Essays on Strategic Interactions

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Essays on Strategic Interactions"

Transcription

1 Università degli Studi di Milano - Bicocca Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore PhD THESIS Essays on Strategic Interactions CANDIDATE Claudia Meroni SUPERVISOR Francesco De Sinopoli Graduate School in Public Economics - DEFAP Academic Year 2013/14 i

2 Abstract In Poisson games, an extension of perfect equilibrium based on perturbations of the strategy space does not guarantee that players use admissible actions. This observation suggests that such a class of perturbations is not the correct one. In the first chapter, the right space of perturbations is characterized to give a definition of perfect equilibrium in Poisson games. Furthermore, such a space is used to define the corresponding strategically stable sets of equilibria. They are shown to satisfy existence, admissibility, and robustness against iterated deletion of dominated strategies and inferior replies. In the second chapter, it is shown that in every Poisson game the number of connected components of Nash equilibria is finite. This result is obtained by exploiting the geometric structure of the Nash equilibrium set, which is shown to be a semi-analytic set; i.e., a set defined by a finite system of analytic inequalities. Furthermore, it is also shown that every Poisson game has a stable set contained in a connected component of equilibria. In the third chapter, a different model of strategic interaction is analyzed, the double round-robin tournament. A tournament is a simultaneous n-player game that is built on a two-player game g. Each player meets all the other players in turn and in every match the game g is played. The winner of the tournament is the player who attains the highest total score, which is given by the sum of the payoffs that he gets in all the matches he plays. Arad and Rubinstein (2013) analyze tournaments of the round-robin type, where each player is matched with every other player once to play a symmetric game g. With the aim of extending the analysis of tournaments to asymmetric games, double round-robins are studied, where each player meets all his opponents twice to play g in alternating roles. In particular, the relationship between equilibria of the tournament and equilibria of the base game g is explored. ii

3 Contents Abstract ii Chapter 1. Strategic Stability in Poisson Games Introduction Preliminaries Admissibility Perfection Stability Examples 21 Appendix A. Stable Sets in Generic Poisson Games 25 Appendix B. On the Inadequacy of Inner-Perfection 26 Chapter 2. The Structure of Nash Equilibria in Poisson Games Introduction Preliminaries The Set of Nash Equilibria Connectedness 35 Chapter 3. Double Round-Robin Tournaments Introduction The Model The Two-Player Interaction The Tournament Examples 53 Bibliography 57 iii

4 CHAPTER 1 Strategic Stability in Poisson Games 1.1. Introduction Poisson games belong to the general class of models characterized by population uncertainty (Myerson, 1998; Milchtaich, 2004). These games have been introduced by Myerson (1998), and have been widely used to model voting behavior (see, e.g., Myerson (2002); Bouton and Castanheira (2012); Núñez (2014)) as well as more general economic environments (see, e.g., Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2007); Makris (2008, 2009); Ritzberger (2009); McLennan (2011); Jehiel and Lamy (2014)). In these models, every player does not know the exact number of other players in the population. Each player in the game, however, has probabilistic information about it and, given some beliefs about how the members of such a population behave, can compute the expected payoff that results from each of her available choices. Thus, a Nash equilibrium in this context is a description of behavior for the entire population that is consistent with the players utility maximizing actions given that they use such a description to form their beliefs about the population s expected behavior. Similarly to standard normal form and extensive form games, one can easily construct examples of Poisson games where not every Nash equilibrium is a plausible description of rational behavior. In particular, Nash equilibria in Poisson games can be in dominated strategies. Indeed, many applications of Poisson games (see, e.g., Myerson (2002); Maniquet and Morelli (2013); Bouton and Castanheira (2012); Núñez (2014); among others) focus on undominated strategies in their analysis. In addition, there are also examples in the applied * This chapter is based on De Sinopoli et al. (2014). 1

5 2 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES literature of Poisson games that use some other kind of refinements (Huges (2012); Bouton (2013); Bouton and Gratton (forthcoming)). Hence, it seems worthwhile exploring, also in games with population uncertainty, what can be said from a theoretical standpoint about which Nash equilibria are the most reasonable and to propose a definition that selects such equilibria for us. Following the main literature on equilibrium refinements, we start focusing our attention on admissibility. That is, the principle prescribing players not to play dominated strategies (Luce and Raiffa (1957, p.287, Axiom 5)). Furthermore, as in Kohlberg and Mertens (1986), we also require that the solution be robust against iterated deletion of dominated actions. Unfortunately, as it is already well known, such an iterative process can lead to different answers depending on which order is chosen to eliminate the dominated strategies. The response to this caveat is defining a set-valued solution concept and requiring that every solution to a Poisson game contain a solution to any game that can be obtained by eliminating dominated strategies. Of course, a definition of such a concept for Poisson games should be guided by the literature on Strategic Stability for finite games (Kohlberg and Mertens (1986); Mertens (1989, 1991); Hillas (1990); Govindan and Wilson (2008)). In broad terms, a strategically stable set is a subset of Nash equilibria that is robust against every element in some given space of perturbations. The choice of such a space determines the properties that the final concept satisfies and the perturbations are just a means of obtaining the game theoretical properties that we desire (Kohlberg and Mertens (1986, p. 1005, footnote 3)). As argued above, a strategically stable set of equilibria should only contain undominated strategies. Furthermore, it should always contain a strategically stable set of any game obtained by eliminating a dominated strategy. However, De Sinopoli and Pimienta (2009) show that the main instrument used to define strategic stability in normal form games i.e. Nash equilibria of strategy perturbed games fails to guarantee that players only use undominated strategies when applied to Poisson games.

6 1.1. INTRODUCTION 3 Thus, before defining strategically stable sets of equilibria in Poisson games we need to find the appropriate space of perturbations that guarantees that every member of the stable set is undominated. It turns out that the right space of perturbations is of the same nature as the one used in infinite normal-form games (Simon and Stinchcombe (1995); Al-Najjar (1995); Carbonell-Nicolau (2011)) and different from the one used in finite games (Selten (1975)) even if players have finite action sets. Once this class of perturbations has been identified, it can be reinterpreted as a collection of perturbations of the best response correspondence. Then, a stable set is defined as a minimal subset of fixed points of the best response correspondence with the property that every correspondence that can be obtained using such perturbations has a fixed point close to it. As an illustration of stable sets in Poisson games we construct a referendum game with a threshold for implementing a new policy (see Example 1.5). In this example, every voter prefers the new policy over the status quo but some voters incur a cost in supporting it. Given the parametrization that we use, the game has three equilibria which can be ranked according to the probability of implementation of the new policy: zero, low, and high. We show that the first equilibrium is dominated because, in particular, voters who do not incur any cost do not support the new policy. In the second equilibrium, only voters who incur the cost do not support the new policy, even if they are indifferent between supporting it or not. Furthermore, every such a voter would strictly prefer supporting the new policy and paying the cost if the share of voters supporting the new policy was slightly higher than the equilibrium one. We show that this equilibrium is undominated and perfect but becomes unstable once dominated strategies are eliminated. Hence, the unique stable set of the game is the equilibrium in which the new policy is implemented with high probability. We review the general description of Poisson games in the next Section. We then discuss the admissibility postulate in Section 1.3 and the definition of

7 4 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES perfection in Section 1.4. The space of perturbations used to define perfect equilibria is used to describe, in Section 1.5, the stable sets of equilibria in Poisson games. We show that they satisfy existence, admissibility and iterated deletion of dominated strategies. Section 3.5 contains some applications of stability. In Appendix A we show that, in generic Poisson games, every Nash equilibrium is a singleton stable set Preliminaries We begin fixing a Poisson game Γ (n,t, r,c,(c t ) t T, u). The number of players is distributed according to a Poisson random variable with parameter n. Hence, the probability that there are k players in the game is equal to P(k n)= e n n k. k! The set T = {1,...,T} is the set of player types. The probability that a randomly selected player is of each type is given by the vector r = (r 1,..., r T ) (T ). 1 That is, a player is of type t T with probability r t. The finite set of actions is C. However, we allow that not every action be available to type t players. The set of actions that are in fact available to players of type t is C t C. 2 An action profile x Z(C) specifies for each action c C the number of players x(c) that have chosen that action. The set of action profiles is Z(C) Z+ C. Players preferences in the game are summarized by u= (u 1,..., u T ). It is assumed that each function u t : C t Z(C) R be bounded. We interpret u t (c, x) as the payoff accrued by a type t player when she chooses action c and the realization resulting from the rest of the population s behavior is the action profile x Z(C). The set of mixed actions for players of type t is (C t ). If α (C t ) the carrier of α is the subset C (α) C t of pure actions that are given strictly positive probability by α. We identify the mixed action that attaches probability one 1 For any finite set K we write (K) for the set of probability distributions on K. 2 Given two sets E and F, we use the expression E F allowing for set equality.

8 1.2. PRELIMINARIES 5 to action c C with the pure action c. As in Myerson (1998), a strategy function σ is an element of Σ { σ (C) T : σ t (C t ) for all t }. That is, a strategy function maps types to the set of mixed actions available to the corresponding type. We always write strategy functions as bracketed arrays (σ 1,...,σ T ) where σ t (C t ) for t=1,...,t. Furthermore, we may also refer to strategy functions simply as strategies. The average behavior induced by the strategy function σ is represented by τ(σ) (C) and it is defined by τ(σ)(c) t T r(t)σ t (c). Construct the set τ(σ) { τ (C) : τ=τ(σ) for some σ Σ}. 3 When the population s aggregate behavior is summarized by τ τ(σ), the probability that the action profile x Z(C) is realized is equal to P(x τ) c C (e nτ(c) (nτ(c))x(c) x(c)! The expected payoff to a type t player who plays c C t is computed as usual, U t (c,τ) x Z(C) ). P(x τ)u t (c, x). (1.2.1) Note that, for each type t T, each action c C t defines a bounded and continuous function U t (c, ) : (C) R. Action c C t is a pure best response against τ (C) for players of type t if c argmax c C t U t (c,τ). The finite set of such actions is written PBR t (τ). The set of best responses against τ is BR t (τ) (PBR t (τ)). We write BR(τ) Σ for the collection of strategy functions σ that satisfy σ t BR t (τ) for every t. 3 In the usual description of Poisson games (Myerson (1998)), the set τ(σ) coincides with (C) because every type has the same action set. We need to relax this assumption because after eliminating dominated actions different types can end up with different action sets. In these cases, τ(σ) is a subset of (C). Take as an example a plurality voting game with three candidates (a, b and c) and two types of voters, each type of voter having the same ex-ante probability. Let type 1 voters have preferences a 1 b 1 c and let type 2 voters have preferences c 2 b 2 a. There is no cost of voting and abstention is not possible. Consider the game obtained after eliminating dominated actions so that type 1 voters cannot vote for candidate c and type 2 voters cannot vote for candidate a. In this game, τ(σ) {( τ(a), τ(b), τ(c)) (C) : τ(a), τ(c) 1/2}.

9 6 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES DEFINITION 1.1 (Nash equilibrium). The strategy function σ is a Nash equilibrium of the Poisson game Γ if σ BR(τ(σ)). Since Σ is compact and convex and BR τ is upper semicontinuous and convex valued, every Poisson game has a Nash equilibrium (Myerson (1998)). Furthermore, once we fix n, T, r, C and (C t ) t T, standard arguments show that the Nash equilibrium correspondence (mapping utilities to equilibria) is upper semicontinuous Admissibility Consider a referendum where voters have only two options, voting yes or no to some policy question. For the policy to be implemented the law requires that at least K > 1 voters vote yes, otherwise the policy is not implemented. Every voter in the game wants the policy to be implemented. The strategy that prescribes every player to vote no is a Nash equilibrium, however, it is clear that such a strategy is dominated. Similar examples can be easily constructed. We now introduce the standard concept of dominated actions and dominated strategies. DEFINITION 1.2 (Dominated actions). Action α is dominated by β for players of type t if U t (α,τ) U t (β,τ) for every τ τ(σ) and U t (α,τ ) < U t (β,τ ) for some τ τ(σ). That is, an action α is dominated if there is another action such that, regardless of what other players do, always gives higher utility than α and, sometimes, strictly higher. We say that an action α is strictly dominated by β if the inequality is strict for every τ τ(σ). Following from this concept, there is a definition of dominated strategies. DEFINITION 1.3 (Dominated strategies). The strategy function σ is dominated if there is a t T such that σ t is a dominated action for players of type t.

10 1.3. ADMISSIBILITY 7 Likewise, a strategy function is strictly dominated if it prescribes a strictly dominated action for some type. De Sinopoli and Pimienta (2009) prove that every Poisson game has a Nash equilibrium in undominated strategies. In an attempt to capture undominated behavior, we can also give a straightforward extension of the definition of perfection to Poisson games. If E is a finite set, let us denote by (E) the set of completely mixed probability distributions on E. This is the set of distributions that give strictly positive probability to every element in E. We now define a perturbation as a pair (ε,σ ) where ε>0 and σ is a completely mixed, i.e., a strategy function such that σ t (C t ) for every t T. In a perturbed game and under the perturbation (ε,σ ), if the strategy function σ is played then, for each type t, the action σ t is substituted by (1 ε)σ t + εσ t. Given a strategy-perturbation (ε,σ ) we denote the corresponding strategy-perturbed Poisson game by Γ ε,σ. We can now give the usual definition of perfect equilibrium. For the time being, we call it inner-perfection. DEFINITION 1.4 (Inner-perfection). The strategy function σ is an innerperfect equilibrium if there is a sequence of perturbations {(ε k,σ k )} k and a sequence of strategy functions {ς k } k such that {ε k } k converges to zero, {ς k } k converges to σ, and ς k is a Nash equilibrium of Γ ε,σ k for every k. Using standard arguments, De Sinopoli and Pimienta (2009) show that every Poisson game has an inner-perfect equilibrium and that the usual alternative definitions (based on, e.g., ε-perfect equilibria) are also equivalent in the context of Poisson games. It is also showed there that, contrary to well known results for normal form games, inner-perfect equilibria can be in dominated strategies. The following example illustrates why.

11 8 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES EXAMPLE 1.1. Let Γ be a Poisson game with expected number of players equal to n= 2, set of types T = {1}, set of actions C= {a, b}, and utility function u(a, x)= e 2 u(b, x)= { 1 0 for every x Z(C), if x(a)= x(b)=1, and otherwise. Notice that e 2 is the probability that x(a) = x(b) = 1 under the strategy σ = ( 1 2 a+ 1 2 b). Also notice that action b is dominated by action a, the former only does as good as the latter against the strategy σ=( 1 2 a+ 1 2 b), and does strictly worse for any other strategy σ σ. The action γ= 1 2 a+ 1 2 b is also dominated by a. Nevertheless, it is a best response against σ. Finally, since σ is completely mixed, we can conclude that the dominated strategy σ is an inner-perfect equilibrium. In order to see where the difference with respect to normal form games is coming from, it is useful to plot how the players utility varies as the opponents change their behavior. We do that in Figure 1.1, where we represent utilities with respect to the probability attached to action a by an average member of the population. (There is only one type of player so, in this example, the sets Σ and τ(σ) coincide.) The first thing to notice is that U(b, ) is not linear in Σ and that it attains its maximum at the completely mixed strategy σ=( 1 2 a+ 1 2 b). At that point, U(a, ) coincides with U(b, ). If we were to integrate U(a, ) and U(b, ) over the domain of strategies, the integral of U(a, ) would always be larger than the integral of U(b, ). Of course, not only is this true when we integrate with respect to the Lebesgue measure, but also when we integrate with respect to any Borel probability measure that does not give probability one to {σ}. Hence, if we approach σ by an arbitrary sequence of sufficiently mixed Borel probability measures over Σ, action b would always be an inferior response to every element of such a sequence. In the next section we formalize and generalize this intuition.

12 1.4. PERFECTION 9 e 2 U(a, ) U(b, ) τ(a) 0 1/2 1 FIGURE 1.1. Utility functions in Example Perfection The set τ(σ) is equipped with the Euclidean distance d, so (τ(σ), d) is a compact metric space. The distance between τ and an arbitrary subset A τ(σ) is d(τ, A) inf { d(τ,a) : a A }. We let B denote the σ-algebra of Borel sets in τ(σ) (C). The set of all Borel probability measures over the measurable space (τ(σ), B) is denoted M. We topologize M with the weak* topology. This topology is characterized by the following: a sequence of measures {µ k } M converges (weakly) to µ if for every continuous function f : τ(σ) R the sequence of real numbers τ(σ) f dµk converges to τ(σ) f dµ. It can be showed (Billingsley (1968, pg. 239)) that M is a compact metrizable space and that a sequence {µ k } converges to µ if and only if it converges with respect to the Prokhorov metric. Let δ : τ(σ) M be the function that maps each τ τ(σ) to the Dirac measure δ(τ) M that assigns probability one to {τ}. With abuse of notation, if σ Σ we write δ(σ) instead of δ(τ(σ)). Denote by M the subset of measures µ M that satisfy µ(o)>0 for every nonempty open set O τ(σ). We extend the domain of the utility functions to M : U t (c,µ) U t (c,τ)dµ. τ(σ) PROPOSITION 1.1. The utility functions U t (c, ) : M R are continuous and linear in M. PROOF. Consider a sequence {µ k } µ. Since the functions U t (c, ) are continuous on τ(σ), from weak convergence we obtain U t (c,µ k ) U t (c,µ).

13 10 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES To prove linearity, take some α [0,1], some µ, µ M, and note that U t (c,αµ+(1 α)µ )= τ(σ) α U t (c,τ)dµ+(1 α) τ(σ) U t (c,τ)d(αµ+(1 α)µ )= τ(σ) U t (c,τ)dµ = αu t (c,µ)+(1 α)u t (c,µ ). REMARK 1.1. Recall that the utility functions U t (c, ) are continuous but, typically, not linear in τ(σ). Given any µ M we write PBR t (µ) for the set of actions c C t that maximize U t (c,µ). As usual, we also define the set of mixed actions BR t (µ) (PBR t (µ)). The sets PBR(µ) and BR(µ) are defined accordingly. The correspondence BR is upper semicontinuous and convex valued. The following result follows directly from the definitions. PROPOSITION 1.2. The strategy function σ is a Nash equilibrium of the Poisson game Γ if and only if σ BR(δ(σ)). It is convenient to recast the definition of dominated actions using the extension of the utility functions to M. We do so in the next proposition and state it without proof. PROPOSITION 1.3. Action α is dominated by β for players of type t if and only if U t (α,µ) U t (β,µ) for every µ M and U t (α,µ )< U t (β,µ ) for some µ M. Moreover, an action α is strictly dominated by β if the strict inequality holds for every µ M. We are now in a position to characterize the set of dominated actions for a given type. The next theorem is reminiscent of classical results that hold in finite normal form games (see Gale and Sherman (1950); Bohnenblust et al. (1950); Pearce (1984)).

14 1.4. PERFECTION 11 THEOREM 1.1. An action α (C t ) is undominated for a player of type t if and only if there is a µ M such that α BR t (µ ). PROOF. If there is a measure µ that assigns positive probability to every open set in τ(σ) and α BR t (µ ) then action α cannot be dominated. Suppose now that α BR t (µ ) for every µ M. Fix some ρ M, some 0<ε<1, and construct the infinite two-player zero-sum game Γ(t,α,ρ,ε) ( (C t ),M,V ε α,ρ ) where, for any β (C t ) and µ M, player one s payoff function Vα,ρ ε is given by: V ε α,ρ (β,µ) U t(β,ερ +(1 ε)µ) U t (α,ερ +(1 ε)µ). Let (β ε,µ ε ) be a Nash equilibrium of Γ(t,α,ρ,ε). 4 We have 0=V ε α,ρ (α,µε )<V ε α,ρ (βε,µ ε ) V ε α,ρ (βε,µ) for every µ M. (1.4.1) The weak inequality follows from player two s Nash equilibrium conditions and the strict inequality follows because α is never a best response against any element in M. Hence, β ε dominates α in the zero-sum game Γ(t,α,ρ,ε). Passing to a subsequence if necessary, consider the limit β of {β ε } as ε goes to zero. Define the function V α as follows: V α (β,µ) U t (β,µ) U t (α,µ). From (1.4.1) we know that V ε α,ρ (β ε,µ)>0 for every µ M. Hence, by continuity, V α (β,µ) 0 for every µ M. Now we only need to find µ M such that V α (β,µ )>0. For ε small enough the carrier C (β ) is a subset of the carrier C (β ε ), therefore, for such small values of ε we also have V ε α,ρ (β,µ)>0 for every µ M. 4 There is always a Nash equilibrium. In particular, if dp is the Prokhorov metric on M, Prokhorov s Theorem implies that (M,d p ) is a compact metric space because (τ(σ),d) is also a compact metric space (Billingsley (1968, pg. 37)). The set M is also a nonempty and convex subset of a normed vector space. Furthermore, the payoff function V ε α,ρ is linear in both arguments, making the associated best response correspondence convex valued (and upper semicontinuous). Existence of Nash equilibrium follows from the Fan-Glicksberg fixed point theorem.

15 12 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES Since, by definition, V α (β,ερ + (1 ε)µ)=v ε α,ρ (β,µ), we can conclude that α is dominated by β in the original Poisson game. This result implies that a definition of perfection that guarantees that players do not play dominated actions needs to be based on elements of the set M. Hence, we define a perturbation as a pair (ε,µ ) (0,1) M. The interpretation is that with vanishing probability ε, the average behavior of the population is perturbed towards the completely mixed measure µ. Thus, a Nash equilibrium of such a perturbed game is a strategy function σ that satisfies σ BR((1 ε)δ(σ)+εµ ). Moreover, a strategy function satisfies this property if and only if it is a Nash equilibrium of a suitably defined utility-perturbed Poisson game. Given a Poisson game Γ = (n,t, r,c,(c t ) t T, u) and a perturbation (ε,µ ) we define the perturbed Poisson game Γ ε,µ ( n,t, r,c,(c t ) t T, u( ε,µ ) ) where the utility functions are given, for every type t T and every action c C t, by u t (c, x ε,µ ) (1 ε)u t (c, x)+ε U t (c,τ)dµ. (1.4.2) PROPOSITION 1.4. Given a perturbation (ε,µ ), the strategy function σ is a Nash equilibrium of Γ ε,µ if and only if σ BR((1 ε)δ(σ)+εµ ). PROOF. Just notice that for every t T and every c C t, τ(σ) U t (c,(1 ε)δ(σ)+εµ )=(1 ε)u t (c,δ(σ))+εu t (c,µ ) = (1 ε)u t (c,τ(σ))+ε U t (c,τ)dµ = (1 ε) = x Z(C) = x Z(C) x Z(C) P(x τ(σ)) τ(σ) P(x τ(σ))u t (c, x)+ε τ(σ) [ (1 ε)u t (c, x)+ε τ(σ) U t (c,τ)dµ U t (c,τ)dµ ] P(x τ(σ))u t (c, x ε,µ )= U t (c,τ(σ) ε,µ ). Note that, given a perturbation (ε,µ ), we can first normalize utility functions in Γ ε,µ by dividing them by (1 ε) and think of the perturbation as adding,

16 1.4. PERFECTION 13 for each type t T and each action c C t, the constant value ε 1 ε τ(σ) U t(c,τ)dµ to the function U t (c, ). In Example 1.1, for instance, for any perturbation (ε,µ ) the value that is added to U t (a, ) by the perturbation in the corresponding perturbed Poisson game is always strictly larger than the value added to U t (b, ) (see Figure 1.1). This lifts the expected utility function U t (a, ) more than U t (b, ) and makes action b strictly dominated in the perturbed Poisson game. Note as well that, given a Poisson game Γ, the set of all perturbed Poisson games (as defined above) is a strict subset of the set of Poisson games that can be generated by perturbing the utility functions in Γ. Taking the perturbations to zero, we introduce a new definition of perfection for Poisson games. DEFINITION 1.5 (Outer-perfection). The strategy function σ is an outerperfect equilibrium if there is a sequence of perturbations { (ε k,µ k ) } k and a sequence of strategy functions { σ k} k such that { ε k} k converges to zero, { σ k} k converges to σ, and σ k is a Nash equilibrium of Γ ε k,µ k for every k. Every perturbed Poisson game has a Nash equilibrium. For any sequence of Poisson games we can construct an associated sequence of Nash equilibria. Such a sequence is contained in the compact set Σ so it has a subsequence that converges. Hence, every Poisson game has an outer-perfect equilibrium. (Furthermore, it can also be proved that if the sequence of strategies {σ k } k supports an outer-perfect equilibrium σ given the sequence of perturbations {(ε k,µ k )} k then the sequence of perturbed equilibria {(1 ε k )δ(σ k )+ε k µ k } k converges weakly to δ(σ).) The major difference between this concept and the usual implementation of perfection in finite or infinite normal form games (Selten (1975); Simon and Stinchcombe (1995); also, inner-perfect equilibria in the present paper) is that the set of perturbations is not a subset of the set of mixed strategies in the game. Thus, a perturbed Poisson game cannot be interpreted as a game where players make mistakes when implementing their intended actions. We adhere to the view that, if the possibility of mistakes is real then

17 14 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES it should be properly modeled in the game (Kohlberg and Mertens (1986, p. 1005, footnote 3)). Perturbations are just technical devices used to obtain desirable game theoretical properties. We complete this argument presenting in Appendix B an example that illustrates the inadequacy of a concept of strategic stability based on inner-perfect equilibria (which is the concept that, in the current context, does admit a motivation based on players mistakes when playing the game). We also show at the end of this section that outer-perfection neither implies nor is implied by inner-perfection. The following two corollaries follow from Theorem 1.1. COROLLARY 1.1. Every outer-perfect equilibrium is a Nash equilibrium in undominated strategies. PROOF. Theorem 1.1 implies that, for any perturbation (ε,µ ), every dominated action in the Poisson game Γ becomes strictly dominated in Γ ε,µ. Hence, it is used with probability zero in every Nash equilibrium of Γ ε,µ. Since an outer-perfect equilibrium is the limit point of a sequence of Nash equilibria of perturbed Poisson games, such a dominated action is also used with probability zero in any outer-perfect equilibrium of Γ. COROLLARY 1.2. If #T = 1 then every undominated equilibrium is outerperfect. PROOF. Let σ be an undominated equilibrium. Because σ is an equilibrium, σ BR(δ(σ)). Because σ is undominated, there is a measure µ M such that σ BR(µ ). Therefore, Proposition 1.1 implies that σ BR((1 ε)δ(σ)+εµ ). Taking ε to zero proves the result. In the next example we show that Corollary 1.2 does not generalize to Poisson games with more than two types. EXAMPLE 1.2. Take a Poisson game with expected number of players n = 2, set of types T = {1,2}, and set of actions C= C 1 = C 2 = {a, b}. The probability of

18 1.4. PERFECTION 15 2e 2 U 1 (b, ) 2e 2 U 2 (b, ) U 1 (a, ) e 2 U 2 (a, ) τ(a) 1/2 1/ FIGURE 1.2. Utility functions in Example 1.2. τ(a) each type is r 1 = 2/3 and r 2 = 1/3. Utility functions are as follows: 5 u 1 (a, x)= { 1 if x(a)= x(b)=1, 0 otherwise, u 2 (a, x)= e 2 for every x, u 1 (b, x)= (2 x(a))e 2, u 2 (b, x)=(2 x(a))e 2. The corresponding expected utility functions U 1 and U 2 are plotted in Figure 1.2. As we can see, no type has a dominated action. It is easy to see that the strategy function σ=( 3 4 a+ 1 4 b, b) is an undominated Nash equilibrium such that τ(σ)= 1 2 a+ 1 2 b. However, it is not outer-perfect. Given that U 1(a, ) is always below U 2 (a, ) and that U 1 (b, )= U 2 (a, ), for any µ M such that type 1 players are indifferent between a and b, necessarily, players of type 2 strictly prefer a to b. Hence, we cannot construct a sequence of perturbed Poisson games whose associated sequence of Nash equilibria converges to σ. (In turn, the Nash equilibrium ( 1 4 a+ 3 4 b,a) is indeed outer-perfect.) We now explore further the relationship between inner-perfect and outerperfect equilibria. We have already seen above that an inner-perfect equilibrium can be a dominated strategy. Therefore, not every inner-perfect equilibrium is outer-perfect. We can also easily illustrate this last fact here with the strategy function σ = ( 3 4 a+ 1 4 b, b) in Example 1.2. Indeed, the sequence 5 Note, however, that the utility functions ui are not bounded, contrary to our assumption when we defined Poisson games. We chose unbounded utility functions only for the sake of simplicity in the exposition of the result.

19 16 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES 2 U(b, ) 0 1 U(a, ) FIGURE 1.3. Utility functions in Example 1.3. σ(a) of completely mixed strategies σ ε = ( ( 3 2ε 4 )a+(1+2ε 4 )b,εa+(1 ε)b) converges to σ. Given that τ(σ ε ) = τ(σ) for every small enough ε, the strategy function σ is a best response against every element in such a sequence. Thus, σ is an inner-perfect equilibrium (in undominated strategies). On the other hand, as we show in the next example, not every outer-perfect equilibrium is inner-perfect. EXAMPLE 1.3. Let the Poisson game Γ have expected number of players equal to n= 4, only one type, set of actions C= {a, b} and utility function: 2 if x(a)=0, u(a, x)= 8 if x(a)=1, 0 otherwise, u(b, x) = 2 for every x. We represent the corresponding utility functions U(a, ) and U(b, ) in Figure Strategies a and b are both undominated. Furthermore, (b) is a Nash equilibrium of the game and, since #T = 1, Corollary 1.2 implies that it is also an outer-perfect equilibrium. However, it is not inner-perfect as for any completely mixed strategy close to strategy (b) action a is strictly preferred to action b. 6 An analogous picture can be obtained from a Poisson model of a congestion problem such as the Farol Bar game proposed by Arthur (1994). Each agent has two alternatives: drinking a beer at home (action b) or at a bar (action a). The utility of drinking in the bar alone is the same as the one from drinking at home. Furthermore, the utility of drinking in the bar is increasing in the company up to a point where the bar is too crowded and it starts to decline.

20 1.5. STABILITY 17 We summarize these observations in the next proposition. PROPOSITION 1.5. A Nash equilibrium in undominated actions is not necessarily outer-perfect even if it is also an inner-perfect equilibrium. Moreover, an outer-perfect equilibrium is not necessarily inner-perfect Stability In the following example, we show that the process of iterated deletion of dominated actions can lead to different solutions depending on the order of elimination. EXAMPLE 1.4 (Iterated dominance). This example shows why iterated dominance and existence force us to use a set valued solution concept. Consider a Poisson game with set of types T {1,2} with probabilities r 1 = 1/4 and r 2 = 3/4, and set of actions C 1 = C 2 = C {a, b, c, d}. Preferences are given by the following utility functions. 2 if x(a) x(b), u 1 (a, x)= 0 otherwise, 1 if x(b) x(a), u 1 (b, x)= 0 otherwise, u 1 (c, x)= 0 for all x Z(C), u 1 (d, x)= 1 for all x Z(C). 1 if x(c)> x(d), u 2 (a, x)= 0 otherwise, 1 if x(d)> x(c), u 2 (b, x)= 0 otherwise, u 2 (c, x)= 0 for all x Z(C), u 2 (d, x)= 1 for all x Z(C). Actions c and d are dominated for both types. If we first eliminate d from C 1 and C 2 then b is dominated for type 2 players. Eliminating b from C 2 and c from C 1 and C 2, we see that at least 3/4 of the population choose a. Correspondingly, the best action for players of type 1 for every remaining strategy of the population is to also play a. We obtain that (a,a) survives the process of iterated deletion of dominated actions.

21 18 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES On the other hand, if we first eliminate c from C 1 and C 2 then a is dominated for type 2 players. We can eliminate a for type 2 players and d for every player in the game to conclude that at least 3/4 of the population choose b. Provided the expected number of players n is large enough, choosing b dominates choosing a for players of type 1. With this order of elimination of dominated actions, only the strategy function (b, b) survives. Note that the two equilibria that we obtain through the process of iterated deletion of dominated actions also induce different expected utility to the players in the game. Thus, if we want to provide a definition of equilibrium that is robust against iterated deletion of dominated actions we are led to define a set-valued concept. In the previous example, e.g., such an equilibrium concept would have to include both (a, a) and (b, b). Following Kohlberg and Mertens (1986) we say that a set of equilibria is stable if it is minimal with respect to the following property: PROPERTY (S). S Σ is a closed set of Nash equilibria of Γ satisfying: for any ε>0 there is a η>0 such that for any perturbation (η,µ ) with 0<η< η we can find a σ that is ε-close to S and satisfies σ BR((1 η)δ(σ)+ηµ ). REMARK 1.2. Property (S) in Kohlberg and Mertens (1986) requires that every close by strategy perturbed game have a Nash equilibrium close to S. Taking into account the space of perturbations used here (see page 12), we instead directly perturb the best response correspondence by perturbing the aggregate behavior of the population. As a result, Property (S) here requires that every close by perturbed correspondence have a fixed point close to S. Of course, Proposition 1.4 implies that such a fixed point is a Nash equilibrium of a close by (payoff) perturbed Poisson game. PROPOSITION 1.6. Every Poisson game has a stable set. Existence of stable sets in Poisson games is a particular case of a more general existence result. Stable sets in Poisson games are an example of Q-robust

22 1.5. STABILITY 19 2 U(b, ) σ U(a, ) τ(a) 0 1 FIGURE 1.4. Utility functions in a game with a disconnected stable set. sets of fixed points (McLennan (2012, Definition 8.3.5)). Loosely speaking, a set of fixed points X of a correspondence F is essential if every correspondence close to F has a fixed point close to X. This means that X is stable against every small perturbation of F. For instance, we can show that the set of all Nash equilibria of a (Poisson) game is essential. We can weaken this concept and restrict the set of allowed perturbations to those belonging to some class Q. (In our case, the characterization given in Theorem 1.1 indicates that we only consider perturbations caused by altering the average behavior of the population towards some µ M.) Then we say that a set of fixed points X of a correspondence F is Q-robust if every correspondence close to F that can be obtained through a perturbation in Q has a fixed point close to X. McLennan (2012) shows that, if F is an upper semicountinuous and closed valued correspondence, every Q-robust set contains a minimal Q-robust set and that every connected Q-robust set contains a minimal connected Q-robust set (Theorem 8.3.8). However, not every stable set is necessarily connected. Indeed, let us modify the utility functions in Example 1.3 so that the expected utility functions are those depicted in Figure 2.1. (Utility functions u(a, ) and u(b, ) can be found that generate such U(a, ) and U(b, ).) In this new game, U(a, ) and U(b, ) coincide in three isolated points. Furthermore, there are 2 stable sets, {σ } and {(a),(b)}. Not only is the latter stable set disconnected but also its members belong to different connected components of Nash equilibria. Hence, {σ } is the unique connected stable set.

23 20 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES We now prove that stable sets satisfy admissibility. PROPOSITION 1.7. Every point of a stable set is an outer-perfect, hence, undominated, equilibrium. PROOF. Let S be a stable set and let σ S be a strategy function that is not an outer-perfect equilibrium. Therefore, there is some ε > 0 and some η > 0 such that for every η < η and every µ we have ς BR((1 η)δ(ς)+ηµ ) whenever d(σ,ς)< ε. This implies that no strategy in the open ball B(σ, ε/2) { ς : d(σ,ς)< ε/2 } is an outer-perfect equilibrium either. Thus, it follows that S\{B(σ, ε/2)} satisfies Property (S), so either it is a stable set or it contains one. By minimality, S is not a stable set. Furthermore, stable sets are robust to elimination of dominated actions in the following sense: PROPOSITION 1.8. A stable set contains a stable set of any game obtained by deletion of a dominated pure action or a pure action that is an inferior response to any strategy function in the stable set. PROOF. Take a stable set S of the Poisson game Γ. Let c C t be an action that is either dominated for players of type t or satisfies c BR t (τ(σ)) for every σ S. Let Γ be the reduced game obtained from Γ by deleting c from C t. We know that σ S implies σ t (c)=0. Therefore, every strategy function in S can be considered as a strategy function in the smaller game Γ. Let Σ Σ be the resulting space of mixed strategies, so that τ( Σ) τ(σ). Furthermore, let the set of Borel measures on τ( Σ). M be Fix ε and choose an η as in Property (S). Consider the measures µ M and µ M. For any 0<κ<1, we have µ κ κµ+(1 κ) µ M. Hence, there is a σ κ that is ε-close to S such that σ κ BR((1 η)δ(σ κ )+ηµ κ ). Taking the limit as κ approaches zero gives us, by continuity, a strategy function σ that is ε-close to S and satisfies σ BR((1 η)δ( σ)+η µ). We conclude that S satisfies Property (S) in Γ. Thus, either S is a stable set of Γ or it contains one.

24 1.6. EXAMPLES 21 REMARK 1.3. Robustness against elimination of inferior responses has been used to formalize forward induction (Kohlberg and Mertens (1986); Mertens (1989)). Once we fix a solution of the game, players should consider as certain not to be employed those behaviors of the opponents in which some players use an inferior response against every member of the solution. If we accept that, we can ask that the solution be robust against the deletion of such inferior responses (Kohlberg (1990, p. 13); Hillas and Kohlberg (2002, p. 1645)). A similar reasoning may be used in Poisson games. Therefore, in this sense, we can say that stable sets in a Poisson game satisfy forward induction Examples We now compute the stable sets of the past examples. In Example 1.1 the only undominated action is a so, by admissibility, {(a)} is the unique stable set. In Example 1.2 the strict equilibrium (b, b) is, of course, a singleton stable set. The strategy function (a,a) is a Nash equilibrium such that, for every small perturbation, the corresponding perturbed Poisson game has a Nash equilibrium close to (a,a). To see this note that action a is a strict best response for type 2 players. For players of type 1, if a perturbation lifts U(a, ) more than U(b, ) then a is a strict best response in the perturbed game. (See the discussion following Equation (1.4.2).) On the other hand, if a perturbation lifts U(b, ) more than U(a, ) then both functions cross at some point close to τ(a)=1. Hence, {(a,a)} is also a stable set. Finally, we can also see that the strategy function ( 1 4 a+ 3 4 b,a) is strictly outer-perfect and, consequently, also a singleton stable set. 7 The Poisson game in Example 1.3 (see also the game described in footnote 6) has two Nash equilibria that are also outer-perfect, the pure strategy (b) and a 7 A strictly outer-perfect equilibrium of a Poisson game Γ is a Nash equilibrium σ with the property that every perturbed Poisson game sufficiently close to Γ has a Nash equilibrium close to σ.

25 22 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES mixed strategy σ that satisfies U(a,σ )= U(b,σ ). The set {(b)} is not stable because for those perturbations that, in the resulting perturbed Poisson game, lift U(a, ) more than U(b, ) there is no Nash equilibrium close to (b). In turn, {σ } is clearly stable. Example 1.4 has a one dimensional and connected set of Nash equilibria that goes from (a,a) to (b, b). (In every point of this set type 2 players are indifferent between a and b and, in a subset of it, type 1 players are also indifferent between a and b). We already argued that a stable set must contain (a,a) and (b, b). In both equilibria type 1 players play a strict best response. Given that neither a nor b are dominated, there are close by perturbed games that lift U 2 (a, ) more than U 2 (b, ) as well as perturbed games that lift U 2 (b, ) more than U 2 (a, ). The strategy function (a,a) is a Nash equilibrium of every game in the first class of perturbed games while (b, b) is a Nash equilibrium of every game in the second class of perturbed games. Therefore, by minimality, the unique stable set is {(a, a),(b, b)}. We conclude this section analyzing a variation of the referendum example proposed at the beginning of Section 3. EXAMPLE 1.5 (A voting example). There is a referendum where voters have to vote either yes or no to some new policy and at least K > 1 voters should vote yes for the policy to be implemented. For concreteness, let us assume K = 2 and that the expected number of players is 4. Every voter prefers the new policy to the status quo. Let us fix players payoff from the outcome of the election equal to 1 if the policy is implemented and equal to 0 if it is not. Suppose further that there are two types of voters. Type 1 voters incur a cost c = 1 2 e 1 2 ( 0.3) if they vote yes whereas type 2 voters do not have any cost of voting. Let the probability that a player is of type 2 be equal to 1 8. Voting yes is a weakly dominant action for type 2 players. They are only indifferent between yes and no under the strategy function (no,no). The expected utility functions of type 1 players are depicted in Figure 1.5. Given the utility

26 1.6. EXAMPLES 23 U 1 (no, ) U 1 (yes, ) 1 8 τ 1 τ(yes) FIGURE 1.5. Utility functions for type 1 players in Example 1.5. values chosen, U 1 (no, ) represents the probability that two or more voters vote yes for each value of τ(yes). On the other hand, U 1 (yes, ) is equal to the probability that one or more voters vote yes minus the cost c. The two functions cross in two isolated points, 1 8 and τ ( 0.44). When τ(yes)< 1 8, few other voters are expected to vote yes and type 1 voters prefer to vote no because their probability of being pivotal is not enough to overcome their cost to voting yes. As the number of other voters who are expected to vote yes increases, the probability of being pivotal in the referendum increases and type 1 voters start preferring voting yes to voting no. When the number of other voters who are expected to vote yes grows even larger so that τ(yes) > τ, the probability that the other voters meet the threshold necessary for the policy to be implemented increases, making yes again an inferior response for type 1 voters. Hence, this game has three isolated Nash equilibria. There is a dominated Nash equilibrium where every player votes no, a low support equilibrium where only type 2 players play yes, and a high support equilibrium where type 2 voters play yes and type 1 voters play yes with probability 8 7 (τ 1 8 ). The last two Nash equilibria are both outer-perfect, however, the high support equilibrium is the unique stable set of the game. Indeed, consider the low support equilibrium and eliminate the dominated action no for type 2 players. In the reduced game at least 1 8 of the population vote yes. Thus, if we only consider values of τ such that τ(yes) 1 8, we obtain a picture similar to the one in Figure 1.3. In

27 24 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES the same fashion as in that example, it can be seen that there are close by perturbed games that do not have a Nash equilibrium close to the low support equilibrium. From this we conclude that the unique stable set of the game consists only of the high support equilibrium.

28 APPENDIX A. STABLE SETS IN GENERIC POISSON GAMES 25 Appendix A. Stable Sets in Generic Poisson Games We show that for generic Poisson games every Nash equilibrium is a singleton stable set. We do this in a similar fashion to Carbonell-Nicolau (2010) who uses Fort s Theorem (Fort (1951)) to show that, for some large families of infinite normal-form games, generic members are such that every Nash equilibrium is essential. 8 We point out, however, that the same caveat that is usually raised upon this type of genericity results applies here. The examples of Poisson games that we find in applications are nongeneric: there typically is a non-injective function mapping action profiles to events (in the case of voting games, e.g., pivotal events) where utilities are defined instead. Once we fix n, T, r, C an (C t ) t T, a Poisson game is given by a function u : T C Z(C) R. Since T and C are finite and Z(C) is countable, we can see such a function u as a point in the space of all bounded sequences l. Thus, the Nash equilibrium correspondence NE can be thought of as NE : l Σ. Such a correspondence is upper semicontinuous and compact valued. Recall that a G δ set is a countable intersection of open sets. A topological space is called a Baire space if the union of any countable collection of closed sets with empty interior has empty interior. Since (l, ) is a Banach space, 9 the Baire Category Theorem implies that it is also a Baire space. THEOREM 1.2 (Fort (1951)). If F : X Y is an upper semicontinuous and compact valued correspondence from a Baire space to a metric space then F is both upper and lower semicontinuous at every point of a dense G δ subset of X. At a lower semicontinuity point u of the Nash equilibrium correspondence, for every Nash equilibrium σ of u and every sequence of Poisson games {u k } k converging to u, there is an associated sequence {σ k } k converging to σ such that 8 A Nash equilibrium σ of a game Γ is essential (Wu Wen-Tsun (1963)) if every game close to Γ has a Nash equilibrium close to σ. Of course, an essential Nash equilibrium is a singleton stable set. 9 In our context, we can write u = max t T max c Ct sup ut x Z(C) (c, x).

29 26 1. STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES σ k is a Nash equilibrium of u k for every k. This is, in particular, true for every sequence of perturbed Poisson games converging to u. We thus conclude: COROLLARY 1.3. For every game in a dense G δ set of Poisson games every Nash equilibrium is a singleton stable set. Appendix B. On the Inadequacy of Inner-Perfection In the following example we illustrate why a definition of stability based on inner-perfect equilibrium perturbations is not adequate even if it is accompanied by a restriction that only allows to select undominated actions. EXAMPLE 1.6. Consider the Poisson game Γ with n=2, only one type, set of actions C = {a, b, c}, and utility function u(a, x) = { x(c)+1 x(c) if x(a)+ x(c)=1, otherwise, u(b, x) = e 1 for all x Z(C), u(c, x) = 1 for all x Z(C). Action γ= 1 2 a+ 1 2 b is not dominated: it does better than action a against the strategy (b) and it does better than action b against the strategy ( 1 2 b+ 1 2 c). For any strategy-perturbation (ε,σ ) such that ε is close enough to zero, consider the strategy-perturbed game Γ ε,σ and the strategy ς ε,σ 1 (( 1 z(εσ ) ( (c)) 1+ z(εσ εσ (c) εσ (c)) (a) a+ 1 ε 2 2 ) ) εσ (b) b, where the correcting factor z(εσ (c))>0 is chosen so that P(1 1 z(εσ (c)))= e 1 2εσ (c). The strategy ς ε,σ is an undominated Nash equilibrium of the strategy-perturbed game Γ ε,σ which is close to σ=( 1 2 a+ 1 2 b). (Note that under the corresponding perturbed strategy σ ε,σ (1 ε)ς ε,σ +εσ the expected value of x(c) is 2εσ (c) and, therefore, U(a,σ ε,σ )= e 1.) Hence, {( 1 2 a+ 1 2 b)} would be a stable set of the Poisson game according to a definition of stability based on strategy-perturbations (i.e. inner-perfection).

STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES

STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES STRATEGIC STABILITY IN POISSON GAMES FRANCESCO DE SINOPOLI, CLAUDIA MERONI, AND CARLOS PIMIENTA ABSTRACT. In Poisson games, an extension of perfect equilibrium based on perturbations of the strategy space

More information

The structure of Nash equilibria in Poisson games

The structure of Nash equilibria in Poisson games Working Paper Series Department of Economics University of Verona The structure of Nash equilibria in Poisson games Claudia Meroni, Carlos Pimienta WP Number: 25 October 2015 ISSN: 2036-2919 (paper), 2036-4679

More information

UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES

UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES FRANCESCO DE SINOPOLI AND CARLOS GONZÁLEZ PIMIENTA, Abstract. In games with population uncertainty some perfect equilibria are in dominated strategies.

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES

UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES UNDOMINATED (AND) PERFECT EQUILIBRIA IN POISSON GAMES FRANCESCO DE SINOPOLI AND CARLOS GONZÁLEZ PIMIENTA, Abstract. In games with population uncertainty some perfect equilibria are in dominated strategies.

More information

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Thema Working Paper n 2010-02 Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Sincere Scoring Rules Nunez Matias May, 2010 Sincere Scoring Rules Matías Núñez May 2010 Abstract Approval Voting is shown to be the unique

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Elnaz Bajoori, János Flesch, Dries Vermeulen. Perfect equilibrium in games with compact action spaces RM/11/029

Elnaz Bajoori, János Flesch, Dries Vermeulen. Perfect equilibrium in games with compact action spaces RM/11/029 Elnaz Bajoori, János Flesch, Dries Vermeulen Perfect equilibrium in games with compact action spaces RM//029 Perfect equilibrium in games with compact action spaces Elnaz Bajoori János Flesch Dries Vermeulen

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Amrita Dhillon and Ben Lockwood This version: March 2001 Abstract De Sinopoli and Turrini (1999) present an example to show

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction CRITICAL TYPES JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. Economic models employ assumptions about agents infinite hierarchies of belief. We might hope to achieve reasonable approximations by specifying

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games journal of economic theory 82, 267276 (1998) article no. ET982418 Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games Atsushi Kajii* Institute of Policy and Planning Sciences, University of Tsukuba, 1-1-1

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Mark Fey Department of Political Science University of Rochester

More information

Essential equilibria in normal-form games

Essential equilibria in normal-form games Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010) 421 431 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Note Essential equilibria in normal-form games Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau 1 Department of Economics, Rutgers University, 75 Hamilton

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

The Index of Nash Equilibria

The Index of Nash Equilibria Equilibria in Games, Santiago, Chile January 10, 2017 Finite Normal-Form Games We consider in these lectures, the set of finite games with fixed strategy sets and parametrized by the payoff functions.

More information

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED DOV SAMET Abstract. An informal argument shows that common knowledge of rationality implies the iterative elimination of strongly dominated strategies. Rationality

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Game Theory and Rationality

Game Theory and Rationality April 6, 2015 Notation for Strategic Form Games Definition A strategic form game (or normal form game) is defined by 1 The set of players i = {1,..., N} 2 The (usually finite) set of actions A i for each

More information

Math 535: Topology Homework 1. Mueen Nawaz

Math 535: Topology Homework 1. Mueen Nawaz Math 535: Topology Homework 1 Mueen Nawaz Mueen Nawaz Math 535 Topology Homework 1 Problem 1 Problem 1 Find all topologies on the set X = {0, 1, 2}. In the list below, a, b, c X and it is assumed that

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies

Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies Iterated Strict Dominance in Pure Strategies We know that no rational player ever plays strictly dominated strategies. As each player knows that each player is rational, each player knows that his opponents

More information

Condorcet Consistency of Approval Voting: a counter example in Large Poisson Games

Condorcet Consistency of Approval Voting: a counter example in Large Poisson Games Condorcet Consistency of Approval Voting: a counter example in Large Poisson Games Matías Núñez May 2009 Abstract Approval Voting is analyzed in a context of large elections with strategic voters: the

More information

ON FORWARD INDUCTION

ON FORWARD INDUCTION Econometrica, Submission #6956, revised ON FORWARD INDUCTION SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. A player s pure strategy is called relevant for an outcome of a game in extensive form with perfect

More information

CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY

CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY Srihari Govindan and Robert Wilson University of Iowa and Stanford University 1 Motive for Equilibrium Selection The original Nash definition allows 1. Multiple equilibria

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics International Journal of Game Theory ISSN 0020-7276 Volume 44 Number 1 Int J Game Theory

More information

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction Lecture notes Course Analysis for PhD students Uppsala University, Spring 2018 Rostyslav Kozhan Chapter 1 Measures 1.1 Some prerequisites I will follow closely the textbook Real analysis: Modern Techniques

More information

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY H. JEROME KEISLER AND YENENG SUN Abstract. An atomless probability space (Ω, A, P ) is said to have the saturation property for a probability measure µ on

More information

The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games

The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games Games 20, 2, 235-256; doi:0.3390/g2030235 Article OPEN ACCESS games ISSN 2073-4336 www.mdpi.com/journal/games The Existence of Perfect Equilibrium in Discontinuous Games Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau Department

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009

NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009 NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009 Kohlberg and Mertens (Econometrica 1986) We will use the term (game) tree for the extensive form of a game with perfect recall (i.e., where every player

More information

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu

Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS. Heng Liu Working Paper EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN COMMON-VALUE SECOND-PRICE AUCTIONS Heng Liu This note considers equilibrium selection in common-value secondprice auctions with two bidders. We show that for each

More information

Construction of a general measure structure

Construction of a general measure structure Chapter 4 Construction of a general measure structure We turn to the development of general measure theory. The ingredients are a set describing the universe of points, a class of measurable subsets along

More information

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan.

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan. RESEARCH PAPER NO. 2000 AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS Srihari Govindan Robert Wilson September 2008 This work was partially funded by a National Science

More information

Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games

Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games Hannu Salonen 1 Department of Economics University of Turku 20014 Turku Finland email: hansal@utu.fi Abstract We study games with utilitarian preferences: the

More information

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments University of Pennsylvania Department of Economics June 22, 2008 Introduction: Higher Order Beliefs Global Games (Carlsson and Van Damme, 1993): A B A 0, 0 0, θ 2 B θ 2, 0 θ, θ Dominance Regions: A if

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

The Condorcet Jur(ies) Theorem

The Condorcet Jur(ies) Theorem The Condorcet Jur(ies) Theorem David S. Ahn University of California, Berkeley Santiago Oliveros Haas School of Business, UC Berkeley September 2010 Abstract Two issues can be decided in a single election

More information

Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games. Aboa Centre for Economics

Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games. Aboa Centre for Economics Hannu Salonen Utilitarian Preferences and Potential Games Aboa Centre for Economics Discussion paper No. 85 Turku 2013 The Aboa Centre for Economics is a joint initiative of the economics departments of

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Asu Ozdaglar MIT March 2, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review of Supermodular Games Reading: Fudenberg and Tirole, Section 12.3.

More information

Lower Semicontinuity of the Solution Set Mapping in Some Optimization Problems

Lower Semicontinuity of the Solution Set Mapping in Some Optimization Problems Lower Semicontinuity of the Solution Set Mapping in Some Optimization Problems Roberto Lucchetti coauthors: A. Daniilidis, M.A. Goberna, M.A. López, Y. Viossat Dipartimento di Matematica, Politecnico di

More information

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים THE HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM TOWARDS A CHARACTERIZATION OF RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS by ITAI ARIELI Discussion Paper # 475 February 2008 מרכז לחקר הרציונליות CENTER FOR THE

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland.

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. Measures These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. 1 Introduction Our motivation for studying measure theory is to lay a foundation

More information

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem MS&E 336 Lecture 8: Supermodular games Ramesh Johari April 30, 2007 In this lecture, we develop the theory of supermodular games; key references are the papers of Topkis [7], Vives [8], and Milgrom and

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses Chapter 4 Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses Let us return now to our analysis of an arbitrary strategic game G := (S 1,...,S n, p 1,...,p n ). Let s i, s i be strategies of player i. We say that

More information

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about 0368.4170: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen Lecture 7 02 December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about Two-Player zero-sum games (min-max theorem) Mixed

More information

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Geir B. Asheim a Andrés Perea b October 16, 2017 Abstract We provide comparable algorithms for the Dekel-Fudenberg procedure, iterated admissibility, proper rationalizability

More information

SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction

SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. A refinement of the set of Nash equilibria that satisfies two assumptions is shown to select a subset that is stable

More information

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions By Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago Paper can be found at https://sites.google.com/site/philipjreny/home/research

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces Course 212: Academic Year 1991-2 Section 1: Metric Spaces D. R. Wilkins Contents 1 Metric Spaces 3 1.1 Distance Functions and Metric Spaces............. 3 1.2 Convergence and Continuity in Metric Spaces.........

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

LECTURE 15: COMPLETENESS AND CONVEXITY

LECTURE 15: COMPLETENESS AND CONVEXITY LECTURE 15: COMPLETENESS AND CONVEXITY 1. The Hopf-Rinow Theorem Recall that a Riemannian manifold (M, g) is called geodesically complete if the maximal defining interval of any geodesic is R. On the other

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Your first day at work MATH 806 (Fall 2015)

Your first day at work MATH 806 (Fall 2015) Your first day at work MATH 806 (Fall 2015) 1. Let X be a set (with no particular algebraic structure). A function d : X X R is called a metric on X (and then X is called a metric space) when d satisfies

More information

Zero sum games Proving the vn theorem. Zero sum games. Roberto Lucchetti. Politecnico di Milano

Zero sum games Proving the vn theorem. Zero sum games. Roberto Lucchetti. Politecnico di Milano Politecnico di Milano General form Definition A two player zero sum game in strategic form is the triplet (X, Y, f : X Y R) f (x, y) is what Pl1 gets from Pl2, when they play x, y respectively. Thus g

More information

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem Set 2: s Math 201A: Fall 2016 Problem 1. (a) Prove that a closed subset of a complete metric space is complete. (b) Prove that a closed subset of a compact metric space is compact. (c) Prove that

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class. Political Economy of Institutions and Development: 14.773 Problem Set 1 Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class. Answer Questions 1-3. handed in. The other two questions are for practice and are not

More information

Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions

Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics, University of Chicago Abstract: We develop concepts

More information

Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting

Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting Online Appendix: Optimal Retrospective Voting Ethan Bueno de Mesquita 1 Amanda Friedenberg 2 The notation and setup will be as in the main text, with the following exceptions: Let x l : Ω R be a random

More information

An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control

An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control Vasile Staicu University of Aveiro UNICA, May 2018 Vasile Staicu (University of Aveiro) An introduction to Mathematical Theory of Control UNICA, May 2018

More information

Generic Determinacy of Nash Equilibrium in Network Formation Games

Generic Determinacy of Nash Equilibrium in Network Formation Games School of Economics UNSW, Sydney 2052 Australia http://www.economics.unsw.edu.au Generic Determinacy of Nash Equilibrium in Network Formation Games Carlos Gonzáles Pimienta School of Economics Discussion

More information

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Perfect information A finite extensive game with perfect information

More information

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers Page 1 Theorems Wednesday, May 9, 2018 12:53 AM Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property Suppose is an ordered set with the least-upper-bound property Suppose, and is bounded below be the set of lower

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Variants of Nash Equilibrium. CMPT 882 Computational Game Theory Simon Fraser University Spring 2010 Instructor: Oliver Schulte

Variants of Nash Equilibrium. CMPT 882 Computational Game Theory Simon Fraser University Spring 2010 Instructor: Oliver Schulte Variants of Nash Equilibrium CMPT 882 Computational Game Theory Simon Fraser University Spring 2010 Instructor: Oliver Schulte 1 Equilibrium Refinements A complex game may have many Nash equilibria. Can

More information

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics - PhD in Part 1: Supermodularity and complementarity in the one-dimensional and Paulo Brito ISEG - Technical University of Lisbon November 24, 2010 1 2 - Supermodular optimization 3 one-dimensional 4 Supermodular

More information

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define 1 Measures 1.1 Jordan content in R N II - REAL ANALYSIS Let I be an interval in R. Then its 1-content is defined as c 1 (I) := b a if I is bounded with endpoints a, b. If I is unbounded, we define c 1

More information

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games MATHIEU MARTIN THEMA, Departments of Economics Université de Cergy Pontoise, 33 Boulevard du Port, 95011 Cergy Pontoise cedex, France. e-mail: mathieu.martin@eco.u-cergy.fr

More information

Noisy Evolution in Normal Form Games

Noisy Evolution in Normal Form Games Noisy Evolution in Normal Form Games Christoph Kuzmics J. L. Kellogg School of Management Northwestern University 2001 Sheridan Road Evanston, IL 60208-2009 email: C.A.Kuzmics.99@cantab.net phone: 847

More information

Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall

Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall Carlos Alós-Ferrer and Klaus Ritzberger University of Cologne and Royal Holloway, University of London, 1 and VGSF 1 as of Aug. 1, 2016 1 Introduction

More information

Basic Game Theory. Kate Larson. January 7, University of Waterloo. Kate Larson. What is Game Theory? Normal Form Games. Computing Equilibria

Basic Game Theory. Kate Larson. January 7, University of Waterloo. Kate Larson. What is Game Theory? Normal Form Games. Computing Equilibria Basic Game Theory University of Waterloo January 7, 2013 Outline 1 2 3 What is game theory? The study of games! Bluffing in poker What move to make in chess How to play Rock-Scissors-Paper Also study of

More information

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities NUPRI Working Paper 2016-03 Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities Takuya Iimura, Toshimasa Maruta, and Takahiro Watanabe October, 2016 Nihon University Population Research Institute http://www.nihon-u.ac.jp/research/institute/population/nupri/en/publications.html

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 25, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Uniqueness of a Pure Nash Equilibrium for Continuous Games Reading: Rosen J.B., Existence

More information

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples February 24, 2011 Summary: We introduce the Nash Equilibrium: an outcome (action profile) which is stable in the sense that no player

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

l(y j ) = 0 for all y j (1)

l(y j ) = 0 for all y j (1) Problem 1. The closed linear span of a subset {y j } of a normed vector space is defined as the intersection of all closed subspaces containing all y j and thus the smallest such subspace. 1 Show that

More information

1. Introduction. 2. A Simple Model

1. Introduction. 2. A Simple Model . Introduction In the last years, evolutionary-game theory has provided robust solutions to the problem of selection among multiple Nash equilibria in symmetric coordination games (Samuelson, 997). More

More information

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1

MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION. Problem 1 MATH 54 - TOPOLOGY SUMMER 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION ELEMENTS OF SOLUTION Problem 1 1. Let X be a Hausdorff space and K 1, K 2 disjoint compact subsets of X. Prove that there exist disjoint open sets U 1 and

More information

Mathematical Methods in Economics (Part I) Lecture Note

Mathematical Methods in Economics (Part I) Lecture Note Mathematical Methods in Economics (Part I) Lecture Note Kai Hao Yang 09/03/2018 Contents 1 Basic Topology and Linear Algebra 4 1.1 Review of Metric Space and Introduction of Topological Space........ 4

More information

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627 U.S.A. Michel Le Breton CORE

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES PRISCILLA T. Y. MAN Abstract. Reputation is often modelled by a small but positive prior probability that a player is a behavioral type in repeated games. This paper

More information

ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction

ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. The connected uniformly-hyperstable sets of a finite game are shown to be precisely the essential components of Nash equilibria. 1. Introduction

More information

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA MARIA GOLTSMAN Abstract. This note shows that, in separable environments, any monotonic social choice function

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information