The connection of skew Boolean algebras and discriminator varieties to Church algebras

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The connection of skew Boolean algebras and discriminator varieties to Church algebras"

Transcription

1 The connection of skew Boolean algebras and discriminator varieties to Church algebras Karin Cvetko-Vah and Antonino Salibra Abstract. We establish a connection between skew Boolean algebras and Church algebras. We prove that the set of all semicentral elements in a right Church algebra forms a right-handed skew Boolean algebra for the properly defined operations. The main result of this paper states that the variety of all semicentral right Church algebras of type τ is term equivalent to the variety of right-handed skew Boolean algebras with additional regular operations. As a corollary to this result we show that a pointed variety is a discriminator variety if and only if it is a 0-regular variety of right-handed skew Boolean algebras. 1. Introduction Skew Boolean algebras are non-commutative one-pointed generalisations of (possibly generalised) Boolean algebras. A typical example of a skew Boolean algebra is provided by the algebra of all partial functions from a given set A to {0, 1}, with properly defined operations. Just as Boolean algebras have a lattice reduct, skew Boolean algebras have a skew lattice reduct, to be defined below. By a result of Leech [11] every skew lattice S embeds into the direct product of a right-handed and a left-handed skew lattice, called the right and left factors of S (See Section 2.3 for definitions of right- and left-handedness). It follows that right- and left-handed skew lattices are not just special cases of skew Boolean algebras but rather reveal significant structures. For instance, it was proven in [5] that a skew lattice S satisfies an equational identity if and only if both the left and the right factor of S satisfy that equational identity. The significance of skew Boolean algebras is revealed in part by a result of Leech [12] stating that any right-handed skew Boolean algebra can be embedded into some skew Boolean algebra of partial functions. This result has been further explored in [1] and [9], where results show that any skew Boolean algebra is dual to a sheaf over a locally-compact Boolean space. Skew Boolean algebras are closely related to pointed discriminator varieties, i.e. discriminator varieties with a constant term. To see this, one needs skew Boolean intersection algebras, i.e. skew Boolean algebras that are closed under finite infima with respect to the natural partial order which is defined precisely in the next section. We denote by P D 0 the pointed discriminator variety of type (3, 0) generated by the class of all pointed discriminator algebras 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary: 03G10; Secondary: 08B26. Key words and phrases: skew Boolean algebra, Church algebra, discriminator variety, factor congruence, decomposition operator.

2 2 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. (A; d, 0), where d is the discriminator function on A and 0 is a nullary operation. By a result of Bignall and Leech [3] the variety P D 0 is term equivalent to the variety of all right-handed skew Boolean intersection algebras. The key observation motivating the introduction of Church algebras [14] is that many algebras arising in completely different fields of mathematics - including Heyting algebras, rings with unit, or combinatory algebras - have a term operation q satisfying the fundamental properties of the if-then-else connective: q(1, x, y) = x and q(0, x, y) = y. As simple as they may appear, these properties are enough to yield rather strong results. We mention here that central elements in the sense of Vaggione [18] are especially convenient to work with because they can be given a simple equational characterisation in Church algebras. A central element a of a Church algebra satisfies the identities q(a, a, 0) = a = q(a, 1, a) and determines a pair (θ a, θ a ) of complementary factor congruences. The identity q(a, a, 0) = a implies that θ a equals the principal congruence θ(a, 0) and, similarly, the identity q(a, 1, a) = a implies θ a = θ(a, 1). We also mention that central elements of a Church algebra constitute a Boolean algebra with respect to the operations x y = q(x, y, 0), x y = q(x, 1, y) and x = q(x, 0, 1). In [16] the notion of a Boolean-like algebra was introduced as a generalisation of a Boolean algebra. A Boolean-like algebra is a Church algebra A such that every a A is central. Boolean-like varieties can be characterised in terms of discriminator varieties: a double-pointed variety V of a given type τ is a Boolean-like variety iff V is a discriminator variety such that A = 2 for every subdirectly irreducible member A of V. It also turns out that some important properties of Boolean algebras are shared not only by Boolean-like algebras, but also by algebras whose elements satisfy all the equational conditions of central elements except x = q(x, 1, x). These algebras, and the varieties they form, were termed idempotent semi- Boolean-like in [16]. Idempotent semi-boolean-like algebras are closely related to double-pointed discriminator varieties. Actually, a double-pointed variety is a discriminator variety iff it is idempotent semi-boolean-like and 0-regular [16, Theorem 5.6]. In the present paper we study how skew Boolean algebras are connected to Church algebras. Our aim is to compare the characterisation of one-pointed discriminator varieties by Bignall and Leech [3] to the characterization of double-pointed discriminator varieties by Salibra et al. [16]. In Section 3 we introduce the one-pointed version of Church algebras. We define a right (resp. left) Church algebra as an arbitrary algebra of a given type τ with a fixed ternary term q and a constant 0 that satisfy the identity q(0, x, y) = y (resp. q(0, x, y) = x). We generalise the notation of a central element and introduce the notion of a semicentral element that satisfies all the equational conditions of central elements except q(x, 1, x) = x. In Section 4 we introduce semicentral right Church algebras as right Church algebras with all elements being semicentral. We show that operations can be defined on the set S(A)

3 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 3 of all semicentral elements in a right Church algebra A such that S(A) with these operations forms a right-handed skew Boolean algebra. We prove that the variety of all semicentral right Church algebras of type τ is term equivalent to the variety of right-handed skew Boolean algebras with additional regular operations. In Section 5 we study the connection with discriminator varieties and prove that a pointed variety is a discriminator variety if and only if it is a 0-regular variety of semicentral right Church algebras. New systems of axioms for skew Boolean intersection algebras are provided. 2. Preliminaries If A is an algebra and x, y A, then θ(x, y) denotes the least congruence on A including the pair (x, y). We denote respectively by, the least and the greatest congruence of the congruence lattice Con(A) Factor congruences. Definition 1. A congruence φ on an algebra A is a factor congruence if there exists another congruence φ such that φ φ = and φ φ =. In this case we call (φ, φ) a pair of complementary factor congruences. Under the hypotheses of Definition 1 the homomorphism f : A A/φ A/ φ defined by f(x) = (x/φ, x/ φ) is an isomorphism. Hence, we have: (φ, φ) is a pair of complementary factor congruences of A if, and only if, A = A/φ A/ φ under the natural map x (x/φ, x/ φ). So, the existence of factor congruences is just another way of saying this algebra is a direct product of simpler algebras. The set of factor congruences of A is not, in general, a sublattice of Con(A). and are the trivial factor congruences, corresponding to A = A B, where B is a trivial algebra; of course, B is isomorphic to A/ and A is isomorphic to A/. An algebra A is directly indecomposable if it admits only the two trivial factor congruences ( and ). Clearly, every simple algebra is directly indecomposable, while there are algebras which are directly indecomposable but not simple: they have congruences, which however do not split the algebra up neatly as a Cartesian product Decomposition operations. Factor congruences can be characterised in terms of certain algebra homomorphisms called decomposition operations (see [15, Def. 4.32] for more details). Definition 2. Let A be an algebra of type τ. A decomposition operation on A is a function f : A A A satisfying the following conditions: f(x, x) = x; f(f(x, y), z) = f(x, z) = f(x, f(y, z)); f is an algebra homomorphism from A A into A.

4 4 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. When τ =, the third condition of Definition 2 is redundant. There exists a bijective correspondence between pairs of complementary factor congruences and decomposition operations, and thus, between decomposition operations and factorisations like A = B C. Proposition 1. [15, Thm. 4.33] Let A be an algebra of type τ. Given a decomposition operation f on A, the binary relations θ f and θ f defined by: x θ f y if, and only if, f(x, y) = x, x θ f y if, and only if, f(x, y) = y, form a pair of complementary factor congruences. Conversely, given a pair (φ, φ) of complementary factor congruences, the function f defined by: f(x, y) = u if, and only if, yφu φx, (2.1) determines a decomposition operation on A such that φ = θ f and φ = θ f. Notice that if (φ, φ) is a pair of complementary factor congruences, then for all x and y there is just one element u such that yφu φx Skew Lattices. We review some basic definitions and results on a noncommutative generalisation of lattices, probably the most interesting and successful: the concept of skew lattice [11], in fact, along with the related notion of skew Boolean algebra, has important connections with discriminator varieties; the interested reader is referred to [13] or [17] for far more comprehensive accounts. Definition 3. A skew lattice is an algebra A = (A,, ) of type (2, 2) satisfying: Associativity: x (y z) = (x y) z; Idempotence: x x = x = x x Absorption: x (x y) = x = x (x y); x (y z) = (x y) z (y x) x = x = (y x) x It is not difficult to see that the absorption condition is equivalent to the following pair of biconditionals: x y = y iff x y = x; and x y = x iff x y = y. Definition 4. A skew lattice A is called left-zero ( right-zero) if a b = a (a b = b) for all a, b A. Skew lattices that are as noncommutative as possible are rectangular skew lattices. They include left-zero (right-zero) skew lattices and other remarkable examples. Definition 5. A skew lattice is rectangular if it satisfies the identity x y = y x. We collect in the next lemma and propositions some useful properties of rectangular skew lattices.

5 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 5 Lemma 1. The following conditions are equivalent for a skew lattice A: (1) A is rectangular. (2) A satisfies x y x = x. (3) A satisfies x (y x) = y x. (4) A satisfies (y x) y = y x. (5) A satisfies x y x = x. (6) A satisfies (x y) x = x y. (7) A satisfies y (x y) = x y. (8) A satisfies x y z = x z. (9) A satisfies x y z = x z. Proposition 2. Every rectangular skew lattice A is isomorphic to a direct product of a left-zero skew lattice and a right-zero skew lattice. Proof. Define X = {x A : x A} and Y = {A x : x A}. It is not difficult to show that A can be embedded into X Y via the mapping f(x) = (x A, A x). Every rectangular skew lattice is completely distributive: the identities x (y z) = (x y) (x z) and (y z) x = (y x) (z x) are satisfied for {, } = {, }. Lemma 2. In any skew lattice the relation, defined by a b iff a b = a = b a or equivalently a b = b = b a, is a partial ordering. Observe that a b a a a b a for every a, b. Define x = {y : y x} and x = {y : y x}. It can be seen that x = {x y x : y A} and x = {x y x : y A} are subalgebras of A, by means of which we can identify further interesting subclasses of skew lattices: Definition 6. A skew lattice A is normal if x is a lattice for every x; it is Boolean if x is a Boolean lattice for every x A. Normal skew lattices are a variety, axiomatized relative to skew lattices by the equation x y z x = x z y x. In any skew lattice A we define a preorder: a d b iff a b a = a iff b a b = b. Observe that a b d a d a b and b a d a d b a, for every a, b. The equivalence induced by d, denoted as D, is in fact a congruence, and A/D is the maximal lattice image of A. The D-equivalence class D a of an element a is {a} iff, for all b A, a b = b a. We remark that D a D b in A/D iff a b a = a in A.

6 6 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. Proposition 3. Let A be a skew lattice. (1) If a, b D x then a b, a b D x. (2) If B is a rectangular subalgebra of A, then adb for all a, b B. (3) For every a, D a is a maximal rectangular subalgebra of A. Proposition 4 ([11]). Let A be a skew lattice and let x, y be members of A/D. (1) If x y, then for each a x there exists b y such that a b in A, and dually, for each b y there exists a x such that a b in A. (2) Let c x A/D y be given and pick a x and b y such that c a, b in A. Then c = a b = b a in A. Thus: x A/D y = {a b : a x, b y, and a b = b a}. Similar considerations hold for A/D. We have that: Proposition 5. Every skew lattice is regular, i.e., it satisfies the identities x y x z x = x y z x and x y x z x = x y z x. Two further preorders can be defined on a skew lattice: (1) x l y iff x y = x; (2) x r y iff y x = x. The equivalences L and R, respectively induced by l and r, are again congruences. Definition 7. A skew lattice is left-handed ( right-handed) if L = D (R = D). L (R) is the minimal congruence making A/L (A/R) a right-handed (lefthanded) skew lattice. Lemma 3. The following conditions are equivalent for a skew lattice A: (1) A is right-handed; (2) for all a, b A, adb implies a b = b; (3) for all a, b A, a b a = b a Skew Boolean algebras. If we expand the skew lattice signature by adjoining a subtraction operation and a constant 0, we get the following noncommutative variant of Boolean algebras (see [12]). Definition 8. A skew Boolean algebra ( SBA, for short) is an algebra A = (A,,, \, 0) of type (2, 2, 2, 0) such that: its reduct (A,, ) is a normal skew lattice satisfying the identities x (y z) = (x y) (x z) and (y z) x = (y x) (z x). Both x 0 = 0 = 0 x and x 0 = x = 0 x hold. the operation \ satisfies the identities (x y x) (x \ y) = x = (x \ y) (x y x); x y x (x \ y) = 0 = (x \ y) x y x.

7 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 7 The commutative SBAs are precisely the class of all generalised Boolean algebras. Recall that SBAs satisfy the generalised De Morgan laws: x \ (y z) = (x \ y) (x \ z) and x \ (y z) = (x \ y) (x \ z). An SBA is primitive if it consists of exactly two D-classes: A > {0}, where A is a rectangular skew lattice. Of interest here are right-handed cases, whose operations have the following descriptions for x, y 0: 0 y 0 0 y x x x 0 y x 0 y \ 0 y x x 0 Particularly important are the right-handed SBAs 3 R and its subalgebra 2 R with respective D-class structures {1, 2} > {0} and {1} > {0}. To within isomorphism, 3 R and 2 R are the only nontrivial subdirectly irreducible righthanded SBAs. Thus every right-handed SBA is a subdirect product of copies of 3 R and/or 2 R. As a consequence an equation is an identity on all right-handed SBAs if and only if it holds on 3 R. In general, the right-handed primitive SBAs are the directly indecomposable right-handed SBAs. Lemma 4 below yields some further easily verified identities that simplify computation in right-handed SBAs. Lemma 4. Let A be a right-handed SBA and x, y, z A. Then: (1) (x y) \ z = (x \ z) (y \ z), (2) (x y) \ z = (x \ z) (y \ z), (3) x (y \ z) = (x y) \ (x z), (4) (x \ y) \ z = (x \ z) \ (y \ z), (5) x \ (y \ z) = (x \ y) (x z x). Proof. All five equations are easily seen to hold on 3 R. Thus they hold on right-handed SBAs. Lemma 5. For right-handed SBAs the following are equivalent: (1) xdy; (2) x y = y & y x = x; (3) x y = x & y x = y; (4) x \ y = 0 & y \ x = 0; (5) z, x z = y z; (6) z, z \ x = z \ y. SBAs such that every finite subset of their universe has an infimum w.r.t. the underlying natural partial ordering of the algebra stand out for their significance. We denote the infimum of x and y w.r.t. the natural partial order by x y and refer to the operation as intersection in order to distinguish it from the skew lattice meet. It turns out that SBAs with the additional

8 8 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. operation can be given an equational characterisation provided we include the operation into the signature. Definition 9. A skew Boolean -algebra is an algebra (A;,,, \, 0) of type (2, 2, 2, 2, 0) s.t.: the reduct (A;,, \, 0) is an SBA and the reduct (A; ) is a meet semilattice; A satisfies the identities x (x y x) = x y x; x (x y) = x y = (x y) x. The next theorem by Bignall and Leech [3] provides a powerful bridge between the theories of SBAs and pointed discriminator varieties: Theorem 1. (i) The variety of type (3, 0) generated by the class of all pointed discriminator algebras (A; t, 0), where t is the discriminator function on A and 0 is a constant, is term equivalent to the variety of right handed skew Boolean -algebras. (ii) Every discriminator variety is term equivalent to a variety V of right handed skew Boolean -algebras with additional operations (g i ) i I such that, for all algebras A V, every congruence θ on the term reduct (A; t, 0) is compatible with g i for all i I. 3. Right (Left) Church algebras We recall that a Church algebra [14] is a double-pointed algebra with a term operation q satisfying the fundamental properties of the if-then-else connective: q(1, x, y) = x and q(0, x, y) = y. To compare Church algebras and SBAs, in the following definition we introduce the one-pointed counterpart of Church algebras. Definition 10. A right (resp. left) Church algebra (RCA) (resp. LCA) is an algebra A of type τ, where we fix a ternary term q and a constant 0 such that q(0, x, y) = y (resp. q(0, x, y) = x). Of course, every pointed algebra is an RCA (LCA), because the third (second) projection map is a term. The notion of an RCA (LCA) is a terminological convenience, to be supplemented by further demands in the main results of the paper. A 0 = (A, q, 0) is the pure reduct of A. The following right (resp. left) derived operations will be important in the remaining part of the paper: x y = q(x, x, y) (resp. x y = q(y, x, y)); x y = q(x, y, 0) (resp. x y = q(y, 0, x)); y \ x = q(x, 0, y) (resp. y \ x = q(x, y, 0)).

9 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 9 Without loss of generality, in the following we develop the theory of RCAs. An element x of an RCA is idempotent if x x = x. Example 1. The following are examples of RCAs: 1. Lattices with bottom, where q(x, y, z) = (x y) z. 2. SBAs, where q(x, y, z) = (x y) (z \ x) (see Section 4.1). 3. Rings, where q(x, y, z) = xy + z xz (see Section 6) Factor Elements. An element e of an RCA is a factor element if the binary operation q(e,, ) is a decomposition operation. If e is a factor element, then by Proposition 1 the relations θ e = {(x, y) : q(e, x, y) = x} and θ e = {(x, y) : q(e, x, y) = y} constitute a pair of complementary factor congruences of A. We denote by F(A) the set of factor elements of an RCA A. The following trivial proposition equationally characterises the factor elements. Proposition 6. A factor element e satisfies the following identities for all x, y, z, x, y A: (A1) q(e, x, x) = x. (A2) q(e, q(e, x, y), z) = q(e, x, z) = q(e, x, q(e, y, z)). (A3) q(e, g(x 1,..., x n ), g(y 1,..., y n )) = g(q(e, x 1, y 1 ),..., q(e, x n, y n )), for every g τ. Of interest is the fact that the set of all factor elements of an RCA forms a subalgebra of the pure reduct. Proposition 7. Let A be an RCA. Then F(A) is a subalgebra of the pure reduct A 0. Proof. Let a, b, c be factor elements and let d = q(a, b, c). We show that d is also a factor element. q(d, x, x) = q(d, q(a, x, x), q(a, x, x)) by (A1) = q(a, q(b, x, x), q(c, x, x)) by (A3) = q(a, x, x) by (A1) = x by (A1) q(d, q(d, x, y), z) = q(d, q(a, q(b, x, y), q(c, x, y)), z) by (A3) = q(a, q(b, q(b, x, y), z), q(c, q(c, x, y), z)) by (A3) = q(a, q(b, x, z), q(c, x, z)) by (A2) = q(d, x, z) by (A3) Similarly for q(d, x, q(d, y, z)) = q(d, x, z).

10 10 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. In the following we apply in each line axiom (A3). q(d, g( x), g(ȳ)) = q(a, q(b, g( x), g(ȳ)), q(c, g( x), g(ȳ))) = q(a, g(..., q(b, x i, y i ),... ), g(... q(c, x i, y i ),... )) = g(..., q(a, q(b, x i, y i ), q(c, x i, y i )),... ) = g(..., q(d, x i, y i ),... ) Proposition 8. Let A be an RCA, e A be a factor element, and s e, t e : A A be two maps defined by t e (x) = e x and s e (x) = x \ e. Then the following conditions hold: (1) t e and s e are endomorphisms of the pure reduct A 0. (2) ker(s e ) = θ e and ker(t e ) = θ e. Proof. (1) The map t e is a homomorphism: t e (q(x)) = e q(x) = q(e, q(x), 0) by def of = q(e, q(x), q(0)) by q(0, 0, 0) = 0 = q(q(e, x 1, 0), q(e, x 2, 0), q(e, x 3, 0)) by (A3) = q(t e (x 1 ), t e (x 2 ), t e (x 3 )). The proof is similar for the map s e. (2) We show that ker(t e ) = {(x, y) : q(e, x, y) = y}. Assume t e (x) = t e (y). Then q(e, x, y) = q(e, q(e, x, 0), y) by (A2) = q(e, q(e, y, 0), y) by e x = e y = q(e, y, y) by (A2) = y by (A1) In the opposite direction, let q(e, x, y) = y. Then we have: q(e, y, 0) = Hp. q(e, q(e, x, y), 0) = (A2) q(e, x, 0). We show that ker(s e ) = {(x, y) : q(e, x, y) = x}. Assume s e (x) = s e (y). Then q(e, x, y) = q(e, x, q(e, 0, y)) by (A2) = q(e, x, q(e, 0, x)) by x \ e = y \ e = q(e, x, x) by (A2) = x by (A1) In the opposite direction, let q(e, x, y) = x. Then we have: q(e, 0, x) = Hp. q(e, 0, q(e, x, y)) = (A2) q(e, 0, y).

11 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras Semicentral Elements. We recall from [16] that an element e of a Church algebra is central if it is a factor element (in the terminology of Section 3.1) satisfying the identity q(e, 1, 0) = e. This last condition can be split into two identities, the first one expressed in terms of the constant 0 and the second one in terms of the constant 1. Proposition 9. Let e be a factor element of a Church algebra A = (A, q, 0, 1). Then the following conditions are equivalent: (1) q(e, 1, 0) = e; (2) q(e, e, 0) = e and q(e, 1, e) = e; Proof. (1) (2). q(e, e, 0) = q(e, q(e, 1, 0), 0) = (A2) q(e, 1, 0) = e and similarly q(e, 1, e) = q(e, 1, q(e, 1, 0)) = (A2) q(e, 1, 0) = e. (2) (1). Let (θ e, θ e ) be the pair of complementary factor congruences associated with e. From the hypothesis and the definition of θ e, θ e it follows that eθ e 0 and 1 θ e e. Since θ e, θ e are congruences, then 0θ e e and e θ e 1. It follows that q(e, 0, e) = 0 and q(e, e, 1) = 1. Then we conclude the proof as follows: q(e, 1, 0) = q(e, q(e, e, 1), q(e, 0, e)) = (A2) q(e, e, e) = (A1) e. Proposition 10. In the hypothesis of the above proposition we have: q(e, e, 0) = e iff θ e = θ(e, 0); q(e, 1, e) = e iff θ e = θ(e, 1). Proof. If q(e, e, 0) = e, then θ(e, 0) {(x, y) : q(e, x, y) = x} = θ e. Conversely, if q(e, x, y) = x, then, by e θ(e, 0) 0 we have x = q(e, x, y) θ(e, 0) q(0, x, y) = y. The second equivalence can be proven in a similar way. Since RCAs are one-pointed algebras, we introduce semicentral elements as the best approximation to central elements of Church algebras. Definition 11. A factor element e of an RCA A is called semicentral if it is idempotent; that is, it satisfies the following further axiom: (A4) q(e, e, 0) = e. We denote by S(A) the set of semicentral elements of A. If e is semicentral, then the pair (θ e, θ e ) of complementary factor congruences determined by the decomposition operation q(e,, ) has a good behaviour. Proposition 11. Let A be an RCA and e A be semicentral. Then, (i) θ e = θ(e, 0), the minimal congruence relating e and 0. (ii) The congruence θ e permutes with every congruence, i.e., φ θ e = θ e φ for every congruence φ Con(A). (iii) a, b A, aθ e q(e, b, a)θ e b. Proof. (i) By the proof of Proposition 10. (ii) Let aφbθ e c for some b. By aφb we have q(e, c, a)φq(e, c, b) and by bθ e c we have q(e, c, b) = c. Moreover, aθ e q(e, c, a) holds because q(e, a, q(e, c, a)) = (A2) q(e, a, a) = (A1) a. In conclusion, aθ e q(e, c, a)φc.

12 12 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. (iii) Since (θ e, θ e ) is a pair of complementary factor congruences, then there exists a unique u such that bθ e uθ e a. Notice that 0θ e e follows from q(e, e, 0) = e. Then we have: a = q(0, b, a)θ e q(e, b, a)θ e q(e, b, u) = b, where the conclusion q(e, b, u) = b follows from the assumption bθ e u. In the following proposition we show that q(x, x, 0) is semicentral for every factor element x. Proposition 12. Let A be an RCA. Then (S(A), q, 0) is a retract of (F(A), q, 0) through the onto homomorphism f : F(A) S(A) defined by f(x) = q(x, x, 0). Proof. Let x, y, z be factor elements. We show that f is a homomorphism: q(f(x), f(y), f(z)) = q(f(x), q(x, f(y), f(y)), q(x, f(z), f(z))) by (A1) = q(x, q(x, q(y, y, 0), q(z, z, 0)), q(z, z, 0)) by (A3) = q(x, q(y, y, 0), q(z, z, 0)) by (A2) = q(q(x, y, z), q(x, y, z), 0) by (A3) = f(q(x, y, z)) by def. f By Proposition 7 q(x, x, 0) is a factor element if x is such. We now show that q(x, x, 0) is idempotent: q(q(x, x, 0), q(x, x, 0), 0) = q(x, q(x, x, 0), 0) by (A3), (A1) = q(x, x, 0) by (A2) 4. Semicentral RCAs In a generic RCA there is no need for the set of semicentral elements to comprise all of the algebra. In this section, we define under the name of semicentral RCA those RCAs where this actually happens. We prove that every variety of semicentral RCAs is term equivalent to a variety of right-handed SBAs with additional operations. Definition 12. An RCA is called a semicentral RCA ( SRCA, for short) if every element is semicentral. An SRCA is thus a pointed algebra A of type τ for which a ternary term operation q is defined such that q(0, x, y) = y. q(x, x, 0) = x. q(x, y, y) = y. q(w, q(w, x, y), z) = q(w, x, z) = q(w, x, q(w, y, z)). w, q(w,, ) : A A A is a homomorphism w.r.t. the τ-operations. Given an RCA A, by Proposition 12 the algebra (S(A), q, 0) of all semicentral elements of A is an SRCA. The set S(A) is not in general closed under the operations of type τ.

13 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 13 Example 2. Every algebra in a one-pointed discriminator variety is an SRCA with respect to the ternary term operation q(x, y, z) = s(x, 0, z, y). Example 3. Let P f (X) be the set of all finite subsets of a set X. Define a ternary operation on P f (X) as follows: q P (F, G, H) = (G F ) (H \ F ), for all F, G, H f X. Then the algebra (P f (X), q P, ) is an SRCA. Example 4. (see [7]) Let F(X, Y ) be the set of all finite functions from X into Y. If f F(X, Y ) then dom(f) is a finite subset of X. Then the algebra (F(X, Y ), q F, 0) is an SRCA, where 0 = is the empty function; For all finite functions f : F Y, g : G Y and h : H Y (F, G, H f X), q F (f, g, h) = g G F h H\F. The following characterisation of the directly indecomposable SRCAs will be useful in the proof of the main theorem of Section 4.1. Lemma 6. Let A be an RCA. Then A is a directly indecomposable SRCA if, and only if, for all x, y, z A: { y if x 0; q(x, y, z) = z if x = 0. Proof. ( ) Given the assumption on A, for each x A, either θ x = and θ x = or θ x = and θ x =. If x 0, then θ x = θ(x, 0) = {(y, z) : q(x, y, z) = y} =, making q(x, y, z) = y for all y, z. ( ) A is an SRCA because, for every x 0, the condition yz(q(x, y, z) = y) implies that x is semicentral. By the way of contradiction, assume now A to be directly decomposable. Let (φ, φ) be a pair of nontrivial complementary factor congruences, and let a 0. Since φ φ =, then there exists b A such that 0φb φa. We have two cases. (b = 0): from 0 φa it follows that y = q(0, x, y) φq(a, x, y) = x, contradicting the nontriviality of φ. (b 0): from 0φb it follows that y = q(0, x, y)φq(b, x, y) = x, contradicting the nontriviality of φ. In particular, the rule for q in Lemma 6 holds in every subdirectly irreducible SRCA A term equivalence result. In this section we prove that every variety of SRCAs of type τ is term equivalent to a variety of right-handed SBAs with additional regular operations.

14 14 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. We start with the pure case, where τ = {q, 0}. Consider the following correspondence between the algebraic similarity types of SBAs and of pure SRCAs. Beginning on the SBA side: q(x, y, z) := (x y) (z \ x) and 0 := 0 Beginning on the SRCA side: x y := q(x, x, y), x y := q(x, y, 0) y \ x := q(x, 0, y) and again 0 := 0. If B is an SBA, then B q = (B; q, 0) denotes the corresponding algebra in the similarity type of SRCAs. Similarly, if A is an SRCA, then A = (A;,, \, 0) denotes the corresponding algebra in the similarity type of SBAs. Theorem 2. The above correspondences define a term equivalence between the varieties of pure SRCAs and of right-handed SBAs. More precisely, (i) If A is a pure SRCA, then A is a right-handed SBA; (ii) If B is a right-handed SBA, then B q is a pure SRCA; (iii) (A ) q = A and (B q ) = B. Proof. Given a subdirectly irreducible SRCA, by Lemma 6 we have: { x if x 0; x y = q(x, x, y) = y if x = 0. { y if x 0; x y = q(x, y, 0) = 0 if x = 0. { 0 if x 0; y \ x = q(x, 0, y) = y if x = 0. But these are primitive right-handed SBA operations. Thus the derived algebra of a subdirectly irreducible SRCA satisfies all identities holding for all righthanded SBAs. Since any SRCA A is a subdirect product of irreducible cases, the derived algebra A = (A;,, \, 0) is a right-handed SBA. Conversely, if B is a primitive right-handed SBA, setting q(x, y, z) = (x y) (z \ x), one has { y if x 0; q(x, y, z) = z if x = 0. Thus (B, q, 0) is a directly indecomposable SRCA by Lemma 6. Hence, for any right-handed SBA B, B q = (B, q, 0) is an SRCA since right-handed SBAs are subdirect products of right-handed primitive SBAs. That (A ) q = A and (B q ) = B are easily seen when A and B are subdirectly irreducible. Therefore this occurs in general. Remark 1. Directly indecomposable (subdirectly irreducible) SRCAs thus correspond to directly indecomposable (subdirectly irreducible) right-handed SBAs. In particular, the rule for q(x, y, z) in Lemma 6 provides directly indecomposable SRCAs. The derived SRCA (3 R ) q corresponds to the subdirectly irreducible

15 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 15 right-handed SBA 3 R defined in Section 2.4. As such, the subdirectly irreducible algebra (3 R ) q is a generator for the variety of all pure SRCAs. Also, an SRCA equation is an identity for all pure SRCAs iff that equation is an identity in (3 R ) q. Corollary 1. Let A be an RCA. Then the algebra (S(A),,, \, 0) is a righthanded SBA. Example 5. The reduct (F(X, Y ),,, \, 0) of the SRCA (F(X, Y ), q F, 0) of Example 4 is a right-handed SBA (see also [7]), where f g = f g G\F, f g = g G F and f \ g = f F \G. Theorem 2 can be likewise extended to a generic variety of SRCAs of type τ. Definition 13. An algebra of type τ is a right-handed SBA with additional regular operations if it is a right-handed SBA satisfying the following identity for all g τ: (x g(ȳ)) (g( z) \ x) = g((x y 1 ) (z 1 \ x),..., (x y n ) (z n \ x)). Theorem 3. Every variety of SRCAs of type τ is term equivalent to a variety of right-handed SBAs with additional regular operations SRCAs and the Green s relation D. Let A be an SRCA. Define the relation D on A as follows: xdy (y x = x) and (x y = y). Besides the equivalent conditions of Lemma 5 for right-handed SBAs we now have: Proposition 13. For any SRCA A the following conditions are equivalent, for all x, y A: (1) xdy; (2) θ x = θ y ; (3) yθ x 0 and xθ y 0; (4) q(x, a, b) = q(y, a, b) for all a, b A. Proof. (2) (3) Recall that θ x = θ(x, 0) and that yθ x 0 is equivalent to θ(y, 0) θ(x, 0). (3) (1) yθ x 0 iff q(x, y, 0) = y. Similarly for xθ y 0. (1) (4) Given xdy, by applying the term equivalence of Theorem 2 we have: q(x, a, b) = (x a) (b \ x) = Lemma 5 (y a) (b \ y) = q(y, a, b). (4) (1) x y = q(x, y, 0) = q(y, y, 0) = y and y x = q(y, x, 0) = q(x, x, 0) = x. Proposition 14. Let A be an SRCA. Then the following conditions hold: (1) D is a congruence on the pure reduct A 0.

16 16 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. (2) On each equivalence class D x (x 0), q(x, y, z) = y for all y, z D x. Proof. (1) The pure SRCA A 0 and the right-handed SBA (A 0 ) share a common underlying set, with the operations of each algebra polynomiallydefined from those of the other. Thus both algebras share common congruences, making the congruence D on (A 0 ) a congruence on A 0. (2) By Lemma 5 x y = y = y x and x \ y = 0 = y \ x in all D-classes of a right-handed SBA. Then, by the term equivalence result of Theorem 2 in each D-class we have: q(x, y, z) = (x y) (z \ x) = y 0 = y. Example 6. Let (F(X, Y ), q F, 0) be the algebra of Example 4. If f : F Y and g : G Y are finite functions (F, G f X), then we have that fdg iff F = G. The pair of complementary factor congruences associated with f : F Y is defined as follows: g θ f h iff g G F = h H F ; g θ f h iff g G\F = h H\F. Then the algebra (F(X, Y ), q F, 0) can be decomposed as a Cartesian product of (F(F, Y ), q F, 0) and the algebra (F(X \ F, Y ), q F, 0): (g : G Y ) (g G F, g G\F ) Ideals. The bijective correspondence between the Boolean algebra of central elements and the Boolean algebra of factor congruences is one of the most important properties of Church algebras. RCAs lack this full correspondence. Semicentral elements of an RCA correspond to a proper subset of the set of factor congruences. In this section we introduce ideals of RCAs and show that, for every semicentral element e, the equivalence class 0/θ e is a principal ideal, which is an idempotent semi-boolean-like-algebra (see [16, Definition 4.1]). We also characterise the Boolean algebra of central elements of a principal ideal. Definition 14. Let A be an RCA. An ideal I is a subalgebra of the pure reduct A 0 satisfying the following condition: x A and y, z I q(x, y, z) I. Notice that, if I is an ideal, then x y, y \ x I for all x A and y I. An ideal I is principal if there is an element e I such that q(e, x, y) = x for all x, y I. In such a case, the principal ideal I is said to be generated by e. Proposition 15. Let A be an RCA and e A be semicentral. Then we have: (1) The equivalence class 0/θ e is a principal ideal generated by e. (2) The algebra A e = (0/θ e, q Ae, 1 Ae, 0 Ae ), where q Ae = q A, 1 Ae = e and 0 Ae = 0 A, is a Church algebra.

17 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 17 Proof. (1) 0/θ e is an ideal because q(x, y, z)θ e q(x, 0, 0) = 0 for all x A and y, z 0/θ e. By q(e, e, 0) = e we get e 0/θ e. Moreover, the ideal 0/θ e is generated by e since q(e, x, y) = x for all xθ e y. (2) By definition of θ e we have xθ e 0 iff q(e, x, 0) = x. We recall from [16] that a double-pointed algebra B is a semi-boolean-likealgebra if it is a Church algebra all of whose elements are factor elements (that is, they satisfy axioms (A1)-(A3) of Proposition 6). B is idempotent if it satisfies (A4). By Theorem 2 and Lemma 2 the relation, defined by is a partial ordering in every SRCA. x y iff x y = x = y x, Proposition 16. Let A be a pure SRCA and e A. Then we have: (1) The Church algebra A e is an idempotent semi-boolean-like-algebra. (2) e = {x : x e} is a subalgebra of A e. (3) The algebra ( e,,,, e, 0), where x y = q(x, e, y); x y = q(x, y, 0); x = q(x, 0, e), is the Boolean algebra of central elements of A e. Proof. (1) The identities (A1)-(A4) hold in A e because they hold in the algebra A. (2) We have e 0/θ e. Let x, y, z e. We show that q(x, y, z) e: q(x, y, z) e = q(q(x, y, z), e, 0) by Def. = q(x, q(y, e, 0), q(z, e, 0)) by (A3) = q(x, y, z) by y, z e The other identity e q(x, y, z) = q(x, y, z) holds because q(x, y, z) 0/θ e. (3) We recall from [16] that an element x of a semi-boolean-like algebra is central if, and only if, q(x, 1, 0) = x. Since 1 = e, then an element x 0/θ e (that is, q(e, x, 0) = x) is central iff q(x, e, 0) = x. It follows that x 0/θ e is central iff x e A generalised Boolean algebra of factor congruences. Factor congruences in a general algebra do not satisfy any particular condition. For example, the set of factor congruences is not in general a sublattice of the lattice of all congruences. In this section we show that, if A is an RCA and Con F (A) = {θ e : e S(A)}, then a structure of generalised Boolean algebra can be given to the set Con F (A). Consider the algebra (Con F (A),,, \, 0), whose operations are defined as follows, for every φ, ψ Con F (A): (i): 0 =, the diagonal relation; (ii): φ ψ = φ ψ

18 18 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. (iii): φ ψ = φ ψ, where the symbol denotes the composition of binary relations. (iv): φ \ ψ = φ ψ, where ψ is the factor congruence which is the complement of ψ. Recall that the join of two factor congruences is just the composition of the relations. Proposition 17. The function θ : S(A) Con F (A), mapping e θ e, is a homomorphism from the right-handed skew Boolean algebra (S(A),,, \, 0) onto the algebra (Con F (A),,, \, 0). The kernel of the map θ is Green s relation D. Proof. (1) θ e d = θ e θ d : If q(e, x, y) = x and q(d, x, y) = x then q(q(e, d, 0), x, y) = q(e, q(d, x, y), y) by (A3) = q(e, x, y) by q(d, x, y) = x = x by q(e, x, y) = x If q(q(e, d, 0), x, y) = x, then q(e, x, y) = q(e, q(q(e, d, 0), x, y), y) by q(q(e, d, 0), x, y) = x = q(e, q(e, q(d, x, y), y), y) by (A3) ( ) = q(e, q(d, x, y), y) by (A2) = q(q(e, d, 0), x, y) by (A3) = x By (*) we have x = q(e, x, y) and x = q(e, q(d, x, y), y). We conclude as follows: x = q(e, q(d, x, y), y) = (A3) q(d, q(e, x, y), y) = q(d, x, y). (2) θ e d = θ e θ d : Let x θ e y θ d z. Then we have: q(q(e, e, d), x, z) = q(q(e, e, d), q(e, x, y), z) by q(e, x, y) = x = q(e, q(e, x, z), q(d, y, z)) by (A3) = q(e, q(e, x, z), y) by q(d, y, z) = y = q(e, x, y) by (A2) = x by q(e, x, y) = x In the opposite direction, let q(q(e, e, d), x, z) = x. x θ e q(e, z, x) θ d z. We have Then we prove that z = q(q(e, e, d), z, x) by q(q(e, e, d), z, x) = z = q(e, q(e, z, x), q(d, z, x)) by (A3) = q(e, z, q(d, z, x)) by (A2) = q(d, z, q(e, z, x)) by (A3) Moreover, q(e, x, q(e, z, x)) = x by (A2).

19 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 19 (3) θ e\d = θ e θ d : Let q(e, x, y) = x and q(d, x, y) = y. Then q(q(d, 0, e), x, y) = q(q(d, 0, e), x, q(d, x, y)) by q(d, x, y) = y = q(d, x, q(e, x, y)) by (A3) = q(d, x, x) by q(e, x, y) = x = x by (A1) In the opposite direction, let q(q(d, 0, e), x, y) = x, so that q(d, y, q(e, x, y)) = x. Then we have: and q(d, x, y) = q(d, q(d, y, q(e, x, y)), y) by q(d, y, q(e, x, y)) = x = q(d, y, y) by (A2) = y by (A1) q(e, x, y) = q(e, q(d, y, x), y) by q(d, x, y) = y = q(d, y, q(e, x, y)) by (A3) = x by q(d, y, q(e, x, y)) = x By Proposition 13 the kernel of the map θ is Green s relation D. Corollary 2. The algebra (Con F (A),,, \, 0) is a generalised Boolean algebra of permuting factor congruences. 5. A characterisation of one-pointed discriminator varieties In this section we characterise pointed discriminator varieties in terms of SRCAs and provide a new system of axioms for skew Boolean -algebras. We recall that a pointed variety V is 0-regular if the congruences of algebras in V are uniquely determined by their 0-classes. Fichtner [8] has shown that a pointed variety is 0-regular if, and only if, there exist binary terms d 1 (x, y),..., d n (x, y) satisfying the following two conditions: (1) d i (x, x) = 0 for every i = 1,..., n; (2) d 1 (x, y) = 0... d n (x, y) = 0 x = y. Theorem 4. The following conditions are equivalent for a pointed variety V of type τ: (1) V is a discriminator variety; (2) V is a variety of SRCAs satisfying the following identities for a suitable term d(x, y): d(x, x) = 0; q(d(x, y), x, y) = x. (3) V is a 0-regular variety of SRCAs. (4) V is a variety of SRCAs satisfying the following identities for a suitable term x y: x x = x; q(x y, y, x) = x.

20 20 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. (5) V is a variety of SRCAs satisfying the following identities for a suitable term x y: x x = x; x y = y x; q(x y, x, 0) = x y. (6) V is a variety of right handed skew Boolean -algebras with additional regular operations (see Definition 13). Proof. (1 2) Let A be a subdirectly irreducible algebra in V. Define q(x, y, z) = s(x, 0, z, y). The algebra A is an RCA because q(0, y, z) = s(0, 0, z, y) = z. If x 0 then q(x, y, z) = s(x, 0, z, y) = y; thus A is an SRCA by Lemma 6. Define d(x, y) = s(x, y, 0, s(x, 0, y, x)). Then d(x, x) = s(x, x, 0, s(x, 0, x, x)) = 0. We prove the other identity. Assume x y. q(d(x, y), x, y) = s(s(x, y, 0, s(x, 0, y, x)), 0, y, x) = s(s(x, 0, y, x), 0, y, x) by x y if x = 0: = s(y, 0, y, x) = x if x 0: = s(x, 0, y, x) = x. (2 3) If d(x, y) = 0 then x = q(d(x, y), x, y) = q(0, x, y) = y. (3 1) Let A V be a subdirectly irreducible algebra. Define d(x, y) = d 1 (x, y) d n (x, y). We have d(x, x) = 0 because 0 0 = 0. Let a b. If n = 1, then d(a, b) = d 1 (a, b) 0. If n > 1, then there exists a least 1 i n such that d i (a, b) 0. In the following we write d j for d j (a, b) (j = 1,..., n). Define d(a, b) = (d 1 d i 1 ) d i (d i+1 d n ) = 0 d i (d i+1 d n ) = d i (d i+1 d n ) = q(d i, d i, d i+1 d n ) = d i (by Lemma 6) 0. s(x, y, z, t) = q(d(x, y), t, z). Then we have: s(x, x, z, t) = q(d(x, x), t, z) = q(0, t, z) = z. Let now x y, so that d(x, y) 0. Then by Lemma 6 we obtain s(x, y, z, t) = q(d(x, y), t, z) = t for all t, z A. Then s is the switching quaternary term. (4 2) Define d(x, y) = (x y)\x y. Then we have: d(x, x) = (x x)\x x = x \ x = 0. We now show that the identity q(d(x, y), x, y) = x holds in every subdirectly irreducible member A of the variety. Let x y. Then A = x y 0 since by Lemma 6 { y if x = 0; x y = x if x 0.

21 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 21 It follows that the identity q(x y, x, y) = x holds. In conclusion, we have: q(d(x, y), x, y) = q((x y) \ x y, x, y) by Def. = q(q(x y, 0, x y), x, y) by Def. = q(x y, y, q(x y, x, y)) by (A3) = q(x y, y, x) by above = x by Hyp. (2 4) Define x y = (x y) \ d(x, y). In every subdirectly irreducible member of the variety we have: { x if x = y; x y = q(d(x, y), 0, x y) = 0 if x y. Then the identities x x = x and q(x y, y, x) = x are easily derived. The equivalence of (4), (5) and (6) can be easily derived by showing that in every subdirectly irreducible member of the variety we have: { x if x = y; x y = 0 otherwise. 6. Rings Rings are a good source of examples of skew lattices and SBAs (see [11]). We recall from [6] that, if the idempotents of a ring R are closed under multiplication, the idempotents form an SBA under the operations x y = xy, x y = x+y +yx xyx yxy and x\y = x xyx. More generally, any maximal normal band of idempotents in a ring forms an SBA under the above operations. The given join operation becomes the more familiar join x y = x + y xy in the left or right handed cases. A ring R is an RCA with respect to the operation q(x, y, z) = xy + z xz. In this section we show that the semicentral elements of R are the idempotents e satisfying the identity exy = xey for all x, y R. Theorem 5. Let R be a ring and set q(x, y, z) = xy + z xz. Then: (i) (R, q, 0) is an RCA, (ii) S(R) = {e E(R) x, y R : exy = xey}, where E(R) denotes the set of all the idempotents of R, (iii) S(R) contains the generalised Boolean algebra of all central idempotents of R, and (iv) S(R) is a right-handed SBA for the operations defined by x y = xy, x y = x y = x + y xy and x \ y = x yx. Proof. (i) q(0, y, z) = 0 + z 0 = z. (ii) Note that all elements of R satisfy (A1), and that (A2) and (A4) are satisfied exactly by the idempotents of R. Hence S(R) E(R) and S(R) is

22 22 K. Cvetko-Vah and A. Salibra Algebra univers. the set of all the idempotents e in R that satisfy (A3) for either of the basic operations +,,. First we check that all the idempotents satisfy (A3) for either + or. Indeed, for e E(R) we have and q(e, x 1 + x 2, y 1 + y 2 ) = e(x 1 + x 2 ) + y 1 + y 2 e(y 1 + y 2 ) = ex 1 + y 1 ey 1 + ex 2 + y 2 ey 2 = q(e, x 1, y 1 ) + q(e, x 2, y 2 ), q(e, x, y) = e( x) + ( y) e( y) = ex y + ey = (ex + y ey) = q(e, x, y). Finally, e satisfies (A3) for the basic operation if and only if q(e, x 1 x 2, y 1 y 2 ) = q(e, x 1, y 1 )q(e, x 2, y 2 ) holds for all x 1, x 2, y 1, y 2 R. This further simplifies to ex 1 y 2 ex 1 ey 2 + y 1 ex 2 y 1 ey 2 ey 1 ex 2 + ey 1 ey 2 = 0. (6.1) We claim that e E(R) satisfies condition (6.1) for all x 1, x 2, y 1, y 2 R if and only if it satisfies condition exy = xey, (6.2) for all x, y R. So, assume (6.1) and take x 1 = x 2 = 0, y 2 = e. Then (6.1) simplifies to y 1 e = ey 1 e, for all y 1 R. Using this, (6.1) simplifies to ex 1 y 2 = x 1 ey 2, for all x 1, y 2 R, which is exactly our condition (6.2). To prove the converse, assume that (6.2) holds for all x, y R. Taking y = e we get exe = xe, for all x R, and thus the left side of (6.1) simplifies to ex 1 y 2 x 1 ey 2, which is equal to 0 by (6.2). Thus, (6.1) follows. (iii) Follows from (ii), since condition (2) is satisfied by all central idempotents e. (iv) S(R) forms a right-handed SBA for the operations defined by x y = q(x, y, 0), x y = q(x, x, y) and x \ y = q(y, 0, x). In our case this simplifies to x y = q(x, y, 0) = xy, x y = q(x, x, y) = x + y xy = x y and x \ y = q(y, 0, x) = x yx. Acknowledgment. We hereby acknowledge the contribution by an anonymous referee, whose suggestions helped us to correct numerous inaccuracies in a first draft of this paper. References [1] Bauer, A., Cvetko-Vah, K., Stone duality for skew Boolean algebras with intersections, Houston J. Math., 39, 2013, [2] Bigelow D., Burris S.N., Boolean algebras of factor congruences. Acta Sci. Math., 54:11-20, [3] Bignall R.J., Leech J., Skew Boolean algebras and discriminator varieties, Algebra Universalis, 33, 1995, pp [4] Burris S.N., Sankappanavar H.P., A Course in Universal Algebra, Springer, Berlin, [5] Cvetko-Vah, K., Internal decompositions of skew lattices, Communications in Algebra, 35(1), (2007): pp

23 Vol. 00, XX The connection of skew Boolean algebras to Church algebras 23 [6] Cvetko-Vah K., Leech J, Rings whose idempotents form a multiplicative set, Communications in Algebra, 40(9), 2012, pp [7] Cvetko-Vah K., Leech J., Spinks M., Skew lattices and binary operations on functions, Journal of Applied Logic, 11(3), 2013, pp [8] Fichtner K., Fine Bermerkung über Mannigfaltigkeiten universeller Algebren mit Idealen. Monatsh. d. Deutsch. Akad. d. Wiss. (Berlin), 12, 1970, pp [9] Kudryavtseva, G. A refinement of Stone duality to skew Boolean algebras, Algebra Universalis, 67, 2012, [10] Ledda A., Paoli F., Salibra A., On Semi-Boolean-like algebras, Acta Univ. Palacki. Olomuc., Fac. rer. nat., Mathematica, 52(1), 2013, pp [11] Leech J., Skew lattices in rings, Algebra Universalis, 26, 1989, pp [12] Leech, J., Skew Boolean algebras, Algebra Universalis, 27, 1990, [13] Leech J., Recent developments in the theory of skew lattices, Semigroup Forum, 52, 1996, pp [14] Manzonetto G., Salibra A., From λ-calculus to universal algebra and back, in MFCS 08, volume 5162 of LNCS, 2008, pp [15] McKenzie R.N., McNulty G.F., Taylor W.F., Algebras, Lattices, Varieties, Volume I. Wadsworth Brooks, Monterey, California, [16] Salibra A., Ledda A., Paoli F., Kowalski T., Boolean-like algebras, Algebra Universalis, 69(2), 2013, pp [17] Spinks M., On the Theory of Pre-BCK Algebras, PhD Thesis, Monash University, [18] Vaggione D., Varieties in which the Pierce stalks are directly indecomposable, Journal of Algebra, 184, 1996, pp Karin Cvetko-Vah University of Ljubljana, Department of Mathematics, Jadranska 19, SI-1000 Ljubljana, Slovenia karin.cvetko@fmf.uni-lj.si URL: Antonino Salibra Università Ca Foscari Venezia, Department of Environmental Sciences, Informatics and Statistics, Via Torino 155, Venezia, Italy salibra@dsi.unive.it URL:

From λ-calculus to universal algebra and back

From λ-calculus to universal algebra and back From λ-calculus to universal algebra and back Giulio Manzonetto 1 and Antonino Salibra 1,2 1 Laboratoire PPS, CNRS-Université Paris 7, 2 Dip. Informatica, Università Ca Foscari di Venezia, Abstract. We

More information

ON SEMI-BOOLEAN-LIKE ALGEBRAS

ON SEMI-BOOLEAN-LIKE ALGEBRAS ON SEMI-BOOLEAN-LIKE ALGEBRAS ANTONIO LEDDA, FRANCESCO PAOLI, ANTONINO SALIBRA A. In a previous paper, we introduced the notion of Boolean-like algebra as a generalisation of Boolean algebras to an arbitrary

More information

From Lambda Calculus to Universal Algebra and Back

From Lambda Calculus to Universal Algebra and Back From Lambda Calculus to Universal Algebra and Back Giulio Manzonetto and Antonino Salibra Laboratoire PPS (Université Paris 7) Dip. Informatica (Università di Venezia) gmanzone@dsi.unive.it salibra@dsi.unive.it

More information

n-dimensional Boolean algebras

n-dimensional Boolean algebras n-dimensional Boolean algebras Antonio Bucciarelli IRIF, Univ Paris Diderot joint work with Antonio Ledda, Francesco Paoli and Antonino Salibra Outline 1 Church algebras and the λ-calculus 2 n-dimensional

More information

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

Christopher J. TAYLOR

Christopher J. TAYLOR REPORTS ON MATHEMATICAL LOGIC 51 (2016), 3 14 doi:10.4467/20842589rm.16.001.5278 Christopher J. TAYLOR DISCRIMINATOR VARIETIES OF DOUBLE-HEYTING ALGEBRAS A b s t r a c t. We prove that a variety of double-heyting

More information

Boolean algebras for lambda calculus

Boolean algebras for lambda calculus Boolean algebras for lambda calculus G. Manzonetto and A. Salibra Laboratoire PPS (Université Paris 7) Università Ca Foscari di Venezia 2 place Jussieu (case 7014) Dipartimento di Informatica 72251 Paris

More information

Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple

Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple Matthew A. Valeriote Abstract A finite universal algebra is called strictly simple if it is simple and has no nontrivial subalgebras. An algebra is said

More information

IMPLICATIVE BCS-ALGEBRA SUBREDUCTS OF SKEW BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

IMPLICATIVE BCS-ALGEBRA SUBREDUCTS OF SKEW BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Scientiae Mathematicae Japonicae Online, Vol. 8, (2003), 597 606 597 IMPLICATIVE BCS-ALGEBRA SUBREDUCTS OF SKEW BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS R. J. BIGNALL AND M. SPINKS Received April 1, 2003 Abstract. The variety

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

Expansions of Heyting algebras

Expansions of Heyting algebras 1 / 16 Expansions of Heyting algebras Christopher Taylor La Trobe University Topology, Algebra, and Categories in Logic Prague, 2017 Motivation Congruences on Heyting algebras are determined exactly by

More information

Skew Boolean algebras

Skew Boolean algebras Skew Boolean algebras Ganna Kudryavtseva University of Ljubljana Faculty of Civil and Geodetic Engineering IMFM, Ljubljana IJS, Ljubljana New directions in inverse semigroups Ottawa, June 2016 Plan of

More information

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices Chapman University Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Orange, California University of Siena Department of Mathematics and Computer

More information

Semilattice Modes II: the amalgamation property

Semilattice Modes II: the amalgamation property Semilattice Modes II: the amalgamation property Keith A. Kearnes Abstract Let V be a variety of semilattice modes with associated semiring R. We prove that if R is a bounded distributive lattice, then

More information

IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES

IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES IDEMPOTENT n-permutable VARIETIES M. VALERIOTE AND R. WILLARD Abstract. One of the important classes of varieties identified in tame congruence theory is the class of varieties which are n-permutable for

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

Homework Problems Some Even with Solutions

Homework Problems Some Even with Solutions Homework Problems Some Even with Solutions Problem 0 Let A be a nonempty set and let Q be a finitary operation on A. Prove that the rank of Q is unique. To say that n is the rank of Q is to assert that

More information

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application Chapman University Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Orange, California University of Siena Department of Mathematics

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices. If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson

10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices. If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson 10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson In this chapter we want to study the structure of finite lattices, and how it is reflected

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

THE ENDOMORPHISM SEMIRING OF A SEMILATTICE

THE ENDOMORPHISM SEMIRING OF A SEMILATTICE THE ENDOMORPHISM SEMIRING OF A SEMILATTICE J. JEŽEK, T. KEPKA AND M. MARÓTI Abstract. We prove that the endomorphism semiring of a nontrivial semilattice is always subdirectly irreducible and describe

More information

Partial Transformations: Semigroups, Categories and Equations. Ernie Manes, UMass, Amherst Semigroups/Categories workshop U Ottawa, May 2010

Partial Transformations: Semigroups, Categories and Equations. Ernie Manes, UMass, Amherst Semigroups/Categories workshop U Ottawa, May 2010 1 Partial Transformations: Semigroups, Categories and Equations Ernie Manes, UMass, Amherst Semigroups/Categories workshop U Ottawa, May 2010 2 What is a zero? 0 S, 0x =0=x0 0 XY : X Y, W f X 0 XY Y g

More information

A NOTE ON MULTIPLIERS OF SUBTRACTION ALGEBRAS

A NOTE ON MULTIPLIERS OF SUBTRACTION ALGEBRAS Hacettepe Journal of Mathematics and Statistics Volume 42 (2) (2013), 165 171 A NOTE ON MULTIPLIERS OF SUBTRACTION ALGEBRAS Sang Deok Lee and Kyung Ho Kim Received 30 : 01 : 2012 : Accepted 20 : 03 : 2012

More information

Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras

Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras T.S. Blyth Jie Fang Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras Abstract. An algebra A is said to be congruence coherent if every subalgebra of A that contains a class of some congruence

More information

EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED

EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED J. Ježek, P. Marković, M. Maróti and R. McKenzie Abstract. The aim of this paper is to prove that there is no finite basis for the equations satisfied by

More information

FACTOR CONGRUENCES IN SEMILATTICES

FACTOR CONGRUENCES IN SEMILATTICES REVISTA DE LA UNIÓN MATEMÁTICA ARGENTINA Volumen 52, Número 1, 2011, Páginas 1 10 FACTOR CONGRUENCES IN SEMILATTICES PEDRO SÁNCHEZ TERRAF Presented by R. Cignoli Abstract. We characterize factor congruences

More information

Some properties of residuated lattices

Some properties of residuated lattices Some properties of residuated lattices Radim Bělohlávek, Ostrava Abstract We investigate some (universal algebraic) properties of residuated lattices algebras which play the role of structures of truth

More information

SIMPLE LOGICS FOR BASIC ALGEBRAS

SIMPLE LOGICS FOR BASIC ALGEBRAS Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 44:3/4 (2015), pp. 95 110 http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/0138-0680.44.3.4.01 Jānis Cīrulis SIMPLE LOGICS FOR BASIC ALGEBRAS Abstract An MV-algebra is an algebra (A,,,

More information

LOCALLY SOLVABLE FACTORS OF VARIETIES

LOCALLY SOLVABLE FACTORS OF VARIETIES PROCEEDINGS OF HE AMERICAN MAHEMAICAL SOCIEY Volume 124, Number 12, December 1996, Pages 3619 3625 S 0002-9939(96)03501-0 LOCALLY SOLVABLE FACORS OF VARIEIES KEIH A. KEARNES (Communicated by Lance W. Small)

More information

FREE STEINER LOOPS. Smile Markovski, Ana Sokolova Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, Republic of Macedonia

FREE STEINER LOOPS. Smile Markovski, Ana Sokolova Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, Republic of Macedonia GLASNIK MATEMATIČKI Vol. 36(56)(2001), 85 93 FREE STEINER LOOPS Smile Markovski, Ana Sokolova Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, Republic of Macedonia Abstract. A Steiner loop, or a sloop, is a groupoid

More information

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY KEITH A. KEARNES Abstract. We show that a locally finite variety satisfies a nontrivial congruence identity

More information

Given a lattice L we will note the set of atoms of L by At (L), and with CoAt (L) the set of co-atoms of L.

Given a lattice L we will note the set of atoms of L by At (L), and with CoAt (L) the set of co-atoms of L. ACTAS DEL VIII CONGRESO DR. ANTONIO A. R. MONTEIRO (2005), Páginas 25 32 SOME REMARKS ON OCKHAM CONGRUENCES LEONARDO CABRER AND SERGIO CELANI ABSTRACT. In this work we shall describe the lattice of congruences

More information

Subdirectly Irreducible Modes

Subdirectly Irreducible Modes Subdirectly Irreducible Modes Keith A. Kearnes Abstract We prove that subdirectly irreducible modes come in three very different types. From the description of the three types we derive the results that

More information

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY Tame congruence theory is not an easy subject and it takes a considerable amount of effort to understand it. When I started this project, I believed that this

More information

THE LATTICE OF SUBVARIETIES OF SEMILATTICE ORDERED ALGEBRAS

THE LATTICE OF SUBVARIETIES OF SEMILATTICE ORDERED ALGEBRAS THE LATTICE OF SUBVARIETIES OF SEMILATTICE ORDERED ALGEBRAS A. PILITOWSKA 1 AND A. ZAMOJSKA-DZIENIO 2 Abstract. This paper is devoted to the semilattice ordered V-algebras of the form (A, Ω, +), where

More information

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE BULLETIN OF THE INTERNATIONAL MATHEMATICAL VIRTUAL INSTITUTE ISSN (p) 2303-4874, ISSN (o) 2303-4955 www.imvibl.org /JOURNALS / BULLETIN Vol. 7(2017), 339-352 DOI: 10.7251/BIMVI1702339R Former BULLETIN

More information

Boolean Semilattices

Boolean Semilattices Boolean Semilattices Clifford Bergman Iowa State University June 2015 Motivating Construction Let G = G, be a groupoid (i.e., 1 binary operation) Form the complex algebra G + = Sb(G),,,,,, G X Y = { x

More information

ARCHIVUM MATHEMATICUM (BRNO) Tomus 48 (2012), M. Sambasiva Rao

ARCHIVUM MATHEMATICUM (BRNO) Tomus 48 (2012), M. Sambasiva Rao ARCHIVUM MATHEMATICUM (BRNO) Tomus 48 (2012), 97 105 δ-ideals IN PSEUDO-COMPLEMENTED DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES M. Sambasiva Rao Abstract. The concept of δ-ideals is introduced in a pseudo-complemented distributive

More information

VARIETIES OF DE MORGAN MONOIDS: COVERS OF ATOMS

VARIETIES OF DE MORGAN MONOIDS: COVERS OF ATOMS VARIETIES OF DE MORGAN MONOIDS: COVERS OF ATOMS T. MORASCHINI, J.G. RAFTERY, AND J.J. WANNENBURG Abstract. The variety DMM of De Morgan monoids has just four minimal subvarieties. The join-irreducible

More information

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM

SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SPECTRAL-LIKE DUALITY FOR DISTRIBUTIVE HILBERT ALGEBRAS WITH INFIMUM SERGIO A. CELANI AND MARÍA ESTEBAN Abstract. Distributive Hilbert Algebras with infimum, or DH -algebras, are algebras with implication

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Luca Carai and Silvio Ghilardi arxiv:1702.08352v2 [math.lo] 25 Jul 2017 Università degli Studi di Milano, Milano, Italy luca.carai@studenti.unimi.it silvio.ghilardi@unimi.it July 26, 2017 Abstract The

More information

Properties of Boolean Algebras

Properties of Boolean Algebras Phillip James Swansea University December 15, 2008 Plan For Today Boolean Algebras and Order..... Brief Re-cap Order A Boolean algebra is a set A together with the distinguished elements 0 and 1, the binary

More information

Math 222A W03 D. Congruence relations

Math 222A W03 D. Congruence relations Math 222A W03 D. 1. The concept Congruence relations Let s start with a familiar case: congruence mod n on the ring Z of integers. Just to be specific, let s use n = 6. This congruence is an equivalence

More information

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE Guram Bezhanishvili and Revaz Grigolia Abstract In this note we characterize all subalgebras and homomorphic images of the free cyclic

More information

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence T. Katriňák and J. Guričan Abstract. Recently, Grätzer, Gunderson and Quackenbush have characterized the spectra of finite pseudocomplemented

More information

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3. ABSTRACT BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 123 3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3.1. Abstract Boolean Algebra. Definition 3.1.1. An abstract Boolean algebra is defined as a set B containing two distinct elements 0 and 1,

More information

On the algebra of relevance logics

On the algebra of relevance logics On the algebra of relevance logics by Johann Joubert Wannenburg Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree Master of Science in the Faculty of Natural & Agricultural Sciences University

More information

The variety of commutative additively and multiplicatively idempotent semirings

The variety of commutative additively and multiplicatively idempotent semirings Semigroup Forum (2018) 96:409 415 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00233-017-9905-2 RESEARCH ARTICLE The variety of commutative additively and multiplicatively idempotent semirings Ivan Chajda 1 Helmut Länger

More information

CONGRUENCE PROPERTIES IN SINGLE ALGEBRAS. Ivan Chajda

CONGRUENCE PROPERTIES IN SINGLE ALGEBRAS. Ivan Chajda CONGRUENCE PROPERTIES IN SINGLE ALGEBRAS Radim Bělohlávek Department of Computer Science Technical University of Ostrava tř. 17. listopadu 708 33 Ostrava-Poruba Czech Republic e-mail: radim.belohlavek@vsb.cz

More information

DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES. 1. Introduction

DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES. 1. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXXVII, 2 (2008), pp. 167 174 167 DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES SHASHIREKHA B. RAI Abstract. In this paper, the concepts of distributive, standard

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

On the variety generated by planar modular lattices

On the variety generated by planar modular lattices On the variety generated by planar modular lattices G. Grätzer and R. W. Quackenbush Abstract. We investigate the variety generated by the class of planar modular lattices. The main result is a structure

More information

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a partially ordered set P, let Co(P) denote the lattice of all order-convex

More information

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012 Notes about Filters Samuel Mimram December 6, 2012 1 Filters and ultrafilters Definition 1. A filter F on a poset (L, ) is a subset of L which is upwardclosed and downward-directed (= is a filter-base):

More information

Simultaneous congruence representations: a special case

Simultaneous congruence representations: a special case Algebra univers. 54 (2005) 249 255 0002-5240/05/020249 07 DOI 10.1007/s00012-005-1931-3 c Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel, 2005 Algebra Universalis Mailbox Simultaneous congruence representations: a special case

More information

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY KEITH A. KEARNES Abstract. We show that any variety of groups that contains a finite nonsolvable group contains an axiomatic formation that is not a subvariety.

More information

γ γ γ γ(α) ). Then γ (a) γ (a ) ( γ 1

γ γ γ γ(α) ). Then γ (a) γ (a ) ( γ 1 The Correspondence Theorem, which we next prove, shows that the congruence lattice of every homomorphic image of a Σ-algebra is isomorphically embeddable as a special kind of sublattice of the congruence

More information

A Generalization of Boolean Rings

A Generalization of Boolean Rings A Generalization of Boolean Rings Adil Yaqub Abstract: A Boolean ring satisfies the identity x 2 = x which, of course, implies the identity x 2 y xy 2 = 0. With this as motivation, we define a subboolean

More information

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 125 Chapter 5. Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 5.1. Semilattices and lattices. Many of the partially ordered sets P we have seen have a further valuable property: that for any two

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

Bounded width problems and algebras

Bounded width problems and algebras Algebra univers. 56 (2007) 439 466 0002-5240/07/030439 28, published online February 21, 2007 DOI 10.1007/s00012-007-2012-6 c Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel, 2007 Algebra Universalis Bounded width problems and

More information

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day.

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day. 8. Distributive Lattices Every dog must have his day. In this chapter and the next we will look at the two most important lattice varieties: distributive and modular lattices. Let us set the context for

More information

The Hermitian part of a Rickart involution ring, I

The Hermitian part of a Rickart involution ring, I ACTA ET COMMENTATIONES UNIVERSITATIS TARTUENSIS DE MATHEMATICA Volume 18, Number 1, June 2014 Available online at http://acutm.math.ut.ee The Hermitian part of a Rickart involution ring, I Jānis Cīrulis

More information

INTRODUCTION TO SEMIGROUPS AND MONOIDS

INTRODUCTION TO SEMIGROUPS AND MONOIDS INTRODUCTION TO SEMIGROUPS AND MONOIDS PETE L. CLARK We give here some basic definitions and very basic results concerning semigroups and monoids. Aside from the mathematical maturity necessary to follow

More information

ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS

ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS DAVID STANOVSKÝ Abstract. We describe a part of the lattice of subvarieties of left distributive left idempotent groupoids (i.e. those satisfying

More information

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra SET THEORY Basic concepts Notations Subset Algebra of sets The power set Ordered pairs and Cartesian product Relations on sets Types of relations and their properties Relational matrix and the graph of

More information

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such

More information

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation Tommaso Flaminio Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Siena Pian dei Mantellini 44 53100 Siena (Italy) flaminio@unisi.it

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.ra] 24 Jun 2013

arxiv: v1 [math.ra] 24 Jun 2013 DISTRIBUTIVITY IN SKEW LATTICES MICHAEL KINYON, JONATHAN LEECH, AND JOÃO PITA COSTA arxiv:1306.5598v1 [math.ra] 24 Jun 2013 Abstract. Distributive skew lattices satisfying x ^ py _ zq ^ x px ^ y ^ xq _

More information

Congruence Computations in Principal Arithmetical Varieties

Congruence Computations in Principal Arithmetical Varieties Congruence Computations in Principal Arithmetical Varieties Alden Pixley December 24, 2011 Introduction In the present note we describe how a single term which can be used for computing principal congruence

More information

VARIETIES OF POSITIVE MODAL ALGEBRAS AND STRUCTURAL COMPLETENESS

VARIETIES OF POSITIVE MODAL ALGEBRAS AND STRUCTURAL COMPLETENESS VARIETIES OF POSITIVE MODAL ALGEBRAS AND STRUCTURAL COMPLETENESS TOMMASO MORASCHINI Abstract. Positive modal algebras are the,,,, 0, 1 -subreducts of modal algebras. We show that the variety of positive

More information

An Overview of Residuated Kleene Algebras and Lattices Peter Jipsen Chapman University, California. 2. Background: Semirings and Kleene algebras

An Overview of Residuated Kleene Algebras and Lattices Peter Jipsen Chapman University, California. 2. Background: Semirings and Kleene algebras An Overview of Residuated Kleene Algebras and Lattices Peter Jipsen Chapman University, California 1. Residuated Lattices with iteration 2. Background: Semirings and Kleene algebras 3. A Gentzen system

More information

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES G. GRÄTZER AND E. KNAPP Abstract. Let D be a finite distributive lattice with

More information

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Nick Bezhanishvili Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam http://www.phil.uu.nl/~bezhanishvili email: N.Bezhanishvili@uva.nl

More information

Fully invariant and verbal congruence relations

Fully invariant and verbal congruence relations Fully invariant and verbal congruence relations Clifford Bergman and Joel Berman Abstract. A congruence relation θ on an algebra A is fully invariant if every endomorphism of A preserves θ. A congruence

More information

Unions of Dominant Chains of Pairwise Disjoint, Completely Isolated Subsemigroups

Unions of Dominant Chains of Pairwise Disjoint, Completely Isolated Subsemigroups Palestine Journal of Mathematics Vol. 4 (Spec. 1) (2015), 490 495 Palestine Polytechnic University-PPU 2015 Unions of Dominant Chains of Pairwise Disjoint, Completely Isolated Subsemigroups Karen A. Linton

More information

Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic

Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic Relational semantics for a fragment of linear logic Dion Coumans March 4, 2011 Abstract Relational semantics, given by Kripke frames, play an essential role in the study of modal and intuitionistic logic.

More information

Unification of terms and language expansions

Unification of terms and language expansions Unification of terms and language expansions in Heyting algebras and commutative residuated lattices Wojciech Dzik Instytut Matematyki Uniwersytet Sl aski, Katowice wojciech.dzik@us.edu.pl joint work with

More information

A SUBALGEBRA INTERSECTION PROPERTY FOR CONGRUENCE DISTRIBUTIVE VARIETIES

A SUBALGEBRA INTERSECTION PROPERTY FOR CONGRUENCE DISTRIBUTIVE VARIETIES A SUBALGEBRA INTERSECTION PROPERTY FOR CONGRUENCE DISTRIBUTIVE VARIETIES MATTHEW A. VALERIOTE Abstract. We prove that if a finite algebra A generates a congruence distributive variety then the subalgebras

More information

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15 CHAPTER 15 Boolean Algebra 15.1 INTRODUCTION Both sets and propositions satisfy similar laws, which are listed in Tables 1-1 and 4-1 (in Chapters 1 and 4, respectively). These laws are used to define an

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS. 1. Introduction

RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS. 1. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXXVI, 2(2007), pp. 263 272 263 RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS S. RUDEANU Abstract. Serfati [7] defined a ring structure on every Post algebra. In this paper we determine all the

More information

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION Daniel Halpern-Leistner 6/20/08 Abstract. I propose an algebraic framework in which to study measures of information. One immediate consequence

More information

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES G. GRÄTZER AND E. KNAPP Abstract. Let D be a finite distributive lattice with

More information

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook and T. Pitassi) Fall, 2014 Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness The Herbrand Theorem We now consider a complete method for proving the unsatisfiability of sets of first-order

More information

PROBLEMS, MATH 214A. Affine and quasi-affine varieties

PROBLEMS, MATH 214A. Affine and quasi-affine varieties PROBLEMS, MATH 214A k is an algebraically closed field Basic notions Affine and quasi-affine varieties 1. Let X A 2 be defined by x 2 + y 2 = 1 and x = 1. Find the ideal I(X). 2. Prove that the subset

More information

MITSCH S ORDER AND INCLUSION FOR BINARY RELATIONS

MITSCH S ORDER AND INCLUSION FOR BINARY RELATIONS MITSCH S ORDER AND INCLUSION FOR BINARY RELATIONS D. G. FITZGERALD Abstract. Mitsch s natural partial order on the semigroup of binary relations has a complex relationship with the compatible partial order

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members

On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members Christian Herrmann and Micheale S. Roddy Abstract. We prove that the following three conditions on a modular

More information

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY

TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY TROPICAL SCHEME THEORY 5. Commutative algebra over idempotent semirings II Quotients of semirings When we work with rings, a quotient object is specified by an ideal. When dealing with semirings (and lattices),

More information

φ(a + b) = φ(a) + φ(b) φ(a b) = φ(a) φ(b),

φ(a + b) = φ(a) + φ(b) φ(a b) = φ(a) φ(b), 16. Ring Homomorphisms and Ideals efinition 16.1. Let φ: R S be a function between two rings. We say that φ is a ring homomorphism if for every a and b R, and in addition φ(1) = 1. φ(a + b) = φ(a) + φ(b)

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

SUMMARY ALGEBRA I LOUIS-PHILIPPE THIBAULT

SUMMARY ALGEBRA I LOUIS-PHILIPPE THIBAULT SUMMARY ALGEBRA I LOUIS-PHILIPPE THIBAULT Contents 1. Group Theory 1 1.1. Basic Notions 1 1.2. Isomorphism Theorems 2 1.3. Jordan- Holder Theorem 2 1.4. Symmetric Group 3 1.5. Group action on Sets 3 1.6.

More information

Subdirectly irreducible algebras in varieties of universal algebras

Subdirectly irreducible algebras in varieties of universal algebras Subdirectly irreducible algebras in varieties of universal algebras Dorien Zwaneveld August 5, 204 Bachelorthesis Supervisors: dr. N. Bezhanishvili, J. Ilin Msc Korteweg-de Vries Institute for Mathematics

More information

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce Luca Spada Department of Mathematics and Computer Science University of Salerno www.logica.dmi.unisa.it/lucaspada

More information

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS TH QUATIONAL THORIS OF RPRSNTABL RSIDUATD SMIGROUPS SZABOLCS MIKULÁS Abstract. We show that the equational theory of representable lower semilattice-ordered residuated semigroups is finitely based. We

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Completely regular Bishop spaces

Completely regular Bishop spaces Completely regular Bishop spaces Iosif Petrakis University of Munich petrakis@math.lmu.de Abstract. Bishop s notion of a function space, here called a Bishop space, is a constructive function-theoretic

More information