For a xed value of, we will prove that there are some simple constraints on the triple of cardinals (b(); d(); 2 ). We will also prove that any triple

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "For a xed value of, we will prove that there are some simple constraints on the triple of cardinals (b(); d(); 2 ). We will also prove that any triple"

Transcription

1 Cardinal invariants above the continuum James Cummings Hebrew University of Jerusalem Saharon Shelah Hebrew University of Jerusalem y February 25, 1998 Abstract We prove some consistency results about b() and d(), which are natural generalisations of the cardinal invariants of the continuum b and d. We also dene invariants b cl() and d cl(), and prove that almost always b() = b cl() and d() = d cl() 1 Introduction The cardinal invariants of the continuum have been extensively studied. They are cardinals, typically between! 1 and 2!, whose values give structural information about!!. The survey paper [2] contains a wealth of information about these cardinals. In this paper we study some natural generalisations to higher cardinals. Specically, for regular, we dene cardinals b() and d() which generalise the well-known invariants of the continuum b and d. Supported by a Postdoctoral Fellowship at the Hebrew University. y Partially supported by the Basic Research Fund of the Israel Academy of Science. Paper number

2 For a xed value of, we will prove that there are some simple constraints on the triple of cardinals (b(); d(); 2 ). We will also prove that any triple of cardinals obeying these constraints can be realised. We will then prove that there is essentially no correlation between the values of the triple (b(); d(); 2 ) for dierent values of, except the obvious one that 7! 2 is non-decreasing. This generalises Easton's celebrated theorem (see [3]) on the possible behaviours of 7! 2 ; since his model was built using Cohen forcing, one can show that in that model b() = + and d() = 2 for every. b() and d() are dened using the co-bounded lter on, and for >! we can replace the co-bounded lter by the club lter to get invariants b cl() and d cl(). We nish the paper by proving that these invariants are essentially the same as those dened using the co-bounded lter. Some investigations have been made into generalising the other cardinal invariants of the continuum, for example in [7] Zapletal considers s() which is a generalised version of the splitting number s. His work has a dierent avour to ours, since getting s() > + needs large cardinals. We are indebted to the referee and Jindrich Zapletal for pointing out a serious problem with the rst version of this paper. 2 Denitions and elementary facts It will be convenient to dene the notions of \bounding number" and \dominating number" in quite a general setting. To avoid some trivialities, all partial orderings P mentioned in this paper (with the exception of the notions of forcing) will be assumed to have the property that 8p 2 P 9q 2 P p < P q. Denition 1: Let P be a partial ordering. Then U P is unbounded if and only if 8p 2 P 9q 2 U q P p. D P is dominating if and only if 8p 2 P 9q 2 D p P q. b(p) is the least cardinality of an unbounded subset of P. 2

3 d(p) is the least cardinality of a dominating subset of P. The next lemma collects a few elementary facts about the cardinals b(p) and d(p). Lemma 1: Let P be a partial ordering, and suppose that = b(p) and = d(p) are innite. Then = cf() cf() jpj: Proof: To show that is regular, suppose for a contradiction that cf() <. Let B be an unbounded family of cardinality, and write B = S <cf() B with jb j <. For each nd p such that 8p 2 B p p, then nd q such that 8 < cf() p q. Then 8p 2 B p q, contradicting the assumption that B was unbounded. Similarly, suppose that cf() <. Let D be dominating with cardinality and write D = S <cf() D where jd j <. For each nd p such that 8p 2 D p p, and then nd q such that 8 < cf() p q. Then 8p 2 D q p, contradicting the assumption that D was dominating. The next result shows that we cannot hope to say much more. Lemma 2: Let and be innite cardinals with = cf() and < =. Dene a partial ordering P = P(; ) in the following way; the underlying set is [] <, and (; x) (; y) if and only if and x y. Then b(p) = and d(p) =. Proof: Let B P be unbounded. If jbj < then we can dene = sup f j 9y (; y) 2 B g < ; x = [ f y j 9 (; y) 2 B g 2 [] < : But then (; x) is a bound for B, so jbj and hence b(p). On the other hand the set f (; ;) j < g is clearly unbounded, so that b(p) =. 3

4 Let D P be dominating. If jdj < then S f y j 9 (; y) 2 D g 6=, and this is impossible, so that d(p). On the other hand GCH holds and cf(), so that jpj = < =. Hence d(p) =. Denition 2: Let P, Q be posets and f : P! Q a function. f embeds P conally into Q if and only if 8p; p 0 2 P p P p 0 () f(p) Q f(p 0 ). 8q 2 Q 9p 2 P q Q f(p). That is, rge(f) is dominating. Lemma 3: If f : P! Q embeds P conally into Q then b(p) = b(q) and d(p) = d(q). Proof: Easy. Lemma 4: Let P be any partial ordering. Then there is P P such that P is a dominating subset of P and P is well-founded. Proof: We enumerate P recursively. Suppose that we have already enumerated elements hb : < i into P. If f b j < g is dominating then we stop, otherwise we choose b so that b b for all <. Clearly the construction stops and enumerates a dominating subset P of P. To see that P is well-founded observe that b < b =) <. Notice that the identity embeds P conally in P, so b(p ) = b(p) and d(p ) = d(p). We also need some information about the preservation of b(p) and d(p) by forcing. Lemma 5: Let P be a partial ordering with b(p) =, d(p) =. 4

5 Let V [G] be a generic extension of V such that every set of ordinals of size less than in V [G] is covered by a set of size less than in V. Then V [G] b(p) =. Let V [G] be a generic extension of V such that every set of ordinals of size less than in V [G] is covered by a set of size less than in V. Then V [G] d(p) =. Proof: We do the rst part, the second is very similar. The hypothesis implies that is a cardinal in V [G], and since \B is unbounded" is upwards absolute from V to V [G] it is clear that V [G] b(p). Suppose for a contradiction that we have C in V [G] unbounded with V [G] jcj <. By our hypothesis there is D 2 V such that C D and V jdj <, but now D is unbounded contradicting the denition of. With these preliminaries out of the way, we can dene the cardinals which will concern us in this paper. Denition 3: Let be a regular cardinal. 1. If f; g 2 then f < g i 9 < 8 > f() < g(). 2. b() = def b(( ; < )). 3. d() = def d(( ; < )). These are dened by analogy with some \cardinal invariants of the continuum" (for a reference on cardinal invariants see [2]) known as b and d. In our notation b = b(!) and d = d(!). Lemma 6: If is regular then + b(). b() = cf(b()). b() cf(d()). 5

6 d() 2. cf(2 ) >. Proof: The rst claim follows from the following trivial fact. Fact 1: Let f f j < g. Then there is a function f 2 such that 8 < f < f. Proof: Dene f() = sup f f () + 1 j < g. < <. Then f() > f () for The next three claims follow easily from our general results on b(p) and d(p), and the last is just Konig's well-known theorem on cardinal exponentiation. We will prove that these are essentially the only restrictions provable in ZFC. One could view this as a renement of Easton's classical result (see [3]) on 7! 2. 3 Hechler forcing In this section we show how to force that certain posets can be conally embedded in ( ; < ). This is a straightforward generalisation of Hechler's work in [4], where he treats the case =!. We start with a brief review of our forcing notation. p q means that p is stronger than q, a -closed forcing notion is one in which every decreasing chain of length less than has a lower bound, and a -dense forcing notion is one in which every sequence of dense open sets of length less than has non-empty intersection. If x is an ordered pair then x 0 will denote the rst component of x and x 1 the second component. 6

7 Denition 4: Let be regular. D () is the notion of forcing whose conditions are pairs (s; F ) with s 2 < and F 2, ordered as follows; (s; F ) (t; F 0 ) if and only if 1. dom(t) dom(s) and t = s dom(t). 2. s() F 0 () for dom(t) < dom(s). 3. F () F 0 () for all. We will think of a generic lter G as adding a function f G :! given by f G = S f s j 9F (s; F ) 2 G g. It is easy to see that G = f (t; F ) j t = f G dom(t); dom(t) =) F () f G () g; so that V [f G ] = V [G] and we can talk about functions from to being D ()-generic. Lemma 7: Let < =, and set P = D (). Then 1. P is -closed. 2. P is + -c.c. 3. If g :! is P-generic over V then 8f 2 \ V f < g. Proof: 1. Let < and suppose that h(t ; F ) : < i S is a descending - sequence of conditions from P. Dening t = f t j < g and F : 7! sup f F () j < g, it is easy to see that (t; F ) is a lower bound for the sequence. 2. Observe that if (s; F ) and (s; F 0 ) are two conditions with the same rst component then they are compatible, because if H : 7! F ()[F 0 () the condition (s; H) is a common lower bound. There are only < = possible rst components, so that P clearly has the + -c.c. 7

8 3. Let f 2 \ V, and let (t; F ) be an arbitrary condition. Let us dene F 0 : 7! (F () [ f()) + 1, then (t; F 0 ) renes (t; F ) and forces that f() < f G () for all dom(t). If = cf() > = < then it is straightforward to iterate D () with < -support for steps and get a model where b() = d() =. Getting a model where b() < d() is a little harder, but we can do it by a \nonlinear iteration" which will embed a well chosen poset conally into ( ; < ). Theorem 1: Let = <, and suppose that Q is any well-founded poset with b(q) +. Then there is a forcing D (; Q ) such that 1. D (; Q ) is -closed and + -c.c. 2. V D(;Q) Q can be conally embedded into ( ; < ) 3. If V b(q) = then V D(;Q) b() =. 4. If V d(q) = then V D(;Q) d() =. Proof: We will dene the conditions and ordering for D (; Q ) by induction on Q. The idea is to iterate D () \along Q" so as to get a conal embedding of Q into. It will be convenient to dene a new poset Q + which consists of Q together with a new element top which is greater than all the elements of Q. We will dene for each a 2 Q + a notion of forcing P a. If a 2 Q + then we will denote f c 2 Q j c < a g by Q=a. It will follow from the denition that if c < a then P c is a complete subordering of P a, and that the map p 2 P a 7! p Q=c is a projection from P a to P c. Suppose that for all b < Q a we have already dened P b. 1. p is a condition in P a if and only if (a) p is a function, dom(p) Q=a and jdom(p)j <. 8

9 (b) For all b 2 dom(p), p(b) = (t; F _ ) where t 2 < and F_ is a P b -name for a member of. 2. If p; q 2 P a then p q if and only if (a) dom(q) dom(p). (b) For all b 2 dom(q), if p(b) = (s; _H) and q(b) = (t; _ I) then i. t = s dom(t). ii. p (Q=b) Pb dom(t) < dom(s) =) s() > I(). _ iii. p (Q=b) Pb 8 _H() I(). _ We dene D (; Q ) = P top, and verify that this forcing does what we claimed. The verication is broken up into a series of claims. Claim 1: D (; Q ) is -closed. Proof: Let < and let hp : < i be a descending -sequence S of conditions. We will dene a new condition p with dom(p) = dom(p ). For each b 2 dom(p ) let p (b) = (t (b); F_ (b)). Let p(b) = (t; F _ S ) where t = f t (b) j b 2 dom(p ) g and F _ (b) is a P b - name for the pointwise supremum of f F_ (b) j b 2 dom(p ) g. Then it it is easy to check that p is a condition and is a lower bound for hp : < i Claim 2: D (; Q ) is + -c.c. Proof: Let hp : < + i be a family of conditions. Since = < we may assume that the domains form a -system with root r. We may also assume that for b 2 r, p (b) = (t b ; F (b)) where t b is independent of. It is now easy to see that any two conditions in the family are compatible. 9

10 Claim 3: If c < a then P c is a complete subordering of P a, and the map p 7! p Q=c is a projection from P a to P c. Proof: This is routine. If G is D (; Q )-generic, then for each a 2 Q we can dene f a G 2 \ V [G] by f a G = S f t(a) 0 j t 2 G g. It is these functions that will give us a conal embedding of Q into ( \ V [G]; < ), via the map a 7! f a G. Claim 4: If a < Q b then f a G < f b G. Proof: Let p be a condition and let F_ be the canonical P b -name for fg. a Rene p to q in the following way; q(c) = p(c) for c 6= b, and if p(b) = (t; _H) then q(b) = (t; I) _ where I _ names the pointwise maximum of F_ and _H. Then q forces that fg() b is greater than fg() a for dom(t). Notice that by the same proof f b G dominates every function in V Pa. Claim 5: If a Q b then f a G f b G. Proof: If b < Q a then we showed in the last claim that fg b < fg, a so we may assume without loss of generality that b Q a. Let p be a condition and let <. Choose large enough that fdom(p(a) 0 ); dom(p(b) 0 ); g. Let p(b) = (t; F _ ), and nd q 2 P b such that q p (Q=b) and q decides F _ ( + 1). Let p 1 be the condition such that p 1 (c) = p(c) if c Q b and p 1 (c) = q(c) if c < Q b. Then p 1 renes p and p 1 (a) = p(a), p 1 (b) = p(b). Let p(a) = (s; _H). Find r 2 P a such that r p 1 (Q=a) and r decides _H ( + 1). Let p 2 be the condition such that p 2 (c) = p 1 (c) if c Q a and p 2 (c) = r(c) if c < Q a. Then p 2 renes p 1 and p 2 (a) = p(a), p 2 (b) = p(b). 10

11 Now it is easy to extend p 2 to a condition which forces f a G() > f b G(). Claim 6: The map a 7! f a G embeds Q conally into ( ; < ) in the generic extension by D (; Q ). Proof: We have already checked that the map is order-preserving. It remains to be seen that its range is dominating. Let G be D (; Q )-generic and let f 2 \ V [G]. Then f = ( f) _ G for some canonical name f, _ and by the + -c.c. we may assume that there is X Q such that jxj = and f _ only involves conditions p with dom(p) X. Now b(q) + so that we can nd a 2 Q with X Q=a. This implies that f _ is a P a -name for a function in, so that f < f a G and we are done. Claim 7: If V b(q) = then V D(;Q) b() =. Proof: Let G be D (; Q )-generic. By lemma 3 it will suce to show that V [G] b(q) =. This follows from lemma 5, the fact that D (; Q ) is + - c.c. and the assumption that b(q) +. Claim 8: If V d(q) = then V D(;Q) d() =. Proof: Exactly like the last claim. This nishes the proof of Theorem 1. 11

12 4 Controlling the invariants at a xed cardinal In this section we show how to force that the triple (b(); d(); 2 ) can be anything \reasonable" for a xed value of. Theorem 2: Let = < and let GCH hold at all cardinals. Let ; ; be cardinals such that + = cf() cf(), and cf() >. Then there is a forcing M (; ; ; ) such that in the generic extension b() =, d() = and 2 =. Proof: In V dene Q = P(; ), as in lemma 2. We know that V b(q) = and V d(q) =. Fix Q a conal wellfounded subset of Q, and then dene a new well-founded poset R as follows. Denition 5: The elements of R are pairs (p; i) where either i = 0 and p 2 or i = 1 and p 2 Q. (p; i) (q; j) i i = j = 0 and p q in, i = j = 1 and p q in Q, or i = 0 and j = 1. Now we set M (; ; ; ) = D (; R). It is routine to use the closure and chain condition to argue that M makes 2 =. Since R contains a conal copy of Q, it is also easy to see that M forces b() = and d() =. 5 A rst attempt at the main theorem We now aim to put together the basic modules as described in the previous section, so as to control the function 7! (b(); d(); 2 ) for all regular. A naive rst attempt would be to imitate Easton's construction from [3]; this almost works, and will lead us towards the right construction. Let us briey recall the statement and proof of Easton's theorem on the behaviour of 7! 2. 12

13 Lemma 8 (Easton's lemma): If P is -c.c. and Q is -closed then P is - c.c. in V Q and Q is -dense in V P. In particular < ON \V PQ = < ON \V P. Theorem 3 (Easton's theorem): Let F : REG! CARD be a class function such that cf(f ()) > and < =) F () F (). Let GCH hold. Then there is a class forcing P which preserves cardinals and conalities, such that in the extension 2 = F () for all regular. Proof:[Sketch] The \basic module" is P() = Add(; F ()). P is the \Easton product" of the P(), to be more precise p 2 P i 1. p is a function with dom(p) REG and p() 2 P() for all 2 dom(p). 2. For all inaccessible, dom(p) \ is bounded in. P is ordered by pointwise renement. There are certain complications arising from the fact that we are doing class forcing; we ignore them in this sketch. If is regular then we may factor P as P < P() P > in the obvious way. P is always -closed. It follows from GCH and the -system lemma that if is Mahlo or the successor of a regular cardinal then P < is -c.c. On the other hand, if is a non-mahlo inaccessible or the successor of a singular cardinal, then P < is in general only + -c.c. In particular for regular P = P < + is always + -c.c. so that by Easton's lemma ON \ V P = ON \ V P. This implies that in the end we have only added F () many subsets of. It remains to be seen that cardinals and conalities are preserved. It will suce to show that regular cardinals remain regular. If is Mahlo or the successor of a regular cardinal, then Easton's lemma implies that < ON \ V P = < ON \ V P<, and since is regular in V P< (by -c.c.) is clearly regular in V P. Now suppose that = + for singular. If becomes singular in V P let its new conality be, where we see that < and is regular in V. ON \ V P = ON \ V P, so that will have conality in V P. This is 13

14 absurd as P is + -c.c. and + < <. A very similar argument will work in case is a non-mahlo inaccessible. Suppose that we replace Add(; F ()) by P() = M (; (); (); ()), where 7! ((); (); ()) is a function obeying the constraints given by Lemma 6. Let P be the Easton product of the P(). Then exactly as in the proof of Easton's theorem it will follow that P preserves cardinals and conalities, and that 2 = () in V P. Lemma 9: If is inaccessible or the successor of a regular cardinal then b() = (), d() = () and 2 = () in V P. Proof: For any, \ V P = \ V P. b() and d() have the right values in V P() by design, and these values are not changed by -c.c. forcing. So assuming P < is -c.c. those invariants have the right values in V P, and hence in V P. We need some way of coping with the successors of singular cardinals and the non-mahlo inaccessibles. Zapletal pointed out that at the rst inaccessible in an Easton iteration we are certain to add many Cohen subsets, so that there really is a need to modify the construction. 6 Tail forcing Easton's forcing to control 7! 2 can be seen as a kind of iterated forcing in which we choose each iterand from the ground model, or equivalently as a kind of product forcing. Silver's \Reverse Easton forcing" is an iteration in which the iterand at is dened in V P. The \tail forcing" which we describe here is a sort of hybrid. We follow the conventions of Baumgartner's paper [1] in our treatment of iterated forcing, except that when have _ Q 2 V P and form P _ Q we reserve the 14

15 right not to take all P-names for members of Q (as long as we take enough names that the set of their denotations is forced to be dense). For example if Q 2 V we will only take names ^q for q 2 Q, so P ^Q will just be P Q. We will describe a kind of iteration which we call \Easton tail iteration" in which at successor stages we choose iterands from V, but at limit stage we choose Q _ in a dierent way; possibly Q =2 V, but we will arrange things so that the generic G factors at many places below and any nal segment of G essentially determines Q. This idea comes from Magidor and Shelah's paper [5]. We assume for simplicity that in the ground model all limit cardinals are singular or inaccessible. In the application that we intend this is no restriction, as the ground model will obey GCH. Denition 6: A forcing iteration P Easton tail iteration i with iterands h _ Q : + 1 < i is an 1. The iteration has Easton support, that is to say a direct limit is taken at inaccessible limit stages and an inverse limit elsewhere. 2. _Q = 0 unless is a regular cardinal. 3. If is the successor of a regular cardinal then Q 2 V. 4. For all regular, P +1 is + -c.c. 5. For a limit cardinal P is ++ -c.c. if is singular, and + -c.c. if is inaccessible. 6. For all regular with + 1 < there exists an iteration P dense in P such that P +1 = P +1, and for with + 1 < (a) P factors as P +1 P ( + 1; ). (b) If is inaccessible or the successor of a singular, and p 2 P, then p() is a name depending only on P ( + 1; ). (c) P ( + 1; ) is + -closed. 15

16 Clause 6 is of course the interesting one. It holds in a trivial way if P is just a product with Easton supports. Clauses 6a and 6b should really be read together, as the factorisation in 6a only makes sense because 6b already applies to <, and conversely 6b only makes sense once we have the factorisation from 6a. The following result shows that Easton tail iterations do not disturb the universe too much. Lemma 10: Let P be an Easton tail iteration. Then 1. For all regular <, ON \ V P = ON \ V P P preserves all cardinals and conalities. Proof: Exactly like Theorem 3. In the next section we will see how to dene a non-trivial Easton tail iteration. If + is the successor of a regular then it will suce to choose Q + 2 V as any + -closed and ++ -c.c. forcing. The interesting (dicult) stages are the ones where we have to cope with the other sorts of regular cardinal, here we will have to maintain the hypotheses on the chain condition and factorisation properties of the iteration. It turns out that slightly dierent strategies are appropriate for inaccessibles and successors of singulars. 7 The main theorem Theorem 4: Let GCH hold. Let 7! ((); (); ()) be a class function from REG to CARD 3, with + () = cf(()) cf(()) () () and cf(()) > for all. Then there exists a class forcing P 1, preserving all cardinals and conalities, such that in the generic extension b() = (), d() = () and 2 = () for all. 16

17 Proof: We will dene by induction on a sequence of Easton tail iterations P, and then let take a direct limit to get a class forcing P 1. The proof that P 1 has the desired properties is exactly as in [3], so we will concentrate on dening the P. As we dene the P we will also dene dense subsets P intended to witness clause 6 in the denition of an Easton tail iteration. Much of the combinatorics in this section is very similar to that in Section 3. Accordingly we have only sketched the proofs of some of the technical assertions about closure and chain conditions. The easiest case to cope with is that where we are looking at the successor of a regular cardinal. So let be regular and assume that we have dened P + (which is equivalent to P +1 since we do trivial forcing at all points between and + ), and P (which is equivalent to P +1) for all. + Denition 7: Q + = M ( + ; ( + ); ( + ); ( + )) as dened in Section 4. P + +1 = P + Q +, and P + +1 = P + Q + for. It is now easy to check that this denition maintains the conditions for being an Easton tail iteration. Since P + is + -c.c. and we know that + + \ V P1 = + + \ V P + +1, we will get the desired behaviour at + in V P1. Next we consider the case of a cardinal +, where is singular. Suppose we have dened P + (that is P ) and P appropriately. Let R be a + well-founded poset of cardinality () with b(r) = () and d(r) = (), as dened in Section 4. Let R + be R with the addition of a maximal element top. We will dene P + Q _ a by induction on a 2 R +, and then set P + +1 = P + Q _ top. In the induction we will maintain the hypothesis that, for each <, P Q _ + a can be factored as P +1 (P ( + 1; + ) Q _ a ). Let us now x a, and suppose that we have dened P + Q _ b for all b below a in R +. Denition 8: Let b < a, and let _ be a for a function from + to +. Then _ is symmetric i for all <, whenever G 0 G 1 and G 0 0 G 1 are two generics for P +1 (P ( + 1; + ) Q b ), then _ G 0G 1 = _ G0 0 G 1. 17

18 Of course the (technically illegal) quantication over generic objects in this denition can be removed using the truth lemma, to see that the collection of symmetric names really is a set in V. Denition 9: (p; q) is a condition in P + _Q a i 1. p 2 P q is a function, dom(q) R + =a and jdom(q)j. 3. For each b 2 dom(q), q(b) is a pair (s; F _ ) where s 2 <+ + and F_ is a symmetric P + Q _ b -name for a function from + to +. Denition 10: Let (p; q) and (p 0 ; q 0 ) be conditions in P + _Q a. (p 0 ; q 0 ) renes (p; q) i 1. p 0 renes p in P dom(q) dom(q 0 ). 3. For each b 2 dom(q), if we let q(b) = (s; F ) and q(b 0 ) = (s 0 ; F 0 ), then (a) s 0 extends s. (b) If 2 lh(s 0 ) lh(s) then (p 0 ; q 0 (R + =b)) s 0 () F (). (c) For all, (p 0 ; q 0 (R + =b)) F 0 () F (). Denition 11: We dene P + +1 as P + _ Q top. If < then we dene P + +1 as P + _ Q top. It is now routine to check that this denition satises the chain condition and factorisation demands from Denition 6. The chain condition argument works because 2 = +, and any incompatibility in Q top is caused by a disagreement in the rst coordinate at some b 2 R. The factorisation condition (clause 6a) holds because symmetric names can be computed using any nal segment of the P -generic, and the closure condition (clause 6c) follows from the fact that the canonical name for the pointwise sup of a series of functions with symmetric names is itself a symmetric name. Now we check that we have achieved the desired eect on the values of b( + ) and d( + ). 18

19 Lemma 11: The function added by P + Q _ top at b 2 R + eventually dominates all functions in + + \ V P + Q _ b. Proof: It suces to show that if F_ is a P + Q _ b -name for a function from + to + then there is a symmetric name F_ 0 such that 8 F () F 0 (). For each regular < we factor P + Q _ b as P +1 (P (+1; + ) Q _ b ). In V P (+1; + ) Q _ b we may treat F_ as a P +1 -name and dene G () = sup(f j 9p 2 P +1 p _ F () = g): Notice that we may also treat G as a P + Q _ b -name, and that if < then G G. Now let F 0 be the canonical name for a function such that 8 F 0 () = sup < G (), then it is easy to see that F 0 is a symmetric name for a function from + to + and that 8 F () F 0 (). Lemma 12: In V P + +1 there is a copy of R embedded conally into + +. Proof: Let f _ name a function from + to + in V P As P + +1 has the ++ -c.c. we may assume that f _ only depends on + many coordinates in R, and hence (since b(r) = ( + ) ++ ) that f _ is a P + Q _ b -name for some b 2 R. By the preceding lemma the function which is added at coordinate b will dominate f. _ It remains to be seen what we should do for inaccessible. The construction is very similar to that for successors of singulars, with the important dierence that we need to work with a larger class of names for functions in order to guarantee that we dominate everything that we ought to. This in turn leads to a slight complication in the denition of P. Suppose that we have dened P and P appropriately. Let R be a poset with the appropriate properties (jrj = (), b(r) = (), d(r) = ()) and let R + be R with a maximal element called top adjoined. As before we dene P Q _ a by induction on a 2 R +. In the induction we will maintain 19

20 the hypothesis that for each < there is a dense subset of P _ Q a which factorises as P +1 (P ( + 1; ) _ Q a ). Let us x a, and suppose that we have dened everything for all b below a. Denition 12: (p; (; q)) is a condition in P _Q a i 1. p 2 P. 2. <, is regular. 3. q is a function, dom(q) R + =a and jdom(q)j <. 4. For each b 2 dom(q), q(b) is a pair (s; F _ ) where s 2 <+ + and F_ is a P ( + 1; ) Q _ b -name for a function from + to +. Denition 13: Let (p; (; q)) and (p 0 ; ( 0 ; q 0 )) be conditions in P + _Q a. (p 0 ; ( 0 ; q 0 )) renes (p; (; q)) i 1. p 0 renes p in P dom(q) dom(q 0 ) For each b 2 dom(q), if we let q(b) = (s; F ) and q(b 0 ) = (s 0 ; F 0 ), then (a) s 0 extends s. (b) If 2 lh(s 0 ) lh(s) then (p 0 ; q 0 (R + =b)) s 0 () F (). (c) For all, (p 0 ; q 0 (R + =b)) F 0 () F (). Notice that since any P _ Q b -generic induces a P (+1; ) _ Q b -generic, there is a natural interpretation of any P (+1; ) _ Q b -name as a P _ Q b - name. We are using this fact implicitly when we dene the ordering on the conditions. We need to maintain the hypothesis on factorising the forcing, so we make the following denition. 20

21 Denition 14: Let be regular with <. P +1 (P ( + 1; ) _ Q a ) is dened as the set of (p 0 ; (p 1 ; (; q))) such that p 0 2 P +1, p 1 2 P ( + 1; ) and (p 0 _ p 1 ; (; q)) 2 P _ Q a with. The key point here is that the factorisation makes sense, because for such a condition q(b) depends only on P ( + 1; ) _ Q b. Denition 15: We dene P +1 as P _ Q top, and P +1 as P _ Q top, As in the case of a successor of a singular, it is straightforward to see that we have satised the chain condition and factorisation conditions. To nish the proof we need to check that the forcing at has achieved the right eect, which will be clear exactly as in the singular case when we have proved the following lemma. Lemma 13: The function added by P _ Q top at b 2 R eventually dominates all functions in \ V P _ Q b. Proof: We do a density argument. Suppose that f_ names a function in \ V P Q _ b, and let (p; (; q)) be a condition in P _Q top. We factor P Q _ b as P +1 (P ( + 1; ) Q _ b ), and use the fact that P +1 has + -c.c. in V P (+1;) Q _ b to nd a P ( + 1; ) Q _ b -name _g such that 8 f() g(). Now we can rene (p; (; q)) in the natural way by strengthening the second component of q(b) to dominate _g. This gives a condition which forces that the function added at b will eventually dominate f. _ This concludes the proof of Theorem 4. 21

22 8 Variations In this appendix we discuss the invariants that arise if we work with the club lter in place of the co-bounded lter. It turns out that this does not make too much dierence. All the results here are due to Shelah. Denition 16: Let be regular. 1. Let f; g 2. f< cl g i there is C closed and unbounded in such that 2 C =) f() < g(). 2. b cl() = def b(( ; < cl )). 3. d cl() = def d(( ; < cl )). Theorem 5: d cl() d() d cl()!. Proof: If a family of functions is dominating with respect to < it is dominating with respect to < cl, so that d cl() d(). For the converse, let us x D such that D is dominating with respect to < cl and jdj = d cl(). We may assume that every function in D is increasing (replace each f 2 D by f : 7! S f()). Let g 0 2. Dene by induction f n, g n, and C n such that 1. f n 2 D. 2. C n is club in, and 2 C n =) g n () < f n (). 3. C n+1 C n. 4. g n is increasing. 5. g n+1 () > g n () for all. 6. g n+1 () > f n (min(c n ( + 1))) for all. 22

23 T S Now let = min( n<! C n ). We will prove that g 0 () n f n () for >. Fix some >. For each n we know that C n \ 6= ;, so that if we dene n = sup(c n \ ( + 1)) then n is the largest point of C n less than or equal to. Notice that min(c n ( + 1)) = min(c n ( n + 1)). Since C n+1 C n, n+1 n, so that for all suciently large n (say n N) we have n = for some xed. We claim that g 0 () f N +1 (), which we will prove by building a chain of inequalities. Let us dene Then = min(c N ( + 1)) = min(c N ( + 1)): g 0 () g N () g N () < f N () < g N +1 () < f N +1 () f N +1 (); where the key point is that 2 C N +1 and hence g N +1 () < f N +1 (). Now it is easy to manufacture a family of size d cl()! which is dominating with respect to <, so that d() d cl()!. Theorem 6: b cl() = b(). Proof: If a family of functions is unbounded with respect to < cl it is unbounded with respect to <, so that b() b cl(). Suppose for a contradiction that b() < b cl(), and x U 0 such that ju 0 j = b() and U 0 is unbounded with respect to <. We may assume without loss of generality that every function in U 0 is increasing. We perform an inductive construction in! steps, whose aim is to produce a bound for U 0 with respect to <. By assumption U 0 is bounded with respect to < cl, so choose g 0 which bounds it modulo the club lter. Choose also club sets f Cf 0 j f 2 U 0 g such that 2 Cf 0 =) f() < g 0 (). For each f 2 U 0 dene another function f [0] by f [0] : 7! f(min(cf 0 ( + 1))) 23

24 For n 1 dene U n = U n 1 [ f f [n 1] j f 2 U n 1 g. By induction it will follow that ju n j = b(), so that we may choose g n such that g n () > g n 1 () for all and g n bounds U n modulo clubs. We choose clubs f Cf n j f 2 U n g such that 1. 2 C n f =) f() < g n (). 2. If f 2 U n 1, then C n f C n 1 f. 3. If n 2 and f 2 U n 2 then C n f C n 1 f [n 2], where this makes sense because in this case f [n 2] 2 U n 1. For each f 2 U n we dene f [n] : 7! f(min(cf n ( + 1))) to nish round n of the inductive construction. Now we claim that the pointwise sup of the sequence hg n : n <!i is an upper bound T for U 0 with respect to <. Let us x f 2 U 0, and then let = min( Cf n ). We will now give a very similar argument to that of Theorem 5. Fix >. We dene n = sup(c n f \ ( + 1)) and observe that n+1 n, so we may nd N and such that n N =) n =. Let = min(cf N ( + 1)) = min(cf N ( + 1)). We now get a chain of inequalities f() f() = f [N ] () < g N +1 () g N +1 (): This time the key point is that 2 C N +2 f C N +1 f [N], so that f [N ] () < g N +1 (). We have proved that > =) f() S n g n (), so that every function f 2 U 0 is bounded on a nal segment of by 7! S n g n (). This contradicts the choice of U 0 as unbounded with respect to <, so we are done. It is natural to ask whether the rst result can be improved to show that b cl() = b(). This can be done for suciently large, at the cost of using a powerful result from Shelah's paper [6]. 24

25 Denition 17: Let = cf() <. 1. P () = f X j jxj = g. 2. [] is the least cardinality of a family P P () such [ that 8A 2 P () 9B P (jbj < ^ A B): One of the main results of [6] is that ZFC proves a weak form of the GCH. Theorem 7: Let > i!. Then [] = for all suciently large < i!. It is easy to see that if P P is such that 8A 2 P () 9B P (jbj < ^ A [ B); then 8A 2 P () 9C 2 P ja \ Cj =. This is all we use in what follows, and in fact we could get away with 8A 2 P () 9C 2 P ja \ Cj 0. Theorem 8: Let = cf() > i!. Then d() = d cl(). Proof: Let = d cl(). Then > i!, so that we may apply Theorem 7 to nd a regular < i! such that [] =. let us x P P () such that jp j = and 8A 2 P () 9C 2 P ja \ Cj =. Now let D be such that jdj = and D is dominating in ( ; < cl ). We may suppose that D consists of increasing functions. Enumerate D as hh : < i, and then dene h A : 7! S 2A h () for each A 2 P. Since < i!, h A 2. We will prove that f h A j A 2 P g is dominating in ( ; < ). We will do a version of the construction from Theorem 5. Let g 0 2. Dene by induction f, g, and C for <, with the following properties. 1. f 2 D. 2. C is club in, and 2 C =) g () < f (). 3. < =) C C. 25

26 4. g is increasing. 5. If <, then g () > g () for all. 6. If <, then g () > f (min(c ( + 1))) for all. This is easy, because <. By the choice of P we may nd a set A 2 P such that jf h j 2 A g \ f f j < gj =. Enumerate the rst! many such that f 2 f h j 2 A g as h n : n <!i. We may now repeat the proof of Theorem 5 with f n, g n and C n in place of f n, g n and C S n. We nd that for all suciently large we have g 0 () g 0 () n f n (). By S the denition of h A and the fact that f f n j n <! g f h j 2 A g, n f n () h A () for all, so that g 0 < h A. This shows f h A j A 2 P g to be dominating, so we are done. We do not know whether it can ever be the case that d cl() < d(). This is connected with some open and apparently dicult questions in pcf theory. References [1] J. E. Baumgartner, Iterated forcing, Surveys in set theory, (A. Mathias, editor), LMS Lecture Notes 87, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983, pp. 1{59. [2] E. K. van Douwen, The integers and topology, Handbook of Set- Theoretic Topology, (K. Kunen and J. E. Vaughan, editors), North- Holland, Amsterdam, 1984, pp. 111{167. [3] W. Easton, Powers of regular cardinals, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 1 (1964), pp. 139{178. [4] S. Hechler, On the existence of certain conal subsets of!!, Axiomatic Set Theory, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 13 part 26

27 II, American Mathematical Society, Providence, Rhode Island, 1974, pp. 155{173. [5] M. Magidor and S. Shelah, When does almost free imply free?, Journal of the American Mathematical Society (to appear). [6] S. Shelah, The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis revisited, Israel Journal of Mathematics (to appear). [7] J. Zapletal, Splitting number and the core model, (to appear). 27

Cardinal invariants above the continuum

Cardinal invariants above the continuum arxiv:math/9509228v1 [math.lo] 15 Sep 1995 Cardinal invariants above the continuum James Cummings Hebrew University of Jerusalem cummings@math.huji.ac.il Saharon Shelah Hebrew University of Jerusalem shelah@math.huji.ac.il

More information

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (2003) 179 191 www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Milos S. Kurilic Department of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Novi

More information

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

ON REFLECTION OF STATIONARY SETS IN P. The Pennsylvania State University. University Park, PA The Hebrew University

ON REFLECTION OF STATIONARY SETS IN P. The Pennsylvania State University. University Park, PA The Hebrew University ON REFLECTION OF STATIONARY SETS IN P Thomas Jech and Saharon Shelah Department of Mathematics The Pennsylvania State University University Park, PA 16802 Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University

More information

Denition 2: o() is the height of the well-founded relation. Notice that we must have o() (2 ) +. Much is known about the possible behaviours of. For e

Denition 2: o() is the height of the well-founded relation. Notice that we must have o() (2 ) +. Much is known about the possible behaviours of. For e Possible behaviours for the Mitchell ordering James Cummings Math and CS Department Dartmouth College Hanover NH 03755 January 23, 1998 Abstract We use a mixture of forcing and inner models techniques

More information

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new method which combines Prikry forcing with an iteration between the Prikry points. Using our method we prove from

More information

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real Generic Absoluteness Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman Abstract We explore the consistency strength of 3 and 4 absoluteness, for a variety of forcing notions. Introduction Shoeneld's absoluteness theorem

More information

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Successive cardinals with the tree property UCLA March 3, 2014 A classical theorem Theorem (König Infinity Lemma) Every infinite finitely branching tree has an infinite path. Definitions A tree is set T together with an ordering < T which is wellfounded,

More information

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT VERA FISCHER Abstract. In this talk we will consider three properties of iterations with mixed (finite/countable) supports: iterations of arbitrary length preserve ω 1, iterations

More information

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, we construct a model in which there exists an ω 2 -Aronszajn tree, the ω 1 -approachability

More information

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH JIN DU Abstract. Fontanella [2] showed that if κ n : n < ω is an increasing sequence of supercompacts and ν = sup n κ n, then the strong tree property holds

More information

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES P max VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES TETSUYA ISHIU AND PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In his book on P max [6], Woodin presents a collection of partial orders whose extensions satisfy strong

More information

A version of for which ZFC can not predict a single bit Robert M. Solovay May 16, Introduction In [2], Chaitin introd

A version of for which ZFC can not predict a single bit Robert M. Solovay May 16, Introduction In [2], Chaitin introd CDMTCS Research Report Series A Version of for which ZFC can not Predict a Single Bit Robert M. Solovay University of California at Berkeley CDMTCS-104 May 1999 Centre for Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical

More information

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece Is the amalgamation property for L ω1,ω-sentences absolute for transitive models of ZFC? Logic Seminar - UIC 2018 02 01 Ioannis (Yiannis)

More information

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS CAPSTONE MATT LUTHER 1 INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS 2 1. Introduction This paper will summarize many of the ideas from logic and set theory that are

More information

How to Pop a Deep PDA Matters

How to Pop a Deep PDA Matters How to Pop a Deep PDA Matters Peter Leupold Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science Kyoto Sangyo University Kyoto 603-8555, Japan email:leupold@cc.kyoto-su.ac.jp Abstract Deep PDA are push-down automata

More information

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Itay Neeman and Spencer Unger February 28, 2009 1 Introduction These notes are based on results presented by Itay Neeman at the Appalachian Set Theory workshop on February 28,

More information

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Richard Ketchersid Miami University Jindřich Zapletal University of Florida April 17, 2007 Paul Larson Miami University Abstract We isolate a forcing which increases

More information

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω Spencer Unger UCLA October 19, 2013 Outline Combinatorial properties Theorems using supercompactness Bringing results down to ℵ ω Some new theorems A sketch of

More information

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. The purpose of this article is to prove that the forcing axiom for completely

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.gn] 23 Sep 2003

arxiv:math/ v2 [math.gn] 23 Sep 2003 SPM BULLETIN arxiv:math/0305367v2 [math.gn] 23 Sep 2003 ISSUE NUMBER 5: MAY 2003 CE Contents 1. Editor s note 1 Contributions 2 Subscription 2 2. The Minimal Tower problem solved: A personal perspective

More information

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 169 (2001) Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom by Uri Abraham (Beer-Sheva) and Saharon Shelah (Jerusalem) Abstract. Assuming the continuum hypothesis there

More information

Forcing notions in inner models

Forcing notions in inner models Forcing notions in inner models David Asperó Abstract There is a partial order P preserving stationary subsets of! 1 and forcing that every partial order in the ground model V that collapses asu ciently

More information

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries Marko Djordjevi bstract We prove, by a probabilistic argument, that a class of ω-categorical structures, on which algebraic closure

More information

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we continue work from a previous paper on the fragility and indestructibility of the tree property. We present the following: (1)

More information

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ ALAN DOW Abstract. We prove that implies there is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff Lindelöf space of cardinality 2 ℵ1 which has points G δ. In addition, this space has

More information

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM The Journal of Symbolic Logic Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000 GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM KENNETH KUNEN AND DILIP RAGHAVAN Abstract. We continue the investigation of Gregory trees and

More information

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom

Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom arxiv:math/9807178v1 [math.lo] 15 Jul 1998 Lusin sequences under CH and under Martin s Axiom Uri Abraham Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Ben-Gurion University, Beér-Sheva, Israel Saharon

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which there are no Aronszajn trees at ℵ ω+1. This is an improvement

More information

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM ALAN DOW AND TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We show that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with all regular spaces of hereditarily countable π-character being C-closed. This

More information

A variant of Namba Forcing

A variant of Namba Forcing A variant of Namba Forcing Moti Gitik School of Mathematical Sciences Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Science Tel Aviv University Ramat Aviv 69978, Israel August 0, 009 Abstract Ronald Jensen

More information

correctly computed (Theorem below) seems to have been missed, as the argument is not dissimilar to other arguments in this area. If is singular and Jo

correctly computed (Theorem below) seems to have been missed, as the argument is not dissimilar to other arguments in this area. If is singular and Jo On Successors of Jonsson Cardinals J. Vickers Dept. of Mathematics, University of Bristol. Bristol BS8 TW, England. P. D. Welch Graduate School of Science & Technology, Kobe University, Rokko-dai, Nada-ku

More information

From Constructibility and Absoluteness to Computability and Domain Independence

From Constructibility and Absoluteness to Computability and Domain Independence From Constructibility and Absoluteness to Computability and Domain Independence Arnon Avron School of Computer Science Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel aa@math.tau.ac.il Abstract. Gödel s main

More information

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS LAJOS SOUKUP Abstract. The additivity spectrum ADD(I) of an ideal I P(I) is the set of all regular cardinals κ such that there is an increasing chain {A

More information

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED PROPER FORCING REMASTERED BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present the method introduced by Neeman of generalized side conditions with two types of models. We then discuss some applications:

More information

2 THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SUPERSETS OF AN R-MAXIMAL SET The structure of E has been the subject of much investigation over the past fty- ve years, s

2 THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SUPERSETS OF AN R-MAXIMAL SET The structure of E has been the subject of much investigation over the past fty- ve years, s ON THE FILTER OF COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SUPERSETS OF AN R-MAXIMAL SET Steffen Lempp Andre Nies D. Reed Solomon Department of Mathematics University of Wisconsin Madison, WI 53706-1388 USA Department of

More information

SOME RESULTS IN POLYCHROMATIC RAMSEY THEORY

SOME RESULTS IN POLYCHROMATIC RAMSEY THEORY SOME RESULTS IN POLYCHROMATIC RAMSEY THEORY URI ABRAHAM, JAMES CUMMINGS, AND CLIFFORD SMYTH 1. Introduction Classical Ramsey theory (at least in its simplest form) is concerned with problems of the following

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which the tree property

More information

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) Contents 1 Vector Spaces 1 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space.................................. 1 1.2 Subspaces...................................................

More information

Set theoretic properties of Loeb measure 2. Abstract. In this paper we ask the question: to what extent do basic set

Set theoretic properties of Loeb measure 2. Abstract. In this paper we ask the question: to what extent do basic set Set theoretic properties of Loeb measure Arnold W. Miller 1 University of Wisconsin Madison, WI 53706 miller@math.wisc.edu Abstract In this paper we ask the question: to what extent do basic set theoretic

More information

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1. M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, 10001 100NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE Justin Tatch Moore Abstract. The purpose of this note is to define an Aronszajn line η C and prove

More information

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics University of Illinois at Chicago Chicago, IL 60680 Rami Grossberg Department of Mathematics Carnegie

More information

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS PAUL C. EKLOF, LÁSZLÓ FUCHS, AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We consider the question of when the dual of a Whitehead group is a test group for Whitehead groups. This turns

More information

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present a direct proof of the consistency of the existence of a five element basis for the uncountable

More information

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We present a new forcing notion combining diagonal supercompact Prikry focing with interleaved extender based forcing. We start with a supercompact cardinal

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults. a System Can Withstand Without Repairs. Cambridge, MA 02139

Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults. a System Can Withstand Without Repairs. Cambridge, MA 02139 Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults a System Can Withstand Without Repairs Michel Goemans y Nancy Lynch z Isaac Saias x Laboratory for Computer Science Massachusetts Institute of Technology

More information

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper. SARAJEVO JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol.13 (26), No.2, (2017), 141 154 DOI: 10.5644/SJM.13.2.02 PRESERVING OLD ([ω] ℵ0, ) IS PROPER SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We give some sufficient and necessary conditions

More information

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET MOTI GITIK AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. 1. It is shown that the failure of S, for a set S ℵ ω+1 that reflects stationarily often, is consistent with GCH

More information

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS PHILIPP LÜCKE AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. Let L be a finite first-order language and M n n < ω be a sequence of finite L-models containing models

More information

HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS

HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS BARNABÁS FARKAS Abstract. We prove the following version of Hechler's classical theorem: For each partially ordered set (Q, ) with the property that every countable

More information

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom Thilo Weinert 1 1 Contact: e-mail: weinert@math.uni-bonn.de, Phone: +49 228 73 3791 Abstract We introduce the Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom(BAAFA). It turns out that it

More information

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski

Wojciech Stadnicki. On Laver extension. Uniwersytet Wrocławski. Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski Wojciech Stadnicki Uniwersytet Wrocławski On Laver extension Praca semestralna nr 2 (semestr letni 2010/11) Opiekun pracy: Janusz Pawlikowski On Laver extension Wojciech Stadnicki Abstract We prove that

More information

SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC. 1. introduction

SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC. 1. introduction SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC MOHAMMAD GOLSHANI Abstract. We give an affirmative answer to a question of Gorelic [5], by showing it is consistent, relative to the existence of

More information

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Lecture 11: Minimal types MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 11: Minimal types Tin Lok Wong 17 December, 2014 Uniform extension operators are used to construct models with nice structural properties Thus, one has a very simple

More information

form, but that fails as soon as one has an object greater than every natural number. Induction in the < form frequently goes under the fancy name \tra

form, but that fails as soon as one has an object greater than every natural number. Induction in the < form frequently goes under the fancy name \tra Transnite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated Version 1.1 Hilbert Levitz Department of Computer Science Florida State University levitz@cs.fsu.edu Intoduction This is supposed to be a primer

More information

A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS

A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS A UNIVERSAL SEQUENCE OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS STEVO TODORCEVIC Abstract. We show that for each positive integer k there is a sequence F n : R k R of continuous functions which represents via point-wise

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

A global version of a theorem of Ben-David and Magidor

A global version of a theorem of Ben-David and Magidor Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 102 (2000) 199 222 www.elsevier.com/locate/apal A global version of a theorem of Ben-David and Magidor Arthur W. Apter a; ;1, James Cummings b;2 a Department of Mathematics,

More information

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Rutgers University April 29, 2013 Abstract

More information

An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic

An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic San Jose State University SJSU ScholarWorks Master's Theses Master's Theses and Graduate Research Summer 2010 An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic Michael

More information

Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University

Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University SIMPLE COMPLETE BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University Abstract. For every regular cardinal κ

More information

Title Covering a bounded set of functions by Author(s) Kada, Masaru Editor(s) Citation Topology and its Applications. 2007, 1 Issue Date 2007-01 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10466/12488 Rights c2007 Elsevier

More information

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Young Set Theory Workshop 2010, Raach, Austria. The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Justin Tatch Moore 1 Notes taken by Giorgio Venturi In these notes we will present an exposition of the Proper Forcing

More information

The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals. Paul Corazza Maharishi University

The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals. Paul Corazza Maharishi University The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals Paul Corazza Maharishi University The Quest for an Axiomatic Foundation For Large Cardinals Gödel believed natural axioms would be found

More information

Garrett: `Bernstein's analytic continuation of complex powers' 2 Let f be a polynomial in x 1 ; : : : ; x n with real coecients. For complex s, let f

Garrett: `Bernstein's analytic continuation of complex powers' 2 Let f be a polynomial in x 1 ; : : : ; x n with real coecients. For complex s, let f 1 Bernstein's analytic continuation of complex powers c1995, Paul Garrett, garrettmath.umn.edu version January 27, 1998 Analytic continuation of distributions Statement of the theorems on analytic continuation

More information

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs Europ. J. Combinatorics (2002) 23, 257 274 doi:10.1006/eujc.2002.0574 Available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs ANTHONY BONATO, PETER

More information

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES MICHAEL HRUŠÁK AND CARLOS MARTÍNEZ RANERO Abstract. We introduce some guessing principles sufficient for the existence of non-special coherent Aronszajn

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski Stevo Todorcevic Berkeley, April 2, 2014 Outline 1. Global Chain Conditions 2. The Countable Chain Condition 3. Chain Conditions of Knaster, Shanin and Szpilrajn 4.

More information

The Modal Logic of Generic Multiverses

The Modal Logic of Generic Multiverses The Modal Logic of Generic Multiverses MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Jakob Piribauer (born August 6, 1994 in Berlin, Germany) under the supervision of Prof Dr Benedikt Löwe, and submitted to

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 1 Feb 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 1 Feb 2016 arxiv:160200605v1 [mathlo] 1 Feb 2016 A Borel-reducibility Counterpart of Shelah s Main Gap Theorem Tapani Hyttinen, Vadim Kulikov, Miguel Moreno University of Helsinki Abstract We study the Borel-reducibility

More information

Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L

Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L Fudan University National University of Singapore, September 9, 2017 Outline of Topics 1 CT s Problem 2 Gödel s Program 3 Ultimate L 4 Conclusion Remark Outline CT s Problem

More information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Ignacio Montes, Enrique Miranda, Susana Montes University of Oviedo, Dep. of Statistics and Operations Research. Abstract Stochastic dominance, which is

More information

Recursive definitions on surreal numbers

Recursive definitions on surreal numbers Recursive definitions on surreal numbers Antongiulio Fornasiero 19th July 2005 Abstract Let No be Conway s class of surreal numbers. I will make explicit the notion of a function f on No recursively defined

More information

NOTICE WARNING CONCERNING COPYRIGHT RESTRICTIONS: The copyright law of the United States (title 17, U.S. Code) governs the making of photocopies or

NOTICE WARNING CONCERNING COPYRIGHT RESTRICTIONS: The copyright law of the United States (title 17, U.S. Code) governs the making of photocopies or NOTICE WARNING CONCERNING COPYRIGHT RESTRICTIONS: The copyright law of the United States (title 17, U.S. Code) governs the making of photocopies or other reproductions of copyrighted material. Any copying

More information

Multitape Ordinal Machines and Primitive Recursion

Multitape Ordinal Machines and Primitive Recursion Multitape Ordinal Machines and Primitive Recursion Bernhard Irrgang and Benjamin Seyerth University of Bonn, Mathematical Institute Beringstraÿe 1, D-53115 Bonn, Germany irrgang@math.uni-bonn.de, benjamin.seyfferth@gmx.de

More information

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS PHILIPP LÜCKE Abstract. We show that it is consistent with the axioms of ZFC that there exists an infinite centreless group G with the property

More information

More forcing notions imply diamond

More forcing notions imply diamond More forcing notions imply diamond Andrzej Ros lanowski Dept. of Mathematics and Computer Science Bar-Ilan University 52900 Ramat-Gan, Israel and Mathematical Institute of Wroclaw University 50384 Wroclaw,

More information

Reasoning: From Basic Entailments. to Plausible Relations. Department of Computer Science. School of Mathematical Sciences. Tel-Aviv University

Reasoning: From Basic Entailments. to Plausible Relations. Department of Computer Science. School of Mathematical Sciences. Tel-Aviv University General Patterns for Nonmonotonic Reasoning: From Basic Entailments to Plausible Relations Ofer Arieli Arnon Avron Department of Computer Science School of Mathematical Sciences Tel-Aviv University Tel-Aviv

More information

Baire measures on uncountable product spaces 1. Abstract. We show that assuming the continuum hypothesis there exists a

Baire measures on uncountable product spaces 1. Abstract. We show that assuming the continuum hypothesis there exists a Baire measures on uncountable product spaces 1 by Arnold W. Miller 2 Abstract We show that assuming the continuum hypothesis there exists a nontrivial countably additive measure on the Baire subsets of

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Lifting to non-integral idempotents

Lifting to non-integral idempotents Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 162 (2001) 359 366 www.elsevier.com/locate/jpaa Lifting to non-integral idempotents Georey R. Robinson School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Birmingham,

More information

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order. October 12, 2010 Sacks Dicta... the central notions of model theory are absolute absoluteness, unlike cardinality, is a logical concept. That is why model theory does not founder on that rock of undecidability,

More information

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER ALAN DOW AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We construct a model in which the splitting number is large and every ultrafilter has a small subset with no pseudo-intersection.

More information

INCREASING THE GROUPWISE DENSITY NUMBER BY C.C.C. FORCING HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH

INCREASING THE GROUPWISE DENSITY NUMBER BY C.C.C. FORCING HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH INCREASING THE GROUPWISE DENSITY NUMBER BY C.C.C. FORCING HEIKE MILDENBERGER AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We show that ℵ 2 b < g is consistent. This work is dedicated to James Baumgartner on the occasion

More information

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique Université de Paris 7 http://www.logique.jussieu.fr/ boban 15th Boise Extravaganza in Set Theory Boise State University,

More information

1 Introduction A general problem that arises in dierent areas of computer science is the following combination problem: given two structures or theori

1 Introduction A general problem that arises in dierent areas of computer science is the following combination problem: given two structures or theori Combining Unication- and Disunication Algorithms Tractable and Intractable Instances Klaus U. Schulz CIS, University of Munich Oettingenstr. 67 80538 Munchen, Germany e-mail: schulz@cis.uni-muenchen.de

More information

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background. Model Theory II. 80824 22.10.2006-22.01-2007 (not: 17.12) Time: The first meeting will be on SUNDAY, OCT. 22, 10-12, room 209. We will try to make this time change permanent. Please write ehud@math.huji.ac.il

More information

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY Unspecified Journal Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S????-????(XX)0000-0 CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY TETSUYA ISHIU Abstract. Natural structures in set theory played key

More information

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS MARCIN KYSIAK AND TOMASZ WEISS Abstract. We discuss the question which properties of smallness in the sense of measure and category (e.g. being a universally

More information

INTRODUCTION TO NETS. limits to coincide, since it can be deduced: i.e. x

INTRODUCTION TO NETS. limits to coincide, since it can be deduced: i.e. x INTRODUCTION TO NETS TOMMASO RUSSO 1. Sequences do not describe the topology The goal of this rst part is to justify via some examples the fact that sequences are not sucient to describe a topological

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL ALAN DOW UNIVERSITY OF NORTH CAROLINA AT CHARLOTTE Abstract. We obtain an independence result connected to the classic Moore-Mrowka problem. A property known

More information

A Z q -Fan theorem. 1 Introduction. Frédéric Meunier December 11, 2006

A Z q -Fan theorem. 1 Introduction. Frédéric Meunier December 11, 2006 A Z q -Fan theorem Frédéric Meunier December 11, 2006 Abstract In 1952, Ky Fan proved a combinatorial theorem generalizing the Borsuk-Ulam theorem stating that there is no Z 2-equivariant map from the

More information

WHY Y-C.C. DAVID CHODOUNSKÝ AND JINDŘICH ZAPLETAL

WHY Y-C.C. DAVID CHODOUNSKÝ AND JINDŘICH ZAPLETAL WHY Y-C.C. DAVID CHODOUNSKÝ AND JINDŘICH ZAPLETAL Abstract. We outline a portfolio of novel iterable properties of c.c.c. and proper forcing notions and study its most important instantiations, Y-c.c.

More information

Lecture 14 - P v.s. NP 1

Lecture 14 - P v.s. NP 1 CME 305: Discrete Mathematics and Algorithms Instructor: Professor Aaron Sidford (sidford@stanford.edu) February 27, 2018 Lecture 14 - P v.s. NP 1 In this lecture we start Unit 3 on NP-hardness and approximation

More information