Two Kinds of Completeness and the Uses (and Abuses) of Exclusion Principles Matthew C. Haug * The College of William and Mary

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Two Kinds of Completeness and the Uses (and Abuses) of Exclusion Principles Matthew C. Haug * The College of William and Mary"

Transcription

1 Two Kinds of Completeness and the Uses (and Abuses) of Exclusion Principles Matthew C. Haug * The College of William and Mary Abstract I argue that the completeness of physics is composed of two distinct claims. The first is the commonly made claim that, roughly, every physical event is completely causally determined by physical events. The second has rarely, if ever, been explicitly stated in the literature and is the claim that microphysics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental categories that constitute both the causal features and intrinsic nature of all the events that causally affect the physical universe. After showing that these claims are distinct, I argue that they can be used to solve a difficulty with existing responses to the exclusion problem namely, that these existing responses also undermine the powerful causal argument for physicalism. Recognizing that there are two kinds of completeness opens up room for the non-reductive physicalist to solve the exclusion problem while also endorsing a modified, cogent causal argument for a kind of physicalism compatible with her position. 0. Introduction Claims about the completeness of physics have played a large role in contemporary debates about physicalism. The completeness of physics ( completeness for short) is the empirical claim that, roughly, all physical events can be accounted for in purely physical terms. 1 As David Papineau (2001) has pointed out, in one form or another, completeness is a key (sometimes implicit) premise in many arguments for physicalism. It figures in the arguments of David Lewis, David Armstrong, and Donald Davidson and in the related causal argument for physicalism discussed below. Completeness is also one of a group of mutually inconsistent * Matthew C. Haug is an assistant professor of philosophy at The College of William and Mary. His primary research interests are in the intersection of philosophy of mind, metaphysics, and philosophy of science. He has published in Philosophy of Science and Philosophical Studies and has a paper forthcoming in Erkenntnis. 1 The term closure is sometimes used instead of completeness. I prefer the latter term since it is less easily confused with the stronger claims that physical events have only physical causes or that the physical and non-physical domains cannot causally interact. 1

2 theses that make up the exclusion problem that faces non-reductive physicalists (see Kim 1993, 2005). Debates about the exclusion problem tend to take place at a very abstract level. It seems to be an implicit assumption in these debates that the scientific details (about, say, the relation between mental and neurological properties) will not affect the outcome. Of course, some of the grand, sweeping principles that figure in these debates are empirical and cannot be known a priori. Completeness is one such principle, and physicalists of all stripes accept some form of it. The main claim of this paper is that no matter which form of completeness turns out to be true, non-reductive physicalists can solve the causal exclusion problem without undermining a broadly causal argument for physicalism. Thus, even if the implicit assumption is wrong and the complicated and diverse relations between the mental and the physical do in fact bear on debates about reduction, non-reductive physicalists need not worry that a general, exclusion-based argument will undermine their view. 2 Although there has been some discussion in the literature about completeness claims of varying strength and the plausibility of different arguments for them (e.g., Montero 2003, Lowe 2000), it is generally taken for granted that completeness is a thesis solely concerned with causal sufficiency or causal explanation. In this paper, I argue that this common assumption is false. The completeness of physics encompasses two distinct claims. One is the more familiar claim that (roughly) every physical event is completely causally determined by physical causes (causal sufficiency completeness). The other is rarely, if ever, explicitly stated but is implicit in some 2 For example, Matthen and Ariew (2002, 79ff.) suggest that thermodynamic properties like temperature and pressure are not causally efficacious because trends involving them are discontinuous and irreversible. Similar claims might be thought to hold for some mental properties. However, as Matthen and Ariew note (ibid., 82), these considerations are very different from those that figure in the causal exclusion argument. 2

3 discussions of physicalism. It is roughly the claim that microphysics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental categories whose instances compose, and constitute the intrinsic nature of, the physical causes that figure in the first sort of completeness claim (fundamental category completeness). There are three main kinds of arguments for physicalism in the literature: simplicity, explanatory, and causal arguments. Feigl (1958) famously claimed that identifying mental states with physical ones results in a simpler ontology by getting rid of sui generis mental states and psychophysical laws which would otherwise be nomological danglers (i.e. states and laws that would not fit into the law-governed physical universe, but would be extraneous add-ons). But, as Hill (1991, 19 n.1) notes, it has never been shown that laws that use mental concepts make no real contribution to scientific explanations. In a similar vein, Kim (2005, 125) suggests that this simplicity argument is question begging or at least would not convince someone who did not already have physicalist sympathies. The question of whether a separate domain of mental entities is needed to save the phenomena is precisely what is at issue between physicalists and dualists. There is no neutral construal of the phenomena that must be explained by the candidate theories from which the simplest is chosen. Explanatory arguments for physicalism typically claim that type identities between mental and physical properties/events are the best explanation of the mental-physical correlations observed in nature and that this should lead us to accept type materialism (see, e.g., Hill 1991). However, if an explanatory argument works at all, it seems to work only as an argument for reductive physicalism. 3 For, it is less plausible to claim that a supervenience or realization 3 Kim (2005, Ch. 5) argues that explanatory arguments for physicalism (if they are in fact distinct from simplicity and causal arguments) are unsuccessful. As an anonymous referee pointed out, the simplicity argument is most naturally taken to support only reductive physicalism, as well. 3

4 relation, rather than identity, is the best explanation of psychophysical correlations taken by themselves. Although proponents of simplicity and explanatory arguments certainly have room to reply to these lines of thought, it appears that some version of the causal argument is the strongest argument for non-reductive physicalism. This paper shows how non-reductive physicalists can consistently accept a modified causal argument for a version of physicalism consistent with their position while also solving the exclusion problem. In Section 1, I motivate the distinction between causal sufficiency completeness and fundamental category completeness. In Section 2, I discuss how different versions of these claims arise depending on whether one interprets the occurrences of physical in them as highlevel physical or low-level physical. Causal sufficiency completeness is of course one of the four mutually inconsistent claims that make up the exclusion problem, and, in Section 3, I note that three of these claims have also been used, even by non-reductive physicalists, as premises in a causal argument for physicalism. Finally, in Sections 4 and 5, I discuss how existing responses to the exclusion problem also undermine the causal argument for physicalism and show how non-reductive physicalists can develop a modified causal argument for physicalism by appealing to the two kinds of completeness The Distinction Motivated One common formulation of completeness is as follows: Causal sufficiency completeness (CSC): For every physical event and every time t, if that event has a sufficient cause at t, then it has a physical sufficient cause at t. 4 Recognizing that there are two kind of completeness has other important implications, which I hope to explore elsewhere. For instance, if no single interpretation of physical makes both completeness claims true, this may explain why Hempel s dilemma that physicalism is either false or vacuous (or indeterminate in content) has proven so difficult for physicalists to address. 4

5 In other words, every physical event is completely causally determined, insofar as it is causally determined, by physical events (see, e.g., Kim 2005, 15-6). 5 I discuss how the occurrences of physical should be interpreted in the next section. Physicalists claim that the completeness of physics is supported by a wealth of empirical evidence (see, e.g., Papineau 2001). They believe that this evidence supports the claim that only the categories of physics will provide for exceptionless causal generalizations that are stated in a single, unified vocabulary. As Scott Sturgeon puts it: Whereas biology admits that biological effects sometimes have non-biological causes, and psychology admits that psychological effects sometimes have nonpsychological causes and, more generally, special science S admits that S- effects sometimes have non-s causes physics does not admit that physical effects have non-physical causes. Rather, physics considers itself closed and complete. It says physical effects have their chances fully determined by physical events alone. (1998, 413; cf. Baker 1993, 79) The more general idea of descending to a lower microlevel in order to completely explain anomalous phenomena at a higher level is also found in the literature. As Kim has remarked (crediting the physicist David Bohm): each time we descend to a lower microlevel, we do so because the current level is not causally closed ( explanatorily complete may be a better term in this context); that is, because there are phenomena at this level that can only be explained by descending to a lower level (2005, 67). Kim s parenthetical remark suggests that, in addition to causal sufficiency completeness, the general claim that physics is complete involves another claim that is not primarily, or exclusively, concerned with causation namely, that we do not need to appeal to non-physical categories to provide a complete account, not only 5 The provisos ( if that event has a sufficient cause at t and insofar as ) are included to allow for quantum indeterminacy. Solely in the interest of brevity, I omit these provisos in what follows; they should be understood to be implicit. Note that as I am using the terms, X is causally determined by Y if and only if Y is causally sufficient for X. Throughout, I assume a property exemplification view of events, according to which events correspond to ordered triples x, P, t, where x is an object and P is a property exemplified by x at time t. Some might claim that these entities are actually facts or states of affairs. See note 15. 5

6 of the individual causal sequences in the world, but also of the fundamental categories the instances of which constitute the intrinsic nature of those causes. In sum, the categories that are used in special science generalizations are not sufficiently general to provide for a complete account of the fundamental nature of all the events that causally affect the physical universe. It is only a privileged set of physical categories that can accomplish this task. This completeness claim can be put as follows: Fundamental category completeness (FCC): physics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental kinds and categories that are sufficient for a realization basis for all of the events that causally impinge on the physical universe. 6 A realization basis is a set of categories that characterizes the properties/events that realize a given set of phenomena. (In the case of fundamental category completeness, the phenomena in question are all those that causally affect the physical universe.) These categories will not only characterize the causal features of these properties/events but also, if this is something additional, their intrinsic nature. The members of a realization basis per se need not be fundamental. For example, if there is a hierarchy of levels in world, then a set of phenomena may have many different realization bases. This indicates that the qualifier fundamental must be included if fundamental category completeness is to be plausible. Kinds and categories that are macrophysical e.g., those of condensed matter physics, biology, and neuroscience are also arguably in the realization bases of other special science properties, but such kinds and categories are not fundamental (if 6 Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising the worry that a previous formulation of FCC was identical to the statement of physicalism itself, which prompted me to formulate FCC as it is above. 6

7 physicalism is true). Their distribution across the universe is itself supervenient on, and realized by, the distribution of low-level physical kinds and categories. 7 Fundamental category completeness is also suggested by David Papineau s claim that: Current physics, I take it, aims to develop a complete theory of paradigm physical effects [like arm movements] in terms of the categories of energy, field and spacetime structure (1993, 31). Although Papineau does not mention this, the term categories here does not refer to the sufficient causes themselves but to the building blocks of those causes. That is, this empirical claim is not about events but about the fundamental categories whose instances are constituents of events (e.g., fundamental particles like quarks, spacetime structure, etc.). To deny this kind of completeness, Papineau claims would in effect postulate an extra mental force alongside the fundamental physical forces of gravity, the electroweak force, and the strong nuclear force. This might once have made sense, but the cumulative evidence of two centuries of physiological research weighs heavily against it (1996, 4). For example, physics would not be complete, if consciousness or belief were a fundamental category in the realization basis for any of the events that causally affect the physical domain. (Note that these non-physical categories need not be forces, but merely fundamental categories that are needed in the relevant realization basis for events that impinge on the physical universe. I suspect that Papineau focuses on forces because he has not fully distinguished fundamental category completeness from causal sufficiency completeness.) 7 What if the universe turns out not to have a fundamental level? I believe that this does not immediately result in physicalism being a false or uninteresting doctrine. The physicalist can utilize a notion of relative fundamentality. If physicalism is true, then all entities that have physical effects are determined by physical entities such that any further determination of these entities is also by physical entities (cf. Montero 2006, 178). 7

8 These two completeness claims are obviously distinct. For one thing, causal sufficiency completeness does not entail fundamental category completeness. It is possible for physics to be causally complete without providing a complete inventory of fundamental categories that characterize the intrinsic nature of all phenomena that causally affect the physical universe. 8 Further, the accounts that are promised by fundamental category completeness are not entirely causal, while those promised by causal sufficiency completeness are. Explanations that are supported by fundamental category completeness are, in part, constitutive ones in which the existence and properties of a whole are explained by the existence and properties of its parts (cf. Poland s (1994) notion of vertical explanations ). Perhaps this constitutive explanation will be a relatively deflationary one, involving the claim that constitution is identity. Or perhaps it will deny that constitution is identity and utilize realization or another determination relation. In any case, this synchronic relation that grounds the explanation of the properties of a whole in terms of the properties of its parts is the relation in virtue of which special science entities are nothing over and above fundamental physical entities. This relation is distinct from the diachronic, causal one that underwrites the explanations promised by causal sufficiency completeness. 2. Completeness and the Physical It has long been recognized that there are several senses of physical. Contemporary discussions often contrast a low-level or microphysical domain with a disjoint high-level or ordinary physical domain (e.g. Chalmers 1996, 33). 9 For example, low-level physical 8 An anonymous referee prompted me to make this point explicit and suggested that Leibniz may have endorsed causal sufficiency completeness while denying fundamental category completeness, since, arguably according to Leibniz, mental causes are not needed for the causal explanation of physical phenomena, but physical phenomena are themselves ultimately constituted by the monads perceptions. 9 There is, of course, long-standing controversy about whether (low-level) physical can be defined in such a way that physicalism turns out to be a substantive doctrine that is also true. In 8

9 properties, according to Chalmers, are the fundamental properties that are invoked by a completed theory of physics. Perhaps these will include mass, charge, spatiotemporal position; properties characterizing the distribution of various spatiotemporal fields, the exertion of various forces, and the form of various waves; and so on (ibid.). I will stipulate that low-level physical properties are those that belong to only individual low-level physical entities. By contrast, highlevel physical properties and events are constructible out of low-level physical properties and events by means of various operations e.g. some Boolean operations, mereological and perhaps other forms of composition, realization. The high-level physical domain will thus include aggregates of low-level physical entities, and the structural, or micro-based, properties that these aggregates have. 10 It is controversial whether such aggregates of low-level entities are identical to ordinary, macroscopic objects, and completeness itself should leave this question open (see note 11). However, high-level physical properties and events should obviously also include such things as arm movements, earthquakes, and being a toaster, no matter how debates about material constitution turn out. Hence, if such macro-physical events and properties are not already included by closing the low-level physical domain under aggregation, then we should add them. Finally, we can say that the inclusive physical domain is the union of the high-level and low-level physical domains. Which versions of causal sufficiency completeness are plausible when these different senses of physical are substituted into it? It is commonly claimed that the low-level physical this paper, I assume that this can be done. See Crane and Mellor (1990) and Wilson (2006) for discussion. 10 A micro-based, or structural, property, P, is the property of having proper parts that are propertied and related in certain ways. In this paper, I do not take a stand on the general issue of which relations are sufficient to ground high-level physical properties/events in low-level physical ones. However, in Section 5 I follow compatibilists like Bennett and Shoemaker in thinking that a metaphysical necessitation relation is required if high-level properties are to avoid being excluded by low-level physical properties. 9

10 domain contains a sufficient cause for every low-level physical event (cf. Baker 1993, 79; Sturgeon 1998; Kim 2005, 65). That is, it is often claimed that the following is true: CSC LL : Every low-level physical event is completely causally determined by lowlevel physical events. What about the sufficient causes of high-level physical events, like windows breaking and arms raising? Should we expect them all to be low-level physical? The following passage from Kim s 1998 book suggests that the answer is no, at least if we think that the low-level physical domain contains only individual low-level physical entities and their properties: Perhaps the standard micro-macro hierarchy encourages the idea that the causally closed physical domain includes only the basic particles and their properties and relations. But that is a groundless assumption. Plainly the physical domain must also include aggregates of basic particles, aggregates of these aggregates, and so on, without end; atoms, molecules, cells, tables, planets, computers, biological organisms, and all the rest must be, without question, part of the physical domain. It is important that these [objects and their] micro-based properties are counted as physical, for otherwise the physical domain won't be causally closed. Having a mass of one kilogram has causal powers that no smaller masses have, and water molecules, or the property of being water, have causal powers not had by individual hydrogen and oxygen atoms. (1998, 113-4, italics added) The idea is that aggregate objects and their micro-based properties are needed as sufficient causes of some high-level physical events. For example: The shattering of the glass was caused by the baseball and certainly not by the individual particles composing it (Kim 2005, 56). 11 According to this line of thought, the following claim is false: CSC IL : Every inclusive physical event is completely causally determined by lowlevel physical events In these passages, Kim assumes that aggregates of micro-entities are identical to macroscopic objects e.g., the baseball = this composite structure of microparticles (2005, 56). Kim believes that this helps him stop the exclusion problem from generalizing and causal powers from draining away (see his 2005, ch. 2). See also note Note that if Kim s line of thought is correct, then CSC LL is false for the same reasons. E.g. a photon will be deflected more by a large, aggregate object (like the Sun, or the aggregate that constitutes the Sun) than it would be by any single microphysical particle. 10

11 Rather, since some high-level physical events have only high-level physical causes, only the following weaker claim is true: CSC II : Every inclusive physical event is completely causally determined by inclusive physical events. 13 Which version of fundamental category completeness should physicalists accept? Based on the discussion of it above, it is clear that physicalists believe that the following version is supported by the empirical evidence: FCC LI : Low-level physics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental kinds and categories that are sufficient for a realization basis for all of the events that causally impinge on the inclusive physical universe. Unless one endorses a strong kind of emergentism, according to which new fundamental categories emerge at higher levels of aggregation, one should not accept FCC II (the claim that inclusive physics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental kinds and categories that are sufficient for a realization basis for all the events that causally impinge on the inclusive physical universe) unless one also accepts FCC LI. 14 If Kim s line of thought is correct, it shows that FCC LI does not entail CSC IL. Often, the aggregation of microparticles and the resulting determination of properties of a whole by properties of its low-level physical parts will be needed for the bestowal of causal powers that are necessary to provide a sufficient cause of some high-level physical event. (As Kim notes, the microphysical parts of the baseball mentioned above cause the window to break only in the sense 13 Although I find Kim s line of thought appealing, I am officially agnostic about whether it is correct. One of the main points of this paper is that no matter which version of CSC is true, nonreductive physicalists can solve the exclusion problem. Since the low-level physical domain is a proper subset of the inclusive physical domain, we have the following entailments but not their converses: CSC IL CSC LL CSC LI and CSC IL CSC II CSC LI (where CSC LI is roughly the claim that every low-level physical event is completely causally determined by inclusive physical events). Since physicalists think that at least either CSC LL or CSC II is true (is supported by empirical evidence), we can ignore CSC LI without loss of generality. 14 Thanks to an anonymous referee for crucial clarification on this point. 11

12 that they constitute a whole that has that effect.) However, these high-level physical causal powers will not involve any new fundamental forces (or other categories) that are not present in the low-level physical domain. Hence, denying CSC IL, and accepting CSC II instead, provides no reason to abandon FCC LI. 3. The Exclusion Problem and the Causal Argument for Physicalism Causal sufficiency completeness, of course, appears as one of the four mutually inconsistent claims that make up the exclusion problem: Causal sufficiency completeness: Every physical event is completely causally determined by physical events. Causal efficacy: Mental events are causally sufficient for some physical events. Causal exclusion principle: For every time t, (CEPa) there cannot be two or more sufficient causes at t of an event, except for cases of overdetermination, and (CEPb) instances of mental causation are not, in general, cases of overdetermination. Irreducibility: Mental events are not identical to physical events. Although it is seldom explicitly mentioned in print (but see Bennett (2008, 282)), these four claims have been used in the literature for two distinct purposes. First, they have been used to pose a dilemma for non-reductive physicalists (the exclusion problem): either abandon the causal efficacy of the mental or its irreducibility, on pain of giving up either the causal exclusion principle or completeness, which are metaphysical theses that at least any physicalist is supposedly committed to. Second, the first three claims are used as premises in an argument for (something like) the denial of irreducibility. That is, the theses of the exclusion problem provide the material for the causal argument for physicalism of any kind, as against property and substance dualism (cf. Papineau 1993, 2001). Of course, many non-reductive physicalists would like to block the first use while endorsing the second. In the remainder of the paper, I argue that 12

13 existing attempts to do so fail. However, appealing to the two kinds of completeness allows one to solve the exclusion problem while endorsing a modified causal argument for a version of physicalism that need not be reductive. I used the mealy-mouthed phrase (something like) the denial of irreducibility above because the causal argument is often used to support a form of physicalism that does not identify mental events (and properties) with physical events (and properties). Consider David Papineau s treatment of the causal argument. According to Papineau, the causal efficacy of the mental, together with the completeness of physics and an assumption that overdetermination is not widespread, implies that we need somehow to identify the mental cause with the physical cause, so as to avoid the conclusion that [the physical effect in question] was overdetermined (Papineau 1993, 23). Papineau thinks that we can avoid type-identity and token-identity of mental and physical properties by appealing to a generous conception of causation according to which an instance of a strongly supervening fact causes the effects of those facts on which it supervenes (Papineau 2002, Section 1.8); see also (Witmer 2000, 281-2)). 15 In effect, this is the supervenient causation proposal that Kim put forward in his (1984), according to which a supervenient property causes whatever its base property does. As Kim later realized, such a move is unsatisfactory. If there can be two numerically distinct simultaneous sufficient causes of a given event, then the causal exclusion principle, as stated above, is violated. Merely claiming that distinct mental and physical facts are congruent, but not identical (see Papineau 1993) results in the exclusion problem simply arising again for these facts. In short, if non-reductive physicalists want to use an exclusion-based, causal argument for physicalism, they cannot merely 15 Papineau argues that the causal relation holds between facts, not events. However, if a fact is an object instantiating a property at a time, then it is a Kimian event. See note 5. 13

14 appropriate the same argument that some reductive physicalists use to claim that non-reductive physicalism is itself inconsistent. Physicalists assure us that there is good empirical evidence that some form of CSC is true. Depending on whether CSC IL, or only one of CSC II or CSC LL, holds we are faced with different versions of the exclusion problem. If only CSC LL is true, we have: CSC LL : Every low-level physical event is completely causally determined by lowlevel physical events. Causal efficacy L : Mental events are causally sufficient for some low-level physical events. Causal exclusion principle: For every time t, (CEPa) there cannot be two or more sufficient causes at t of an event, except for cases of overdetermination, and (CEPb) instances of mental causation are not, in general, cases of overdetermination. Irreducibility L : Mental events are not identical to low-level physical events. If Kim s line of thought presented above is correct and only CSC II is true, then we have: CSC II : Every inclusive physical event is completely causally determined by inclusive physical events. Causal efficacy I : Mental events are causally sufficient for some inclusive physical events. Causal exclusion principle: For every time t, (CEPa) there cannot be two or more sufficient causes at t of an event, except for cases of overdetermination, and (CEPb) instances of mental causation are not, in general, cases of overdetermination. Irreducibility I : Mental events are not identical to inclusive physical events. Finally, if the strongest form of CSC is true, we have: CSC IL : Every inclusive physical event is completely causally determined by lowlevel physical events. Causal efficacy I : Mental events are causally sufficient for some inclusive physical events. 14

15 Causal exclusion principle: For every time t, (CEPa) there cannot be two or more sufficient causes at t of an event, except for cases of overdetermination, and (CEPb) instances of mental causation are not, in general, cases of overdetermination. Irreducibility L : Mental events are not identical to low-level physical events. Below I argue that no matter which version the proponent of the exclusion problem endorses, non-reductive physicalists can solve the exclusion problem while also endorsing a modified causal argument for physicalism. 4. Existing Non-reductive Physicalist Responses Undermine the Causal Argument for Physicalism Perhaps the most popular direct response to the exclusion problem is to deny the causal exclusion principle what is sometimes called a compatibilist response. 16 Some philosophers formulate their response as a rejection of (CEPa) and claim that there are cases where two simultaneous events are causally sufficient for a given event without overdetermining that event (see Bennett 2003, 473). They thus adopt a narrow reading of overdetermination, according to which two simultaneous events, A and B, overdetermine a given event only if A and B are (metaphysically or nomologically) independent. 17 Others adopt a broad reading of overdetermination, as I will in this paper, according to which any two numerically distinct simultaneous sufficient causes of a given event overdetermine that event. These philosophers deny (CEPb); they see overdetermination everywhere and are not troubled by it Perhaps even more popular is to argue that the exclusion problem generalizes to all supervenient properties as well as structural ones and results in the supposedly absurd conclusion that causation only occurs at the fundamental physical level (see, e.g. Noordhof 1999 and Block 2003, among many others). However, since the generalization argument is a reductio, it does not show us exactly what is wrong with the exclusion problem. 17 Versions of this response are defended by Bennett (2003), Horgan (1997), and Yablo (1992), among many others. 18 This sort of response is offered by Sider (2003). 15

16 Obviously, if a compatibilist response is successful, it works equally well as a solution to each of the versions of the exclusion problem presented above. I think that, in the end, all paths to non-reductive physicalism must run through a compatibilist response, the details of which I will discuss further in Section 5. However, it will be instructive to consider some alternate responses to the first two versions of the exclusion problem. For example, Sturgeon (1998) argues, in effect, that only CSC LL is true. As he puts it: No working scientific theory says [inclusive] physical effects have fully revealing [inclusive] physical histories. And neither does commonsense. Quite the contrary: both macro science and everyday experience rely upon mental causes for [inclusive] physical effects (1998, 416). Hence, according to Sturgeon, we are faced only with the first version of the exclusion problem. Further, Sturgeon claims that causal efficacy is plausible only if it claims that mental events have high-level physical effects. No working scientific theory postulates a pervasive causal link between mental events and [low-level physical] events. Neither does commonsense (ibid., 415). Hence, according to Sturgeon, causal efficacy L is false. Since only causal efficacy L is incompatible with with CSC LL, the exclusion problem only appears to be a problem if we equivocate on the sense of physical involved in two of its claims. 19 Now, I don t think that Sturgeon s equivocation argument is all that convincing. Perhaps it is true that neither scientific theory nor commonsense posits a pervasive causal link between 19 Sturgeon s argument is more complicated than this: he argues against several causal principles that bridge the gap between the low-level and high-level physical. Witmer (2000) argues that we can bridge this gap by using a principle of dependent causal transmission that relies on the fact that high-level events are nothing over and above collections of low-level physical events. This principle allows us to derive the claim that mental events are causally sufficient for some low-level physical events from the uncontroversial claim that mental events are causally sufficient for some high-level physical events (ibid., 280-1). However, as noted above, Witmer endorses an untenable supervenience-based response to the exclusion problem that is similar to Papineau s. 16

17 mental events and low-level physical events, but this kind of a pervasive causal link is not needed for the exclusion problem to get off the ground. All we need are some cases of causal interaction between mental and low-level physical events, and these are easy to find (for example, experiments in particle physics). Further, since mental events have high-level physical effects and these, in turn, often have low-level physical effects, we can derive causal efficacy L as long as causation is transitive. 20 In addition, non-reductive physicalists should be reluctant to adopt Sturgeon s response, since his intention is to undermine the causal argument for physicalism in general, not solve the exclusion problem in a way that is compatible with non-reductive physicalism. So, I think that a compatibilist response is the best strategy for non-reductive physicalists to adopt even with respect to the first version of the exclusion problem. I mention Sturgeon s argument only because a related kind of equivocation response may be offered to the second, inclusive physical, version of the exclusion problem. This response by itself also undermines the causal argument for physicalism, but in a different way than Sturgeon s argument does. And, as I will argue, the non-reductive physicalist can rehabilitate an argument for physicalism, in this case, by appealing to FCC LI. Given that high-level physical events include those that are constructible from low-level physical events in certain ways, the non-reductive physicalist can insist that she need not deny that mental events are high-level physical. That is, she may insist that the falsity of irreducibility I is compatible with her position. According to this view, mental properties and events are merely special kinds of inclusive physical properties and events. Mental properties 20 Of course, whether causation is transitive or not is controversial, but, all other things being equal, it would be better if one s solution to the exclusion problem didn t hinge on it turning out not to be. 17

18 and events are just like certain biological properties and events in that they are constructible out of (and thus nothing over and above) low-level physical events. 21 But, according to this view, mental properties are no more identical to low-level physical properties than biological properties like being a gene, being a species or being a predator are. The non-reductive physicalist may argue that this is merely taking Kim s line of thought about aggregates to its logical conclusion. If the causally complete physical domain must include computers, biological organisms, and all the rest, then it seems hard to deny that it will also include (at least some) mental properties and events. That is, if we are asking about the causes of inclusive physical events, causal sufficiency completeness is only plausible if we include high-level physical events (including mental events!) in the causally complete domain. Hence, the non-reductive physicalist can claim that there is no physical domain that is both causally complete and excludes mental events. In effect, this response endorses only CSC II and claims that irreducible mental events (i.e. those that are not identical to, but are appropriately constructible out of, low-level physical events) must be included in the causally complete inclusive physical domain. Further, since this response holds that mental events are sometimes sufficient causes that do not overdetermine physical effects, the non-reductive physicalist can actually endorse the strong version of the causal exclusion principle stated above. For, causal sufficiency completeness (in this case, CSC II ) can no longer be used as a reason to choose the low-level physical cause over a mental one when combined with the causal exclusion principle. The smallest causally complete physical domain includes irreducible mental properties if this 21 For example, Pereboom (2002) presents a non-functionalist version of non-reductive physicalism and suggests that mental properties are abstract, structural properties (see, esp. p ). 18

19 response is sound. This removes the bias against the mental in causal contexts; mental and other high-level physical properties are no longer screened off from causal efficacy. I think that this response to the exclusion problem is perfectly consistent, although it represents a significant reconfiguration of the usual way debates between reductive and nonreductive physicalism are thought about. 22 We might call it an expansive reading of the causal argument since it leaves our conception of the mental relatively fixed and tries to show that there is a legitimate sense of physical that can be expanded to encompass it for example, by showing that whatever relations that are sufficient to show that chemical and biological properties are inclusive physical (e.g., micro-basing, the formation of structural properties, or realization) also hold between mental and low-level physical properties. However, this response faces at least two significant problems. First, this response leaves the causal argument for physicalism with little bite. Second, it is arguable that the exclusion problem merely reappears in the inclusive physical domain i.e., that the exclusion problem generalizes to micro-based or structural high-level physical properties. Consider the first problem. The corresponding version of the causal argument uses CSC II, causal efficacy I, and the causal exclusion principle to argue for the denial of irreducibility I. However, this argument would probably not convince someone who did not already have physicalist sympathies. All of the work is done by the claim that mental properties and events are constructible from low-level physical events and must be included in the smallest domain that includes a sufficient cause for every inclusive physical event. 22 I suspect that this view elaborates some of the interesting complexities that Bennett (2008, 285) alludes to, which are related to her suspicion that the distinction between reductive and nonreductive physicalism is probably not metaphysically very deep (ibid.) 19

20 Even if a dualist accepts CSC II, she might legitimately ask why this interpretation of the causal argument is anything more than a terminological recommendation. Haven t we just bestowed the mental with the honorific term high-level physical? To put the point a slightly different way: Isn t the causal argument for physicalism trivial if a causal completeness claim holds only for a physical domain that is so inclusive that it already contains aggregate macrophysical objects, like humans and other organisms, and all their properties that are constructible from low-level properties in certain ways, including mental ones? Why is this version of physicalism not just dualism by another name, especially if we are liberal about what counts as an acceptable method of construction? 23 We can address this problem by endorsing FCC LI. As long as the non-reductive physicalist endorses this strong fundamental category completeness claim, then her position deserves to be called a version of physicalism. I will present an explicit argument using FCC LI in Section 5, but the rough idea is that in opposition to anti-physicalist property dualism, the nonreductive physicalist holds that mental properties and categories are neither fundamentally different from low-level physical properties nor fundamental themselves. Rather, they are determined by and dependent on (but need not be identical to) those low-level physical properties and categories. Turning to the second problem: this expansive reading of the causal argument depends on the exclusion problem not generalizing to structural or micro-based properties. However, this is at best a highly controversial claim (see, e.g., Block 2003 and Kim 2005, ch. 2). A hard-core proponent of exclusion-based reasoning would insist that the plurality of micro-physical 23 This worry is similar to the triviality or vacuity horn of what has come to be called Hempel s dilemma (cf. Crane and Mellor 1990) the worry that physicalism is a trivial claim if it is defined in terms of ideal physical theory. 20

21 components of a structural property screens the latter off from causal efficacy, just as Kim insists that structural physical properties screen off mental properties that supervene on them. In other words, a hard-core proponent of the exclusion problem would argue that (pluralities of) low-level physical events that underlie, or in some way compose, mental and other high-level physical events are in fact causally sufficient for all inclusive physical events; they would simply deny that mental and high-level physical events are non-overdetermining inclusive physical causes. Such a proponent would, contra Kim, admit that the exclusion problem generalizes to events whose constitutive properties are micro-based. According to this perspective, CSC IL is true, and the causal exclusion principle rules out all alleged instances of causation involving aggregates; only events involving solely individual low-level physical objects, or pluralities (which are not aggregates) of such objects, cause anything (if any causation occurs at all). (Cf. Merricks (2001) who lays out this view but rejects completeness in order to avoid it.) I will not reengage the extensive debate about whether the exclusion problem generalizes. Rather, I will assume that it does, since this puts my opponents (the proponents of the exclusion problem) in as strong a position as possible. Even granting them this assumption, non-reductive physicalists can still solve the exclusion problem while preserving a causal argument for physicalism. 5. Developing a Modified Causal Argument for Physicalism If Sturgeon s response fails and if the exclusion problem generalizes, the best bet for solving each of the first two versions of the exclusion problem is to adopt a compatiblist response. I believe that this is also the best reply to the final version of the exclusion problem, which uses CSC IL. Suppose a convincing case can be made for this compatibilist response, which claims that mental events are always acceptable overdetermining causes of physical 21

22 effects. That is, suppose that the non-reductive physicalist can successfully argue against the strong causal exclusion principle stated above and for a qualified causal exclusion principle that allows for widespread overdetermination by simultaneous causes only if those causes are appropriated related to one another at the least, being linked by a metaphysical necessitation relation (see, e.g., Bennett 2003). This qualified causal exclusion principle does not rule out causation by irreducible mental events, but it too undermines the causal argument for the claim that those events are nothing over and above low-level physical events. Non-reductive physicalists who take a compatibilist approach and also seek to endorse a causal argument for their position can only appeal to a weaker, qualified version of the causal exclusion principle that allows some types of overdetermination (e.g. by determinates and their determinables) while ruling out others (e.g. overdetermination by physical events and independent, sui generis mental events is not allowed). However, the problem that non-reductive physicalists face is how to motivate those qualifications to the causal exclusion principle in a non-ad-hoc, non-question-begging way. The conclusion of the causal argument for nonreductive physicalism is that the mental and the physical are related by some relation R that is not identity and that implies that the mental is physicalistically acceptable. Obviously, the nonreductive physicalist cannot simply qualify the causal exclusion principle so that it allows widespread overdetermination only if the simultaneous causes of a given event are related by relation R. This would be ad hoc or question begging. One cannot both appeal to the supposed relation between the mental and the physical (realization, constitution, etc.) as a solution to the exclusion problem and also use that qualified causal exclusion principle (whose qualifications were introduced because of that very relation) in the causal argument for non-reductive physicalism. The causal argument was supposed to establish that that relation holds that the 22

23 physical realizes or constitutes the mental. The considerations that determine how the causal exclusion principle should be qualified must not be ones that only physicalists will endorse if that principle is to be used in an argument for physicalism. It is likely that any such plausible, neutral considerations will support a qualified causal exclusion principle that, when combined with causal sufficiency completeness and causal efficacy, does not yield physicalism as a conclusion, but merely a type of monism. Thus, there is a tension in some non-reductive physicalists treatment of the causal exclusion principle that is different from the one that Kim emphasizes. These non-reductive physicalists do not simply seem to face a choice between reductionism and epiphenomenalism (i.e., the exclusion problem). They also seem to face a choice between (1) endorsing a valid causal argument for reductive physicalism (that uses the strong causal exclusion principle stated above), (2) endorsing a valid causal argument that falls short of physicalism (more on this below), and (3) endorsing an ineffective argument for non-reductive physicalism, one that uses an ad hoc or question begging qualified causal exclusion principle that solves the exclusion problem but presupposes that mental events are physicalistically acceptable, which is of course exactly what the causal argument was intended to show. Non-reductive physicalists should obviously take the second option and admit that the conclusion of the argument that uses a qualified causal exclusion principle falls short of physicalism. For, it establishes merely a kind of monism, in which either the physical necessitates the mental, the mental necessitates the physical, or some third, neutral event necessitates both the mental and the physical. We have the following argument: CSC IL : Every inclusive physical event is completely causally determined by lowlevel physical causes. Causal efficacy I : Mental events cause some inclusive physical events. 23

24 Qualified causal exclusion principle: For every time t, there can be two or more causes at t of an event only if there is (at least) a metaphysical necessitation relation between those causes (setting aside cases of independent overdetermination, like a death caused by a lightning strike simultaneous with a gunshot, as irrelevant to mental causation). Therefore, causal monism: Mental events (and their constitutive properties), metaphysically necessitate, are necessitated by, or are linked via some other event(s) by a necessitation relation to, low-level physical events (and their constitutive properties). 24 To complete an argument for physicalism we need to establish that only the second of the disjuncts listed above holds; we need a guarantee that only the low-level physical is fundamental, that it is the foundation over which nothing else is over and above. Again, fundamental category completeness comes to the rescue! It is empirically plausible and can be used in an argument that establishes this (and that does not immediately result in the claim that mental properties and categories are identical to microphysical properties and categories): FCC LI : Low-level physics provides a complete inventory of the fundamental kinds and categories that are sufficient for a realization basis for all of the events that causally impinge on the inclusive physical universe. Mental relevance: Mental categories are required for a realization basis of some events that causally impinge on the inclusive physical universe Note that a very similar position results from the expansive, equivocation response to the second version of the exclusion problem: CSC II, causal efficacy I, and the exclusion principle lead to reducibility I : mental events are identical to inclusive physical events. As discussed above, the problem is that this argument tells us very little about the nature of the inclusive physical domain (see note 23). Hence, if CSC II is true and the exclusion problem doesn t generalize, the nonreductive physicalist will still need to appeal to the argument involving FCC LI presented below. For the first version of the exclusion problem, we would obviously just replace CSC IL with CSC LL and causal efficacy I with causal efficacy L in the above argument. 25 This is nothing more than an affirmation of a kind of realism about mental categories: events that causally affect the inclusive physical domain can be correctly categorized with respect to mental features concerning experience (e.g., affective and emotional aspects), content, and attitude (belief, desire, etc.). Of course, epiphenomenalists are free to deny mental relevance, but it is far from clear that this is empirically plausible. Similarly, some dualists may consistently deny CSC (or FCC LI ), but the fact that it is empirically implausible to do so arguably explains 24

Physicalism decomposed

Physicalism decomposed Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.January 20056513339ArticlesAndreas Hüttemann and David Papineau Physicalism decomposed Physicalism

More information

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research The main conclusion of Jaegwon Kim s admirable Mind and the Physical World is that the mindbody problem- Descartes problem of explaining how mental causation

More information

Durham Research Online

Durham Research Online Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 24 October 2016 Version of attached le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Gibb, S. C. (2017) 'The mental

More information

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation. Against Composition as Identity KRIS MCDANIEL The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation. The farmer s field is made of six plots, and in some sense is nothing more

More information

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! Jerry Fodor and his Special Sciences So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! ) The use of special in

More information

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem Kirk Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611-8545 U.S.A. kludwig@phil.ufl.edu

More information

Emerging from the Causal Drain

Emerging from the Causal Drain Emerging from the Causal Drain Richard Corry This is a pre-print of an article published in Philosophical Studies 165 (1):29-47 (2013). The final publication is available at link.springer.com Abstract

More information

Physicalism

Physicalism 2015.11.16 Physicalism Table of contents 1 What is Identity Theory? 2 Closure of Physics and the Unity of Science Supervenience 3 Argument From Agency 4 Arguments From Causal Overdetermination Identity

More information

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv + 408 pages by Bradley Monton June 24, 2009 It probably goes without saying that

More information

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism CAUSATION CAUSATION Chapter 10 Non-Humean Reductionism Humean states of affairs were characterized recursively in chapter 2, the basic idea being that distinct Humean states of affairs cannot stand in

More information

TYPE PHYSICALISM AND CAUSAL EXCLUSION

TYPE PHYSICALISM AND CAUSAL EXCLUSION This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2013). Type Physicalism and Causal Exclusion. Journal of Philosophical Research, 38, 405-418. The final publication is available

More information

65,536 Definitions of Physicalism. David J. Chalmers

65,536 Definitions of Physicalism. David J. Chalmers 65,536 Definitions of Physicalism David J. Chalmers An Intuitive Definition n Physicalism: n All being is ontologically determined by physical being. Definition Template n Physicalism: n All As of type

More information

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 58 (2007), 777 786 Sklar s Maneuver Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Sklar ([1974]) claimed that relationalism about ontology the doctrine that space and time do not exist is compatible with

More information

dialectica Closure Principles and the Laws of Conservation of Energy and Momentumdltc_

dialectica Closure Principles and the Laws of Conservation of Energy and Momentumdltc_ dialectica dialectica Vol. 64, N 3 (2010), pp. 363 384 DOI: 10.1111/j.1746-8361.2010.01237.x Closure Principles and the Laws of Conservation of Energy and Momentumdltc_1237 363..384 Sophie Gibb Abstract

More information

CAUSAL POWERS, FORCES, AND SUPERDUPERVENIENCE. Jessica M. WILSON University of Michigan

CAUSAL POWERS, FORCES, AND SUPERDUPERVENIENCE. Jessica M. WILSON University of Michigan Grazer Philosophische Studien 63 (2002) 53-78 CAUSAL POWERS, FORCES, AND SUPERDUPERVENIENCE Jessica M. WILSON University of Michigan Summary Horgan (1993) proposed that superdupervenience supervenience

More information

Careful, Physicalists: Mind Body Supervenience Can Be Too Superduper

Careful, Physicalists: Mind Body Supervenience Can Be Too Superduper This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2013). Careful, Physicalists: Mind Body Supervenience Can Be Too Superduper. Theoria, 79 (1), 8-21. The final publication is available

More information

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space 12.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 19-25. Now that we have seen Newton s and Leibniz

More information

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Universalism Entails Extensionalism Universalism Entails Extensionalism Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York [Final version published in Analysis, 69 (2009), 599 604] 1. Universalism (also known as Conjunctivism,

More information

Weak and Global Supervenience Are Strong

Weak and Global Supervenience Are Strong Weak and Global Supervenience Are Strong Abstract Kim argues that weak and global supervenience are too weak to guarantee any sort of dependency. Of the three original forms of supervenience, strong, weak,

More information

THE CAUSAL CLOSURE PRINCIPLE

THE CAUSAL CLOSURE PRINCIPLE The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 65, No.261 2015 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1093/pq/pqv030 Advance Access Publication 26th April 2015 THE CAUSAL CLOSURE PRINCIPLE By Sophie Gibb In the mental causation debate,

More information

Is Mind-Brain Interactionism really in trouble?

Is Mind-Brain Interactionism really in trouble? "There once was a ghost who opened Einstein's office door... in doing this he thought he could disprove the conservation of energy law." 1 Did he? The law of conservation of energy-mass has had quite an

More information

Skepticism and Structuralism

Skepticism and Structuralism Skepticism and Structuralism Structuralism with respect to space and/or spatial relations is of considerable interest. Consider what I will call the distance relation: x and y stand in this relation just

More information

*a * * *b * * *c *d *

*a * * *b * * *c *d * K. MCDANIEL DISTANCE AND DISCRETE SPACE Let us say that space is discrete if and only if every finite extended region of space is composed of finitely many atomic regions of space. I assume here that regions

More information

Baysan, U. (2015) Realization relations in metaphysics. Minds and Machines.

Baysan, U. (2015) Realization relations in metaphysics. Minds and Machines. ,,nn Baysan, U. (2015) Realization relations in metaphysics. Minds and Machines. Copyright 2015 Springer A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission

More information

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp. 72-81. The Bundle Theory is compatible with distinct but indiscernible particulars GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. The Bundle Theory I shall discuss is a theory about

More information

The impact of science on metaphysics and its limits

The impact of science on metaphysics and its limits The impact of science on metaphysics and its limits Michael Esfeld University of Lausanne, Department of Philosophy & Centre romand logic, history and philosophy of science CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland

More information

by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY USA phone: fax:

by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY USA phone: fax: WAVE FUNCTION ONTOLOGY by Bradley Monton Department of Philosophy, University of Kentucky, Lexington KY 40506 USA bmonton@uky.edu phone: 1-859-225-8430 fax: 1-859-257-3286 April 19, 2001 1 WAVE FUNCTION

More information

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) 1. The Copenhagen Interpretation Bohr interpreted quantum theory as showing that there is a fundamental partition in nature, between the microphysical

More information

Emergent Substances, Physical Properties, Action Explanations

Emergent Substances, Physical Properties, Action Explanations Dickinson College Dickinson Scholar Faculty and Staff Publications By Year Faculty and Staff Publications 12-2014 Emergent Substances, Physical Properties, Action Explanations Jeff Engelhardt Dickinson

More information

Searle on Emergence. Vladimír Havlík. The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague

Searle on Emergence. Vladimír Havlík. The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague Searle on Emergence Vladimír Havlík The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague Abstract: Searle s conception of ontological emergence is a basis for his explanation of mind and consciousness

More information

Durham E-Theses. Physicalism, Mind, and the Ontology of Properties KAIDA, DAISUKE

Durham E-Theses. Physicalism, Mind, and the Ontology of Properties KAIDA, DAISUKE Durham E-Theses Physicalism, Mind, and the Ontology of Properties KAIDA, DAISUKE How to cite: KAIDA, DAISUKE (2011) Physicalism, Mind, and the Ontology of Properties, Durham theses, Durham University.

More information

Phil 317: [handout #6] Donald Davidson: Mental Events

Phil 317: [handout #6] Donald Davidson: Mental Events Phil 317: [handout #6] Donald Davidson: Mental Events Professor JeeLoo Liu Davidson's Main Goal: 1. To discard type identity theory. 2. To lay out token identity theory. Terminology: * "nomological": lawful,

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms Part 2: Theoretical Terms 1. What Apparatus Is Available for Carrying out Analyses?

More information

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle

Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle Gunk Mountains: A Puzzle Sharon Berry Abstract This note points out a conflict between some common intuitions about metaphysical possibility. On the one hand, it is appealing to deny that there are robust

More information

Emergent proper+es and singular limits: the case of +me- irreversibility. Sergio Chibbaro Institut d Alembert Université Pierre et Marie Curie

Emergent proper+es and singular limits: the case of +me- irreversibility. Sergio Chibbaro Institut d Alembert Université Pierre et Marie Curie Emergent proper+es and singular limits: the case of +me- irreversibility Sergio Chibbaro Institut d Alembert Université Pierre et Marie Curie Introduction: Definition of emergence I J Kim 2000 The whole

More information

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate Richard Johns Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia johns@interchange.ubc.ca January 19, 2005 There are usually considered to be three main views

More information

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL THOMAS HOFWEBER PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL 1. PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AND HILBERT S PROGRAM Hilbert s program in the philosophy of mathematics comes in two parts. One part is a

More information

Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong

Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong Jessica Wilson Draft: July 23, 2012 Introduction Why care about what emergence is, and whether there is any? To start, many complex entities of our acquaintance

More information

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007 Russell s logicism Jeff Speaks September 26, 2007 1 Russell s definition of number............................ 2 2 The idea of reducing one theory to another.................... 4 2.1 Axioms and theories.............................

More information

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality? What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality? Quantum mechanics suggests that we perceive at most a tiny sliver of reality. Of course we already knew that! We knew that the visible

More information

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Ontology on Shaky Grounds 1 Ontology on Shaky Grounds Jean-Pierre Marquis Département de Philosophie Université de Montréal C.P. 6128, succ. Centre-ville Montréal, P.Q. Canada H3C 3J7 Jean-Pierre.Marquis@umontreal.ca In Realistic

More information

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles.

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles. Nomic Essentialism Ted Sider Structuralism seminar 1. Natural necessity Law of nature Causation Counterfactual Disposition Chance Rough unifying idea: these are modal, in that they involve tendencies and

More information

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Incompatibility Paradoxes Chapter 22 Incompatibility Paradoxes 22.1 Simultaneous Values There is never any difficulty in supposing that a classical mechanical system possesses, at a particular instant of time, precise values of

More information

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses Abstract Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006) argues for the disjunction thesis but against the conjunction thesis. I argue that accepting the disjunction thesis undermines his

More information

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere Identity in Physics and Elsewhere Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL 33124, USA E-mail: otaviobueno@mac.com 1. INTRODUCTION Is identity a fundamental concept? Of

More information

Physicalism and sparse ontology

Physicalism and sparse ontology Philos Stud (2009) 143:147 165 DOI 10.1007/s11098-007-9196-7 Physicalism and sparse ontology Kelly Trogdon Published online: 15 January 2008 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008 Abstract A major

More information

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition? What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition? Shan Gao Institute for the History of Natural Sciences, Chinese Academy of Sciences, Beijing 100190, China. E-mail: gaoshan@ihns.ac.cn. December

More information

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM Michele Caponigro ISHTAR, Bergamo University Abstract From conceptual point of view, we argue about the nature of reality inferred from EPR

More information

Part II A Reexamination of Contemporary Utilitarianism

Part II A Reexamination of Contemporary Utilitarianism Part II A Reexamination of Contemporary Utilitarianism In Part II of this book, we will turn to contemporary moral philosophers by this I mean twentieth-century philosophers who have reconstructed modern

More information

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2012 Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals

More information

Theory reduction by means of functional sub-types

Theory reduction by means of functional sub-types Theory reduction by means of functional sub-types Michael Esfeld & Christian Sachse University of Lausanne, Department of Philosophy CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland Michael-Andreas.Esfeld@unil.ch, Christian.Sachse@unil.ch

More information

Supervenience-based Formulations of Physicalism*

Supervenience-based Formulations of Physicalism* NO ^US 39:3 (2005) 426 459 Supervenience-based Formulations of Physicalism* JESSICA WILSON University of Michigan 0 Introduction The many and varied formulations of physicalism instantiate the following

More information

7.1 Significance of question: are there laws in S.S.? (Why care?) Possible answers:

7.1 Significance of question: are there laws in S.S.? (Why care?) Possible answers: I. Roberts: There are no laws of the social sciences Social sciences = sciences involving human behaviour (Economics, Psychology, Sociology, Political Science) 7.1 Significance of question: are there laws

More information

Mental Causation Is Not Just Downward Causation

Mental Causation Is Not Just Downward Causation Dickinson College Dickinson Scholar Faculty and Staff Publications By Year Faculty and Staff Publications 7-2015 Mental Causation Is Not Just Downward Causation Jeff Engelhardt Dickinson College Follow

More information

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning The aim of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning (MER) is to shed light on metaphysical necessity and the broader class of modal properties to which it belongs.

More information

Another Note on Zeno s Arrow

Another Note on Zeno s Arrow Another Note on Zeno s Arrow Ofra Magidor Abstract: In Physics VI.9 Aristotle addresses Zeno s four paradoxes of motion and amongst them the arrow paradox. In his brief remarks on the paradox, Aristotle

More information

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer Last time, when discussing the surprise exam paradox, we discussed the possibility that some claims could be true, but not knowable by certain individuals

More information

The mousetrap. Figure by MIT OCW.

The mousetrap. Figure by MIT OCW. Handout 8: Functionalism The Basic Idea behind various forms of behaviorism (see handout 6) is that to have a mind (or to be in such-and-such mental state) is to (be disposed to) behave in certain ways:

More information

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass? Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass? In 2 of his paper Markosian tries to spell out what he means to say when he says that time passes. Most of his discussion has to do with temporal language

More information

Commentary on Guarini

Commentary on Guarini University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Guarini Andrew Bailey Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Physicalism Feb , 2014

Physicalism Feb , 2014 Physicalism Feb. 12 14, 2014 Overview I Main claim Three kinds of physicalism The argument for physicalism Objections against physicalism Hempel s dilemma The knowledge argument Absent or inverted qualia

More information

Desire-as-belief revisited

Desire-as-belief revisited Desire-as-belief revisited Richard Bradley and Christian List June 30, 2008 1 Introduction On Hume s account of motivation, beliefs and desires are very di erent kinds of propositional attitudes. Beliefs

More information

Emergent Causation and Property Causation

Emergent Causation and Property Causation 6 Emergent Causation and Property Causation Paul Noordhof When we say that one thing caused another in virtue of certain of its properties, we attribute a case of property causation. A necessary condition

More information

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Ted Sider Modality seminar 1. Methodology The title of this book may sound to some readers like Good as Evil, or perhaps Cabbages as Kings. If logic and metaphysics

More information

Causation by Content?

Causation by Content? , 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Mind & Language, ISSN: 0268-1064 Vol. 14. No. 3 September 1999, pp 291 320. Causation by Content? PAUL NOORDHOF Abstract:

More information

Integrated Information Theory: Some Philosophical Issues. David Chalmers

Integrated Information Theory: Some Philosophical Issues. David Chalmers Integrated Information Theory: Some Philosophical Issues David Chalmers Two Issues What is consciousness, according to IIT? Are the axioms/postulates correct and complete? What is the metaphysical status

More information

FROM PHYSICS TO PHYSICALISM. a version of this paper is published in Physicalism and its Discontents

FROM PHYSICS TO PHYSICALISM. a version of this paper is published in Physicalism and its Discontents FROM PHYSICS TO PHYSICALISM a version of this paper is published in Physicalism and its Discontents ed, Gillett and Loewer Cambridge University Press 2001 Introduction Hilary Putnam explains that: The

More information

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Darrell P. Rowbottom This paper shows that Popper s measure of corroboration is inapplicable if, as Popper also argued, the logical probability of synthetic

More information

Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism. David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3

Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism. David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3 Structuralism and the Limits of Skepticism David Chalmers Thalheimer Lecture 3 Skepticism and Realism I Skepticism: We don t know whether external things exist Realism: External things exist Anti-Realism:

More information

Department of Philosophy TCD. Is Physicalism the True Philosophy?

Department of Philosophy TCD. Is Physicalism the True Philosophy? Department of Philosophy TCD Is Physicalism the True Philosophy? Tom Farrell Department of Philosophy TCD Department of Clinical Medicine RCSI Department of Anatomy RCSI TCD 20 March 2018 Philosophy? Casual

More information

First-Degree Entailment

First-Degree Entailment March 5, 2013 Relevance Logics Relevance logics are non-classical logics that try to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication: p (q p) p (p q) (p q) (q r) (p p) q p (q q) p (q q) Counterintuitive?

More information

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008 [Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism Professor JeeLoo Liu The debate: On the nature of persisting material objects [Three-Dimensionalism]:

More information

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification By Wesley Salmon Analysis by Margarita Georgieva, PSTS student, number 0102458 Van Lochemstraat 9-17 7511 EG Enschede Final Paper for Philosophy of Science

More information

Can bare dispositions explain categorical regularities?

Can bare dispositions explain categorical regularities? Can bare dispositions explain categorical regularities? Tyler Hildebrand hildebrt@uw.edu Abstract One of the traditional desiderata for a metaphysical theory of laws of nature is that it be able to explain

More information

The Supervenience Argument, Overdetermination, and Causal Drainage: Assessing Kim s Master Argument. Sven Walter. Institute of Cognitive Science

The Supervenience Argument, Overdetermination, and Causal Drainage: Assessing Kim s Master Argument. Sven Walter. Institute of Cognitive Science The Supervenience Argument, Overdetermination, and Causal Drainage: Assessing Kim s Master Argument Sven Walter Institute of Cognitive Science University of Osnabrueck Albrechtstraße 28 D-49069 Osnabrueck

More information

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014 Evidence and Theory in Physics Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014 Two Features of Physics Physics displays two interesting features: 1) Programmatically, it aspires to be completely

More information

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality Searle s Account Of The Problem In this essay, Searle emphasizes the notion of Intentional content, rather than the cluster of descriptions that Kripke uses to characterize

More information

Weak and Global Supervenience: Functional Bark and Metaphysical Bite?

Weak and Global Supervenience: Functional Bark and Metaphysical Bite? Weak and Global Supervenience: Functional Bark and Metaphysical Bite? Draft Date: 6/2/00 Mark Moyer Abstract Weak and global supervenience are equivalent to strong supervenience for intrinsic properties.

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES

PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES i PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES Edited by WILFRID SELLARS and HERBERT FEIGL with the advice and assistance of PAUL MEEHL, JOHN HOSPERS, MAY BRODBECK VOLUME XVII Contents October 1966 NUMBER 5 Do ReIations Individuate?

More information

Tooley on backward causation

Tooley on backward causation Tooley on backward causation Paul Noordhof Michael Tooley has argued that, if backward causation (of a certain kind) is possible, then a Stalnaker-Lewis account of the truth conditions of counterfactuals

More information

Lowe s argument for dualism from mental causation Philosophia 33 (2005), p

Lowe s argument for dualism from mental causation Philosophia 33 (2005), p Max Kistler Département de philosophie Université Paris X-Nanterre and Institut Jean Nicod 1 bis, avenue de Lowendal 75007 Paris, France e-mail: kistler@free.fr Lowe s argument for dualism from mental

More information

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS JEFFREY A. BARRETT In the long version of his Ph.D. thesis, Hugh Everett III developed pure wave mechanics as a way of solving the quantum measurement

More information

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design Sebastian Lutz Draft: 2011 02 14 Abstract Two common and plausible claims in the philosophy of science are that (i) a theory that makes no predictions is not testable

More information

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge 1 3 Conceivability and Modal Knowledge Christopher Hill ( 2006 ) provides an account of modal knowledge that is set in a broader context of arguing against the view that conceivability provides epistemic

More information

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction Chapter 25 Hardy s Paradox 25.1 Introduction Hardy s paradox resembles the Bohm version of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox, discussed in Chs. 23 and 24, in that it involves two correlated particles,

More information

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000):

Simply Possible. Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000): Simply Possible Theodore Sider Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2000): 585 590 Abstract In the process of arguing against all theories of extended material objects made up of simples, Dean

More information

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY PRESENTIST TIME TRAVEL AND THE LIMITS OF PRESENTIST CAUSALITY COMMENTATOR: MICHAEL NELSON UNIVERSITY

More information

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 (The Philosophical Review 122 (2013): 522 525) Jill North This is a neat little book (138 pages without appendices, under 200 with).

More information

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION: QUANTUM PHILOSOPHY PCES 4.41 Perhaps the most difficult things to understand about QM are (i) how to reconcile our common sense ideas about physical reality with phenomena such as entanglement, & (ii)

More information

QUANTITY AND QUALITY: NATURALNESS IN METAPHYSICS MAYA EDDON

QUANTITY AND QUALITY: NATURALNESS IN METAPHYSICS MAYA EDDON QUANTITY AND QUALITY: NATURALNESS IN METAPHYSICS by MAYA EDDON A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism 17.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 69-82. We will now try to assess the impact of Relativity Theory on the debate

More information

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness?

What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness? What is it like to be a quantum observer? And what does it imply about the nature of consciousness? Shan Gao Research Center for Philosophy of Science and Technology, Shanxi University, Taiyuan 030006,

More information

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes Outline: 1. Homework 4 (discuss reading assignment) 2. The Measurement Problem 3. GRW theory Handouts: None Homework: Yes Vocabulary/Equations:

More information

Physicalism and the Part-Whole Relation

Physicalism and the Part-Whole Relation Physicalism and the Part-Whole Relation Andreas Hüttemann/Universität zu Köln Abstract: In this paper I intend to analyse whether a certain kind of physicalism (part-wholephysicalism) is supported by what

More information

Physics, Time and Determinism

Physics, Time and Determinism Physics, Time and Determinism M.P. Vaughan Free will and determinism Some definitions: 1. Free will is the capacity of an agent to chose a particular outcome 2. Determinism is the notion that all events

More information

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds

Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds Kaplan s Paradox and Epistemically Possible Worlds 1. Epistemically possible worlds David Chalmers Metaphysically possible worlds: S is metaphysically possible iff S is true in some metaphysically possible

More information

The Metaphysics of Mental Causation

The Metaphysics of Mental Causation The Metaphysics of Mental Causation The Exclusion Problem Revisited, Reconsidered and Resolved ANDERS STRAND Ph.D. Thesis in Philosophy Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Art and Ideas Ph.D.

More information

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Jeremy Goodman Draft of February 23, 2015 Abstract An analysis of counterfactuals in terms of the comparative similarity of possible worlds is widely attributed

More information

Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness

Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness Chris Kennedy Seminar on Vagueness University of Chicago 25 April, 2006 Model-theoretic Vagueness vs. Epistemic Vagueness 1 Model-theoretic vagueness The supervaluationist analyses of vagueness developed

More information

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Philosophy 691: Conditionals Northern Illinois University Fall 2011 Geoff Pynn terminology 1. Chapters 10-18 concern subjunctive conditionals, which Bennett distinguishes

More information