and y need not be adjacent in R i.) x f(r) because otherwise R is not an f-improvement over R. Set-monotonicity 6

7 implies that f(r i:(y,x) ) = f(r) and comprehensiveness that R i:(y,x) D. It follows from d(r i:(y,x),r ) < k and the induction hypothesis that f(r i:(y,x) ) = f(r ). Hence, f(r) = f(r ), Now, for the proof of the statement of the theorem, assume for contradiction that f is not Kelly-strategyproof. Then, there have to be R,R D, and i N with R i = R i such that f(r ) P i f(r). The latter obviously entails that f(r) f(r ). The proof idea is to find some R in the comprehensive closure of R and R (and hence in D) such that R is an f-improvement over both R and R, which implies that f(r) = f(r ), a contradiction. Let m f(r ) such that L(m,P i ) f(r ) =. In other words, m is the alternative in f(r ) that is ranked lowest in R i. Note that, if f(r) f(r ), then f(r) f(r ) = {m}. Next, we partition A into the strict lower contour set and the upper contour set of m with respect to R i, i.e., L = L(m,P i ) and U = A\L and define a new preference profile by letting R i = R i L R i U {(x,y): x U,y L}, i.e., the upper part of Ri is ranked as in R i and the lower part as in R i, and R = (R i,ri ) = (R i,r i ). R lies in the comprehensive closure of R and R (and hence in D) because for all x,y A with x Ri y, we have x R i y or x R i y. For x,y U, this follows from Ri U = R i U; for x,y L, from Ri L = R i L ; and for x U,y L from (x,y) R i. R isanf-improvement over Rbecausef(R) L {m}andl(x,pi ) = L(x,P i)forall x L and L(m,Pi ) L(m,P i) = L. Set-monotonicity then implies that f(r ) = f(r). R is an f-improvement over R because f(r ) U and L(x,Pi ) = L(x,P i ) L for all x U. Hence, set-monotonicity impliesthatf(r ) = f(r ) f(r), acontradiction. We conclude the paper with nine remarks. Remark 1 (Set-monotonic SCFs). There are a number of rather attractive SCFs that satisfy set-monotonicity in the general domain L N. In particular, every monotonic SCF that satisfies the strong superset property (SSP) (i.e., choice sets are invariant under the removal of unchosen alternatives) also satisfies set-monotonicity. 6 Prominent Condorcet extensions that satisfy both SSP and monotonicity include the Condorcet rule (which selects a Condorcet winner whenever one exists and returns all alternatives otherwise), the top cycle (also known as weak closure maximality, GETCHA, or the Smith set) (Good, 1971; Smith, 1973; Bordes, 1976; Sen, 1977; Schwartz, 1986), the minimal covering set (Dutta, 1990), the bipartisan set (Laffond et al., 1993) and variations of 6 The strong superset property goes back to early work by Chernoff (1954) (where it was called postulate 5 ) and is also known as α (Brandt and Harrenstein, 2011), the attention filter axiom (Masatlioglu et al., 2012), and outcast (Aizerman and Aleskerov, 1995). The term strong superset property was first used by Bordes (1979). We refer to Monjardet (2008) for a more thorough discussion of the origins of this condition. 7

8 these (see Laslier, 1997; Dutta and Laslier, 1999; Laslier, 2000; Brandt, 2011). 78 Two other SCFs that satisfy set-monotonicity are the Pareto rule and the omninomination rule (which returns all alternatives that are top-ranked by at least one agent). Remark 2 (Coarsenings of Kelly-strategyproof SCFs). For two SCFs f,f, we say that f is a coarsening of f if f (R) f(r) for all R D. Kelly s preference extension has the useful property that X P i Y implies X Pi Y for all non-singleton subsets X X and Y Y. Hence, every coarsening f of a Kelly-strategyproof SCF f is Kelly-strategyproof if f(r) = f (R) whenever f (R) = 1. As a consequence, the (McKelvey) uncovered set (see Duggan, 2013), a coarsening of the minimal covering set that returns singletons if and only if there is a Condorcet winner, is Kelly-strategyproof, eventhoughitviolates set-monotonicity. 9 Inlightofthesecomments, itseemsinteresting to try to identify inclusion-minimal Kelly-strategyproof SCFs. Remark 3 (Group-strategyproofness). The proof of Theorem 1 can be straightforwardly extended to show that no group of agents can misstate their preferences in order to obtain a more preferred outcome. Remark 4 (Fishburn-strategyproofness). It has been shown in other work that Theorem 1 does not carry over to slightly more complete set extensions due to Fishburn and Gärdenfors (Brandt and Brill, 2011). In fact, Pareto-optimality and Fishburn-strategyproofness are already incompatible within the class of majoritarian SCFs (Brandt and Geist, 2014). Remark 5 (Necessary conditions). It seems like there are no natural necessary conditions for Kelly-strategyproofness as long as preferences are linear. For example, any SCF f such that f(r) > ( A /2)+1 for all R D satisfies Kelly-strategyproofness simply because no pair of resulting choice sets is comparable. This observation allows one to easily construct Kelly-strategyproof SCFs that violate set-monotonicity, Maskinmonotonicity, or any other reasonable form of monotonicity. Remark 6 (Weak preferences). When individual preference relations do not have to be antisymmetric, a number of results mentioned in the introduction rule out the possibility of reasonable Kelly-strategyproof SCFs. A new result of this kind, which strengthens some existing theorems, is given as Theorem 2 in the Appendix. 7 Remarkably, the robustness of the minimal covering set and the bipartisan set with respect to strategic manipulation also extends to agenda manipulation. The strong superset property precisely states that an SCF is resistant to adding and deleting losing alternatives (see also the discussion by Bordes, 1983). Moreover, both SCFs are composition-consistent, i.e., they are strongly resistant to the introduction of clones (Laffond et al., 1996). Scoring rules like plurality and Borda s rule are prone to both types of agenda manipulation (Laslier, 1996; Brandt and Harrenstein, 2011) as well as to strategic manipulation. 8 Another prominent Condorcet extension the tournament equilibrium set (Schwartz, 1990) was conjectured to satisfy SSP and monotonicity for almost 20 years. This conjecture was recently disproved by Brandt et al. (2013). In fact, it can be shown that the tournament equilibrium set as well as the related minimal extending set (Brandt, 2011) can be Kelly-manipulated. 9 For generalized strategyproofness as defined by Nehring (2000) (see Remark 6), the second condition is not required and every coarsening of a strategyproof SCF is strategyproof. 8

9 The proof of Theorem 1 can be adapted for weak preferences to show that setmonotonicity implies Nehring s generalized strategyproofness, a weakening of Kellystrategyproofness (Nehring, 2000). 10 Generalized strategyproofness is defined by letting agent i prefer set X to set Y if and only if x P i y for all x X and y Y. Remark 7 (Matching markets). Theorem 1 can be straightforwardly extended to domains in which the indifference relation is fixed for each agent. This is, for example, the case in matching markets where each agent is typically assumed to be indifferent between all matchings in which his assignment is identical. Remark 8 (Connected domains). Theorem 1 does not hold for a weakening of comprehensiveness, which Nehring (2000) refers to as connectedness. A domain D is connected if for all i N, R i,r i D i, the following holds: if there is some R i L \ {R i,r i } with R R R, then there is some R i D i\{r i,r i } with R R R. The following single-agent SCF f, defined on a connected but not comprehensive domain of size three, has been adapted from Nehring (2000) and satisfies set-monotonicity while it violates Kelly-strategyproofness: R 1 : a,b,c,d, R 1 : a,b,d,c, R 1 : b,a,d,c, f((r 1 f((r 1 )) = {c}, f((r 1 )) = {a,b,c,d}, )) = {b}. Remark 9 (Strategic abstention). Fishburn and Brams (1983) introduced a particularly natural variant of strategic manipulation where agents obtain a more preferred outcome by abstaining the election. Moulin (1988) has shown that every resolute Condorcet extension can be manipulated in this way and thus suffers from the so-called no-show paradox. However, Moulin s proof strongly relies on resoluteness. If preferences over sets are given by Kelly s extension, set-valued Condorcet extension that satisfy Kelly-strategyproofness also cannot be manipulated by abstention under very mild conditions. This is, for instance, the case for all SCFs whose outcome only depends on pairwise majority margins (which covers all of the Condorcet extensions mentioned in Remark 1) because any manipulation by abstention can be turned into a manipulation by strategic misrepresentation. 11 Acknowledgments I am grateful to Florian Brandl, Markus Brill, and Paul Harrenstein for helpful discussions and comments. This material is based on work supported by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft under grants BR 2312/3-3, BR 2312/7-1, and BR 2312/7-2. Early results of this paper were presented at the 22nd International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (Barcelona, July 2011). A previous version of this paper, titled Group-Strategyproof Irresolute Social Choice Functions, circulated since For generalized strategyproofness, it would also suffice to require a weakening of set-monotonicity in which the choice set can only get smaller when unchosen alternatives are weakened. 11 Pérez (2001) and Jimeno et al. (2009) have proved versions of Moulin s theorem (Moulin, 1988) for set-valued Condorcet extensions by using stronger assumptions on preference over sets. 9

10 References M. Aizerman and F. Aleskerov. Theory of Choice, volume 38 of Studies in Mathematical and Managerial Economics. North-Holland, T. Bandyopadhyay. Threats, counter-threats and strategic manipulation for non-binary group decision rules. Mathematical Social Sciences, 2(2): , T. Bandyopadhyay. Multi-valued decision rules and coalitional non-manipulability. Economics Letters, 13(1):37 44, 1983a. T. Bandyopadhyay. Manipulation of non-imposed, non-oligarchic, non-binary group decision rules. Economics Letters, 11(1 2):69 73, 1983b. S. Barberà. Manipulation of social decision functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 15 (2): , 1977a. S. Barberà. The manipulation of social choice mechanisms that do not leave too much to chance. Econometrica, 45(7): , 1977b. S. Barberà. A note on group strategy-proof decision schemes. Econometrica, 47(3): , S. Barberà. Strategy-proof social choice. In K. J. Arrow, A. K. Sen, and K. Suzumura, editors, Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, volume 2, chapter 25, pages Elsevier, S. Barberà, B. Dutta, and A. Sen. Strategy-proof social choice correspondences. Journal of Economic Theory, 101(2): , G. Bordes. Consistency, rationality and collective choice. Review of Economic Studies, 43(3): , G. Bordes. Some more results on consistency, rationality and collective choice. In J. J. Laffont, editor, Aggregation and Revelation of Preferences, chapter 10, pages North-Holland, G. Bordes. On the possibility of reasonable consistent majoritarian choice: Some positive results. Journal of Economic Theory, 31: , F. Brandt. Minimal stable sets in tournaments. Journal of Economic Theory, 146(4): , F. Brandt and M. Brill. Necessary and sufficient conditions for the strategyproofness of irresolute social choice functions. In Proceedings of the 13th Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge (TARK), pages ACM Press, F. Brandt and C. Geist. Finding strategyproof social choice functions via SAT solving. In Proceedings of the 13th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multi- Agent Systems (AAMAS), pages IFAAMAS,

11 F. Brandt and P. Harrenstein. Set-rationalizable choice and self-stability. Journal of Economic Theory, 146(4): , F. Brandt, M. Chudnovsky, I. Kim, G. Liu, S. Norin, A. Scott, P. Seymour, and S. Thomassé. A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz. Social Choice and Welfare, 40: , H. Chernoff. Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica, 22: , S. Ching and L. Zhou. Multi-valued strategy-proof social choice rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 19: , J. Duggan. Uncovered sets. Social Choice and Welfare, 41: , J. Duggan and T. Schwartz. Strategic manipulability without resoluteness or shared beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite generalized. Social Choice and Welfare, 17(1):85 93, B. Dutta. On the tournament equilibrium set. Social Choice and Welfare, 7(4): , B. Dutta and J.-F. Laslier. Comparison functions and choice correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 16(4): , A. Feldman. Manipulation and the Pareto rule. Journal of Economic Theory, 21: , 1979a. A. Feldman. Nonmanipulable multi-valued social choice decision functions. Public Choice, 34: , 1979b. P. C. Fishburn and S. J. Brams. Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56(4): , P. Gärdenfors. Manipulation of social choice functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 13 (2): , A. Gibbard. Manipulation of voting schemes. Econometrica, 41: , A. Gibbard. Manipulation of schemes that mix voting with chance. Econometrica, 45 (3): , A. Gibbard. Straightforwardness of game forms with lotteries as outcomes. Econometrica, 46(3): , I. J. Good. A note on Condorcet sets. Public Choice, 10:97 101, J. L. Jimeno, J. Pérez, and E. García. An extension of the Moulin No Show Paradox for voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 33(3): ,

12 J. S. Kelly. Strategy-proofness and social choice functions without single-valuedness. Econometrica, 45(2): , B. Klaus and O. Bochet. The relation between monotonicity and strategyproofness. Social Choice and Welfare, 40(1):41 63, G. Laffond, J.-F. Laslier, and M. Le Breton. The bipartisan set of a tournament game. Games and Economic Behavior, 5: , G. Laffond, J. Lainé, and J.-F. Laslier. Composition-consistent tournament solutions and social choice functions. Social Choice and Welfare, 13:75 93, J.-F. Laslier. Rank-based choice correspondences. Economics Letters, 52: , J.-F. Laslier. Tournament Solutions and Majority Voting. Springer-Verlag, J.-F. Laslier. Aggregation of preferences with a variable set of alternatives. Social Choice and Welfare, 17: , I. MacIntyre and P. K. Pattanaik. Strategic voting under minimally binary group decision functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 25(3): , A. Mas-Colell and H. Sonnenschein. General possibility theorems for group decisions. Review of Economic Studies, 39(2): , Y. Masatlioglu, D. Nakajima, and E. Y. Ozbay. Revealed attention. American Economic Review, 102(5): , E. Maskin. Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Review of Economic Studies, 66 (26):23 38, B. Monjardet. Statement of precedence and a comment on IIA terminology. Games and Economic Behavior, 62: , H. Moulin. Condorcet s principle implies the no show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45:53 64, E. Muller and M. A. Satterthwaite. The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. Journal of Economic Theory, 14(2): , K. Nehring. Monotonicity implies generalized strategy-proofness for correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 17(2): , J. Pérez. The strong no show paradoxes are a common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 18(3): , M. R. Sanver and W. S. Zwicker. Monotonicity properties and their adaption to irresolute social choice rules. Social Choice and Welfare, 39(2 3): ,

13 S. Sato. On strategy-proof social choice correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 31: , M. A. Satterthwaite. Strategy-proofness and Arrow s conditions: Existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10: , T. Schwartz. The Logic of Collective Choice. Columbia University Press, T. Schwartz. Cyclic tournaments and cooperative majority voting: A solution. Social Choice and Welfare, 7(1):19 29, A. K. Sen. Social choice theory: A re-examination. Econometrica, 45(1):53 89, J. H. Smith. Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica, 41(6): , A. D. Taylor. Social Choice and the Mathematics of Manipulation. Cambridge University Press, M. Umezawa. Coalitionally strategy-proof social choice correspondences and the Pareto rule. Social Choice and Welfare, 33: , J. von Neumann and O. Morgenstern. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press, 2nd edition, A. Appendix For the domain of transitive and complete (but not necessarily antisymmetric) preference relations R N, we show that all Condorcet extensions are Kelly-manipulable. This strengthens Theorem 3 by Gärdenfors (1976) and Theorem by Taylor (2005), who showed the same statement for a weaker notion of manipulability and a weaker notion of Condorcet winners, respectively. When assuming that pairwise choices are made according to majority rule, this also strengthens Theorems 1 and 2 by MacIntyre and Pattanaik (1981). However, our construction requires that the number of agents is linear in the number of alternatives. Theorem 2. No Condorcet extension is Kelly-strategyproof in domain R N when there are more than two alternatives. Proof. Let A = {a 1,...,a m } with m 3 and consider the following preference profile R with 3m agents. In the representation below, sets denote indifference classes of the agents. 13

14 R 1,R 2 : {a 2,...,a m },a 1 R 3,R 4 : {a 1,a 3,...,a m },a 2.. R 2m 1,R 2m : {a 1,...,a m 1 },a m R 2m+1 : {a 3,...,a m },a 1,a 2.. R 3m 1 : {a 1,...,a m 2 },a m 1,a m R 3m : {a 2,...,a m 1 },a m,a 1 For every alternative a i, there are two agents who prefer every alternative to a i and are otherwise indifferent. Moreover, for every alternative a i there is one agent who prefers every alternative except a i+1 to a i, ranks a i+1 below a i, and is otherwise indifferent. Since f(r) yields a nonempty choice set, there has to be some a i f(r). Due to the symmetry of the preference profile, we may assume without loss of generality that a 2 f(r). Now, let R 3,R 4 : a 1,{a 3,...,a m },a 2 and define R = (R 3,R 3 ) and R = (R 4,R 4 ). That is, R is identical to R, except that agent 3 lifted a 1 on top and R is identical to R, except that agent 4 lifted a 1 on top. Observe that f(r ) = {a 1 } because a 1 is the Condorcet winner in R. In case that a 2 f(r ), agent 3 can manipulate as follows. Suppose R is the true preference profile. Then, the least favorable alternative of agent 3 is chosen (possibly among other alternatives). He can misstate his preferences as in R such that a 2 is not chosen. Since he is indifferent between all other alternatives, f(r ) P 3 f(r). If a 2 f(r ), agent 4 can manipulate similarly. Suppose R is the true preference profile. Again, the least favorable alternative of agent 4 is chosen. By misstating his preferences as in R, he can assure that one of his preferred alternatives, namely a 1, is selected exclusively because it is the Condorcet winner in R. Hence, f(r ) P 4 f(r ). 14

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for the Strategyproofness of Irresolute Social Choice Functions

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for the Strategyproofness of Irresolute Social Choice Functions Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for the Strategyproofness of Irresolute Social Choice Functions Felix Brandt Technische Universität München 85748 Garching bei München, Germany brandtf@in.tum.de Markus

More information

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Felix Brandt and Paul Harrenstein Technische Universität München 85748 Garching bei München, Germany {brandtf,harrenst}@in.tum.de Rationalizability and similar

More information

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Felix Brandt Christian Geist Paul Harrenstein Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract

More information

A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz

A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz Felix Brandt 1 Technische Universität München Munich, Germany Maria Chudnovsky 2 Columbia University New York, NY, USA Ilhee Kim Princeton University Princeton,

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz

A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz Felix Brandt 1 Technische Universität München Munich, Germany Maria Chudnovsky 2 Columbia University New York, NY, USA Ilhee Kim Gaku Liu Sergey Norin McGill

More information

Extending Tournament Solutions

Extending Tournament Solutions Extending Tournament Solutions Felix Brandt Institut für Informatik Technische Universität München brandtf@in.tum.de Markus Brill Department of Computer Science Duke University brill@cs.duke.edu Paul Harrenstein

More information

Voting with Ties: Strong Impossibilities via SAT Solving

Voting with Ties: Strong Impossibilities via SAT Solving Voting with Ties: Strong Impossibilities via SAT Solving Felix Brandt Technische Universität München Munich, Germany brandtf@in.tum.de Christian Saile Technische Universität München Munich, Germany saile@in.tum.de

More information

Finding Strategyproof Social Choice Functions via SAT Solving

Finding Strategyproof Social Choice Functions via SAT Solving Finding Strategyproof Social Choice Functions via SAT Solving Felix Brandt and Christian Geist Abstract A promising direction in computational social choice is to address open research problems using computer-aided

More information

On the Structure of Stable Tournament Solutions

On the Structure of Stable Tournament Solutions On the Structure of Stable Tournament Solutions Felix Brandt Technical University of Munich Germany Hans Georg Seedig Technical University of Munich Germany Markus Brill Oxford University United Kingdom

More information

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Social Choice and Mechanism Design Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Alexander Westkamp April 2011 Introduction Two concerns regarding our previous approach to collective decision making:

More information

The Tale of the Tournament Equilibrium Set. Felix Brandt Dagstuhl, March 2012

The Tale of the Tournament Equilibrium Set. Felix Brandt Dagstuhl, March 2012 The Tale of the Tournament Equilibrium Set Felix Brandt Dagstuhl, March 2012 Rational Choice Theory Amartya K. Sen 2 Rational Choice Theory Let U be a universe of at least three alternatives. Amartya K.

More information

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Felix Brandt and Paul Harrenstein Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München 80538 Munich, Germany {brandtf,harrenst}@tcs.ifi.lmu.de arxiv:0910.3580v3 [cs.ma] 24

More information

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Martin Barbie, Clemens Puppe * Department of Economics, University of Karlsruhe D 76128 Karlsruhe, Germany and Attila Tasnádi ** Department of Mathematics, Budapest

More information

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions Selçuk Özyurt and M. Remzi Sanver May 22, 2008 Abstract A social choice hyperfunction picks a non-empty set of alternatives

More information

Welfare Maximization Entices Participation

Welfare Maximization Entices Participation Welfare Maximization Entices Participation Florian Brandl Felix Brandt Johannes Hofbauer Technische Universität München {brandlfl,brandtf,hofbauej}@in.tum.de We consider randomized public good mechanisms

More information

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester May 17, 2004 Abstract Suppose a strict

More information

An Analytical and Experimental Comparison of Maximal Lottery Schemes

An Analytical and Experimental Comparison of Maximal Lottery Schemes An Analytical and Experimental Comparison of Maximal Lottery Schemes Florian Brandl Felix Brandt Christian Stricker Technische Universität München {brandlfl,brandtf,stricker}@in.tum.de Abstract Randomized

More information

On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness in Randomized Social Choice

On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness in Randomized Social Choice On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness in Randomized Social Choice Haris Aziz NICTA and UNSW Australia haris.aziz@nicta.com.au Felix Brandt TU München Germany brandtf@in.tum.de

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Volume 31, Issue 1 Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Abstract In an election contest, a losing candidate a can manipulate

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627 U.S.A. Michel Le Breton CORE

More information

When Does Schwartz Conjecture Hold?

When Does Schwartz Conjecture Hold? Proceedings of the Twenty-Fourth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI 015) When Does Schwartz Conjecture Hold? Matthias Mnich Universität Bonn Bonn, Germany Yash Raj Shrestha

More information

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia Abstract A procedure to construct a social welfare function from a social choice function is suggested

More information

Learning from paired comparisons: three is enough, two is not

Learning from paired comparisons: three is enough, two is not Learning from paired comparisons: three is enough, two is not University of Cambridge, Statistics Laboratory, UK; CNRS, Paris School of Economics, France Paris, December 2014 2 Pairwise comparisons A set

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University {kenshin,sandholm}@cscmuedu Abstract The Muller-Satterthwaite

More information

Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes

Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes Laura Kasper Hans Peters Dries Vermeulen July 10, 2018 Abstract We consider voting correspondences that are, besides Condorcet Consistent, immune

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

3 Tournament Solutions

3 Tournament Solutions 3 Tournament Solutions Felix Brandt a, Markus Brill b, and Paul Harrenstein c 3.1 Introduction Perhaps one of the most natural ways to aggregate binary preferences from individual agents to a group of

More information

Minimal Retentive Sets in Tournaments

Minimal Retentive Sets in Tournaments Minimal Retentive Sets in Tournaments From Anywhere to TEQ Felix Brandt Markus Brill Felix Fischer Paul Harrenstein Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München Estoril, April 12, 2010 1 / 17 The Trouble with

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Comparing impossibility theorems

Comparing impossibility theorems Comparing impossibility theorems Randy Calvert, for Pol Sci 507 Spr 2017 All references to A-S & B are to Austen-Smith and Banks (1999). Basic notation X set of alternatives X set of all nonempty subsets

More information

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Social Choice Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Summer term 2017 Version: March 15, 2018 CONTENTS Remarks 1 0 Introduction 2 1 The Case of 2 Alternatives 3 1.1 Examples for social choice rules............................

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Participation Incentives in Randomized Social Choice

Participation Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Participation Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Haris Aziz Data61 and UNSW, Sydney, Australia arxiv:1602.02174v2 [cs.gt] 8 Nov 2016 Abstract When aggregating preferences of agents via voting, two

More information

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes Stanford University ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit/lmh Fall, 2008 :, 1 The Voting Problem Given a (finite) set X of candidates and a (finite) set A of voters each of

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Universal Pareto Dominance and Welfare for Plausible Utility Functions

Universal Pareto Dominance and Welfare for Plausible Utility Functions Universal Pareto Dominance and Welfare for Plausible Utility Functions Haris Aziz NICTA and UNSW Sydney, Australia haris.aziz@nicta.com.au Florian Brandl TU München Munich, Germany brandlfl@in.tum.de Felix

More information

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Arunava Sen and Huaxia Zeng September 2014 Paper No. 13-2014 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014 Testing Top Monotonicity Haris Aziz NICTA and UNSW Australia, Kensington 2033, Australia arxiv:1403.7625v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014 Abstract Top monotonicity is a relaxation of various well-known domain restrictions

More information

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division Lecture 12 Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit epacuit@umd.edu October 18, 2012 PHIL 308S: Voting

More information

Mechanism Design without Money

Mechanism Design without Money Mechanism Design without Money MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Sylvia Boicheva (born December 27th, 1986 in Sofia, Bulgaria) under the supervision of Prof Dr Krzysztof Apt, and submitted to the

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 1 May 2017

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 1 May 2017 Rank Maximal Equal Contribution: a Probabilistic Social Choice Function Haris Aziz and Pang Luo and Christine Rizkallah arxiv:1705.00544v1 [cs.gt] 1 May 2017 1 Data61, CSIRO and UNSW, Sydney, NSW 2033,

More information

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary Jerry S. Kelly Syracuse University College of William

More information

Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized

Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized Strategic Manipulability without Resoluteness or Shared Beliefs: Gibbard-Satterthwaite Generalized Christian Geist Project: Modern Classics in Social Choice Theory Institute for Logic, Language and Computation

More information

Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice

Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Technische Universität München Department of Mathematics Master s Thesis Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice Florian Brandl Supervisor: Prof. Felix Brandt Submission Date: September 28,

More information

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives 3.- Social Choice and Welfare Economics 3.1 Arrow s Theorem We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives Let R denote the set of all preference relations

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

PageRank as a Weak Tournament Solution

PageRank as a Weak Tournament Solution PageRank as a Weak Tournament Solution Felix Brandt and Felix Fischer Institut für Informatik, Universität München 80538 München, Germany {brandtf,fischerf}@tcs.ifi.lmu.de Abstract. We observe that ranking

More information

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS Gopakumar Achuthankutty 1 and Souvik Roy 1 1 Economic Research Unit, Indian Statistical Institute, Kolkata Abstract In line with the works

More information

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness T.C.A. Madhav Raghavan 31 July, 2014 Abstract In this note we study group-strategy-proofness, which is the extension of strategy-proofness to groups

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Todd Davies Symbolic Systems Program Stanford University joint work with Raja Shah, Renee Trochet, and Katarina Ling Decision

More information

On the Fixed-Parameter Tractability of Composition-Consistent Tournament Solutions

On the Fixed-Parameter Tractability of Composition-Consistent Tournament Solutions On the Fixed-Parameter Tractability of Composition-Consistent Tournament Solutions Felix Brandt, Markus Brill, and Hans Georg Seedig Abstract Tournament solutions, i.e., functions that associate with each

More information

Random Assignment with Optional Participation

Random Assignment with Optional Participation Random Assignment with Optional Participation Florian Brandl Institut für Informatik TU München, Germany brandlfl@in.tum.de Felix Brandt Institut für Informatik TU München, Germany brandtf@in.tum.de Johannes

More information

Nash implementable domains for the Borda count

Nash implementable domains for the Borda count MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Nash implementable domains for the Borda count Clemens Puppe and Attila Tasnádi 7 November 2006 Online at http://mpraubuni-muenchende/775/ MPRA Paper No 775, posted 10

More information

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof SERIEs (2011) 2:515 527 DOI 101007/s13209-011-0041-z ORIGINAL ARTICLE The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof Arunava Sen Received: 24 November 2010 / Accepted: 10 January

More information

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information by Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30303

More information

Unanimity, Pareto optimality and strategy-proofness on connected domains

Unanimity, Pareto optimality and strategy-proofness on connected domains Unanimity, Pareto optimality and strategy-proofness on connected domains Souvik Roy and Ton Storcken y February 2016 Abstract This is a preliminary version please do not quote 1 Extended Abstract This

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS AN EFFICIENCY CHARACTERIZATION OF PLURALITY SOCIAL CHOICE ON SIMPLE PREFERENCE DOMAINS Biung-Ghi Ju University of Kansas

More information

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park pacuit.org epacuit@umd.edu March 4, 2014 Eric Pacuit 1 Competing desiderata

More information

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems Eiichi Miyagawa Department of Economics, Columbia University 420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027 Email: em437@columbia.edu July 28, 1999

More information

Single-plateaued choice

Single-plateaued choice Single-plateaued choice Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7, Canada walter.bossert@umontreal.ca and Hans Peters

More information

When is manipulation all about the ones and twos?

When is manipulation all about the ones and twos? When is manipulation all about the ones and twos? Samson Alva University of Texas at San Antonio samson.alva@gmail.com December 5, 2017 Abstract A rule is pairwise strategy-proof if groups of size one

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 2 Jan 2012

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 2 Jan 2012 Testing Substitutability of Weak Preferences Haris Aziz, Markus Brill, Paul Harrenstein Institut für Informatik, Technische Universität München, 85748 Garching bei München, Germany arxiv:1201.0432v1 [cs.gt]

More information

Worst-case mechanism design with undominated strategies

Worst-case mechanism design with undominated strategies Worst-case mechanism design with undominated strategies Takuro Yamashita April 26, 2009 Abstract We consider a way to evaluate mechanisms without assuming mutual knowledge of rationality among the agents.

More information

Strategy proofness and unanimity in private good economies with single-peaked preferences

Strategy proofness and unanimity in private good economies with single-peaked preferences MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Strategy proofness and unanimity in private good economies with single-peaked preferences Mostapha Diss and Ahmed Doghmi and Abdelmonaim Tlidi University of Lyon, Lyon,

More information

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Miho Hong Jaeok Park December 17, 2017 Abstract In this paper, we incorporate externalities into Shapley-Scarf housing markets.

More information

Ordinal Bayesian Incentive Compatibility in Restricted Domains

Ordinal Bayesian Incentive Compatibility in Restricted Domains Ordinal Bayesian Incentive Compatibility in Restricted Domains Debasis Mishra October 12, 2015 Abstract We study deterministic voting mechanisms by considering an ordinal notion of Bayesian incentive compatibility

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Soumyarup Sadhukhan, Ton Storcken

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Soumyarup Sadhukhan, Ton Storcken Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Soumyarup Sadhukhan, Ton Storcken An Extreme Point Characterization of Strategyproof and Unanimous Probabilistic Rules over Binary Restricted Domains RM/16/012 An Extreme Point

More information

Separable Discrete Preferences

Separable Discrete Preferences Separable Discrete Preferences W. James Bradley Department of Mathematics and Statistics Calvin College Grand Rapids, MI 49546 USA Jonathan K. Hodge Department of Mathematics Grand Valley State University

More information

Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice. Abstract. Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University

Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice. Abstract. Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University Efficiency and converse reduction-consistency in collective choice Yan-An Hwang Department of Applied Mathematics, National Dong Hwa University Chun-Hsien Yeh Department of Economics, National Central

More information

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice *

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * by Nick Baigent Institute of Public Economics, Graz University nicholas.baigent@kfunigraz.ac.at Fax: +44 316 3809530

More information

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective.

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective. TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective Author(s) Sakamoto, Norihito Citation Issue 2011-08 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/19289 Right Hitotsubashi University

More information

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Conal Duddy, Nicolas Houy, Jérôme Lang, Ashley Piggins, and William S. Zwicker February 22, 2014 1 What is a Social Dichotomy Function? A dichotomy A = (A

More information

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary Klaus Nehring University of California, Davis October 2002 Abstract Arrow s Impossibility Theorem is derived from a general theorem on social aggregation in property spaces.

More information

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD JOHN P DICKERSON Lecture #21 11/8/2016 CMSC828M Tuesdays & Thursdays 12:30pm 1:45pm IMPOSSIBILITY RESULTS IN VOTING THEORY / SOCIAL CHOICE Thanks to: Tuomas Sandholm

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

A Computational Analysis of the Tournament Equilibrium Set

A Computational Analysis of the Tournament Equilibrium Set Draft August 10, 2009. manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) A Computational Analysis of the Tournament Equilibrium Set Felix Brandt Felix Fischer Paul Harrenstein Maximilian Mair Received: date

More information

COALITIONALLY STRATEGY-PROOF RULES IN ALLOTMENT ECONOMIES WITH HOMOGENEOUS INDIVISIBLE GOODS

COALITIONALLY STRATEGY-PROOF RULES IN ALLOTMENT ECONOMIES WITH HOMOGENEOUS INDIVISIBLE GOODS Discussion Paper No. 686 COALITIONALLY STRATEGY-PROOF RULES IN ALLOTMENT ECONOMIES WITH HOMOGENEOUS INDIVISIBLE GOODS Kentaro Hatsumi and Shigehiro Serizawa March 2007 Revised July 2008 Revised February

More information

Robust mechanism design and dominant strategy voting rules

Robust mechanism design and dominant strategy voting rules Theoretical Economics 9 (2014), 339 360 1555-7561/20140339 Robust mechanism design and dominant strategy voting rules Tilman Börgers Department of Economics, University of Michigan Doug Smith Federal Trade

More information

Computing the Minimal Covering Set

Computing the Minimal Covering Set Computing the Minimal Covering Set Felix Brandt Felix Fischer Institut für Informatik, Universität München Oettingenstr. 67, 80538 München, Germany Abstract We present the first polynomial-time algorithm

More information

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Klaus Nehring Clemens Puppe January 2017 **** Preliminary Version ***** Not to be quoted without permission from the

More information

The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets

The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets The Complexity of Computing Minimal Unidirectional Covering Sets Dorothea Baumeister 1, Felix Brandt 2, Felix Fischer 3, Jan Hoffmann 2, and Jörg Rothe 1 1 Institut für Informatik, Heinrich-Heine-Universität

More information

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games Florian Brandl Technische Universität München brandlfl@in.tum.de Given a skew-symmetric matrix, the corresponding two-player symmetric

More information

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Remzi Sanver and Arunava Sen May 2010 Paper No. 07-2010 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE AUTHOR(S) AND

More information

On Popular Random Assignments

On Popular Random Assignments On Popular Random Assignments Haris Aziz, Felix Brandt, and Paul Stursberg 1 NICTA and University of New South Wales, Sydney, NSW 2033, Australia haris.aziz@nicta.com.au 2 Institut für Informatik, Technische

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic Renou No 902 WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic

More information

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible Bettina Klaus October 2005 Abstract We consider the generalization of Shapley and Scarf s (1974) model of

More information

Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems

Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems Çağatay Kayı and Eve Ramaekers For updated version: http://troi.cc.rochester.edu/ ckyi/kr2006.pdf This

More information

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain College of William and Mary W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2008 Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain Lauren Nicole Merrill College of William

More information

Rules for Aggregating Information

Rules for Aggregating Information Rules for Aggregating Information Christopher P. Chambers and Alan D. Miller May 1, 2010 Abstract We present a model of information aggregation in which agents information is represented through partitions

More information

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives Economic Theory 26, 607 617 (2005) DOI: 10.1007/s00199-004-059-8 Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives Frederick H. Chen and Jac C. Heckelman Department of Economics,

More information

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Ioannis Caragiannis RACTI & Department of Computer Engineering and Informatics University of Patras, Greece caragian@ceid.upatras.gr

More information