A Logical View of Probability

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A Logical View of Probability"

Transcription

1 A Logical View of Probability Nic Wilson 1 and Serafn Moral 2 Abstract. Imprecise Probability (or Upper and Lower Probability) is represented as a very simple but powerful logic. Despite having a very dierent language from classical logics, it enjoys many of the most important properties, which means that some extensions to classical logic can be applied in a fairly straightforward way. The logic is extended to allow qualitative grades of belief, which can be used to represent degrees of caution, and this is applied to create theories of belief revision and non-monotonic inference for probability statements. We also construct a theory of default probability which is based on a variant of Reiter's default logic this can be used to express and reason with default probability statements. 1 INTRODUCTION The best understood and most highly developed theory of uncertainty is Bayesian probability. There is a large literature on its foundations and there are many dierent justications of the theory however, all of these assume that for any proposition a, the beliefs in a and :a are strongly tied together. Without compelling justication, this assumption greatly restricts the type of information that can be satisfactorily represented, e.g., it makes it impossible to represent adequately partial information about an unknown chance distribution P suchas0:6 P(a) 0:8. The strict Bayesian requirement that an epistemic state be a single probability function seems unreasonable. A natural extension of the Bayesian theory is thus to allow sets of probability functions and to consider constraints and bounds on these, and to calculate supremum and inmum values of the probabilities of propositions (known as Upper and Lower Probabilities) given the constraints. Early work on this includes Boole [1] and Good [2] and early appearances in the Articial Intelligence literature include [3,4]. Walley's Imprecise Probability [5] is arguably the most satisfactory of all current theories of uncertain reasoning from a foundational point of view. It is a behavioural version of Upper and Lower Probability built on the work of Smith [6] and Williams [7]. Mathematically, it is similar to other Lower Probability theories but it is based on gambles, with coherence axioms relating the gambles that an agent nds desirable from here it is a small step to turning the system into a logic. In section 2, we dene this logic with a language, very simple proof theory and semantics. The results of this section all follow fairly easily from results in [5]. 1 Department of Computer Science, Queen Mary and Westeld College, Mile End Rd., London E1 4NS, UK 2 Departamento de Ciencias de la Computacion e I. A., Universidad de Granada, Granada - Spain Gambles can represent a surprisingly varied set of probability statements. Another way of viewing gambles is as linear conc 1994 N. Wilson and S. Moral ECAI th European Conference on Articial Intelligence Edited by A. Cohn Published in 1994 by John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Apart from being a simple and elegant way to express this theory of probability, there are other benets of expressing it as a logic. It brings into the logician's domain this semantically very well founded, fairly well-behaved and expressive representation of beliefs. Because the logic has many of the properties of classical logics, it means that augmentations of classical logic can be applied relatively easily to this logic. Imprecise Probability does not distinguish caution from ignorance in section 3 we look at a way of extending the theory to allow qualitative grades, which can be used to represent degrees of caution. Like classical logic, it is very conservative, and is monotonic. It therefore seems natural to look at extensions which tentatively allow stronger conclusions to be drawn, but avoid inconsistency. Three examples of this are given in section 4, work on belief revision and non-monotonic inference relations is extended to this logic, which leads to ways of resolving inconsistencies, and in section 5, a version of Reiter's Default Logic is applied, which allows more complex tentative assumptions. 2 THE LOGIC OF GAMBLES Let be a nite set of possibilities, exactly one of which must be true. A gamble on is a function from to IR. If you were to accept gamble X and! turned out to be true then you would gain X(!) utiles (so you would lose if X(!) < 0). An agent's beliefs are elicited by asking them to tell us a set ; of gambles they nd acceptable, i.e., gambles they would be happy to accept. For 2 IR we write for the constant gamble dened by (!) = for all! 2. If >0 we should certainly consider gamble acceptable since, whatever happens, we gain. If <0 then we should certainly not accept gamble since, whatever happens, we lose. Addition and subtraction of gambles is dened pointwise, so that for gambles X and Y, for each! 2, (X ; Y )(!) =X(!) ; Y (!). For a we dene gamble a to be the indicator function of a, so that a(!) =1if! 2 a and a(!) = 0 otherwise. Any such gamble a would seem acceptable since you couldn't lose. On the other hand, the gamble a ; 1 (given by (a ; 1)(!) =0if! 2 a (a; 1)(!) =;1 otherwise) would only be acceptable to you if you were certain that a were true. If = f! 1! 2g and X is the gamble f! 1g;0:5 (so that X(! 1)=0:5 and X(! 2)=;0:5) and you considered! 1 more likely than! 2 then it seems that you should consider the gamble X acceptable. The expressiveness of gambles

2 straints on an unknown chance distribution, and indeed any such linear inequality can be represented as a gamble. For example, the constraint Pr(a) 0:6 would be represented by the gamble a ; 0:6 the constraint Pr(a) Pr(b) +0:1 would be represented by the gamble b+0:1;a the constraint Pr(ajb) 0:9 by the gamble 0:9b ; (a \ b). In general a linear constraint 1 Pr(a 1)++ k Pr(a k ) is represented by the gamble X = 1a k a k ;. The constraint 1 Pr(a 1)++ k Pr(a k ) is equivalent to the constraint (; 1)Pr(a 1)++(; k )Pr(a k ) ; and so is represented by the gamble ;X. Hence 1 Pr(a 1)++ k Pr(a k )= is represented by the pair of gambles fx ;Xg. The language does, however, have some limitations: independence relationships or constraints such as Pr(ajb) Pr(a) cannot be represented simply in terms of gambles, since they are non-linear. The language Let L be the set of gambles on. The constant gamble 1 we write as > and the constant gamble ;1 we write as?. Proof theory We are going to dene 3 an inference relation `, where for ; L and X 2L,;`X is intended to mean `Given that I'm prepared to accept any gamble in ; then I should also be prepared to accept X'. The axioms and inference rules used to dene ` will be justied by the semantics (with probability functions as models) given later. However, as Walley shows, they can be justied directly (and arguably more satisfactorily, since then the theory is not based on additive probability functions). Axiom Schema: X, for any X with minx 0. For any such X we can't lose so it should be acceptable. Inference Rule (Schema) 1: For any 2 IR such that >0 the inference rule From X deduce X. This relates to the situation where stakes are multiplied by a factor. Inference Rule 2: From X and Y deduce X + Y. This relates to the combination of two gambles. Then, in the usual way, we say that ; Lproves X 2L, abbreviated to ; ` X, if there is a nite sequence X 1... X n of gambles in L with X n = X and each X i is either an element of ;, an axiom or is produced by an inference rule from earlier elements in the sequence. The logical closure, Th(;), of ; Lis dened to be the set fx 2L :;`Xg. The relation ` is reexive i.e., Th(;) ; it is monotonic i.e, ; ) Th(;) Th() it is transitive, i.e, Th(Th(;)) Th(;) (and therefore Th(Th(;)) = Th(;)) and compact i.e, if ; ` X then there exists nite ; 0 ; with ; 0 ` X. Set of gambles ; Lis said to be nitely-generated if Th(;) = Th(; 0 ) for some nite ; 0 ;. 3 Walley [5] is mainly concerned with the notion of `desirable' gambles which does not quite correspond to the relation ` dened here. Desirable gambles can be characterised with relation `0, de- ned in the same way as `, except the axiom schema is replaced by the following reduced set: X, for any X with minx >0. With the exception of completeness for nitely generated ;, `0 has all the properties of ` given here. Semantics The set of models M of L is dened to be the set of probability functions on. For probability function P and gamble P X, P(X) is dened to be the expected value of X, i.e., P(!)X(!). We say that probability function P satis-!2 es gamble X (written P j= X) ip(x) 0, that is, if and only if the expected utility is non-negative, i.e., i we would expect (in the long run) not to lose money from X if P represented objective chances. Note that P satises the constraint 1P(a 1)+ + k P(a k ) if and only if P j= X where X = 1a k a k ; is the gamble representing the constraint. We extend j= in the usual way: P satises set of gambles ; (written P j= ;) if and only if it satises every gamble X in ;, and the semantic entailment relation j= is dened by ; j= X i for all models P, [P j= ;) P j= X]. Theorem 1 (Soundness) For gamble X and set of gambles ;, ; ` X ) ; j= X. We almost have completeness: Theorem 2 (Almost Completeness) For gamble X and set of gambles ;, if; j= X then ; ` X + for all >0. We also have ; j= X if and only if for all ">0, ; ` X + " and also ; j= X +" for all ">0if and only if for all ">0, ; ` X+". If ; is nitely generated then we have full completeness: ; ` X ) ; j= X. Corollary For ; L, ; `? () ; j=?. If ; j=? then we say that ; is inconsistent otherwise ; is said to be consistent. If ; is inconsistent then ; ` X for any gamble X. The relation j= is reexive, transitive, monotonic, but not compact (consider ; = fn(a ; 1+ 1 n ):n2ing for some nonempty proper subset a of ). However, the above corollary means that it does satisfy the related property `If ; j=? then there exists nite ; 0 ; with ; 0 j=?'. Lower previsions and lower probabilities Associated with a set ; of gambles is the lower prevision P : L!IR dened, for X 2Lby P (X) = supf :;` X ; g. The value P (X) is the supremum of prices that the agent is willing to pay for X. By Soundness and Almost Completeness, P (X) = supf :;j= X ; g, which leads to P (X) = inffp(x) : P j= ;g. Lower prevision P is thus the lower envelope of fp :Pj= ;g. Ifa is a proposition, P (a) is usually referred to as the Lower Probability of a. P (a) is the inmum of P(a) over all probability functions P satisfying the constraints represented by ;. The supremum of P(a) over all such probability functions is known as the Upper Probability, P (a), and is given by P (a) =1; P (a). The proof theory can thus generate the optimal upper and lower bounds for the probability of a (or of the expected value of a gamble X), although it may well be less ecient than other more specialised methods such as [8,9]. 3 GRADED SETS OF GAMBLES The gambles that an agent nds acceptable can depend strongly on how cautious they are. For example, suppose I (the rst author) know that Joe lives in Cowley Road, Oxford (which has Knowledge Representation 387 N. Wilson and S. Moral

3 100 houses) but I've no idea which one. Let = f g refer to the set of possible houses that Joe could live in. Now suppose Bob asks me how much I'd be prepared to pay for the gamble corresponding to the proposition a = nf51g (and let's say 1 utile corresponds to 1000 pounds). I might pick P (a) =0:99, so that I would accept the gamble a ; for any <0:99 or I might consider that I don't know enough about a to bet against Bob and refuse to bet, or only accept extremely favourable odds, leading to P (a) about 0. What I decide here could be extremely arbitrary. The theory does not distinguish between caution and ignorance. A lower prevision/probability P may be close to being Bayesian because the knowledge of the agent is fairly complete, or because the agent is bold in her assessments (perhaps she is used to giving Bayesian beliefs). To deal with this problem we could use graded sets of gambles. A graded set of gambles 4 is a function from a set WLto a set D, where D has a total order on it. (A total order on D is a reexive, transitive relation, such that for all 2 D, either or, and only both if =.) For graded set of gambles g, and X Y 2W, g(x) <g(y ) means that X is more rmly believed than Y. For graded set of gambles g and 2 D, let g = fy 2W : g(y ) g. We write g j= (X ) ifg j= X, and g ` (X ) ifg ` X. The statement g j= (X ) can be thought of as saying that the agent, when being cautious to degree, nds X acceptable. For example D might be fcautious boldg with cautious < bold. fx : g(x) = cautiousg would be the more cautious and more deeply held beliefs, fx : g(x) = boldg would be more tentative beliefs. In the next section we will see how graded sets of gambles give rise to very well-behaved systems of belief revision and non-monotonic inference. 4 BELIEF REVISION AND NON-MONOTONIC INFERENCE RELATIONS An important problem is how to revise our beliefs (for this logic, a set of gambles) when we receive new information. If the new information is an observation that a proposition a is true then we condition our beliefs by a see [5] for details. However, if the new information is an extra set of gambles that the agent nds acceptable (perhaps after further consideration of the problem) then we need some way of incorporating this new set of gambles. Desirable properties of expansion and revision Gardenfors [11] considers the operations of expansion and revision of a logically closed set of propositions K by a proposition A (and also contraction, which we do not consider here). Expanding K by A means adding A to the belief set K without retracting any of K the result of the expansion is called K + A. Revising K with new information A means that we add 4 There is a strong relationship between graded sets of gambles and fuzzy probabilities and Gardenfors and Sahlin's unreliable probabilities [10] (using the correspondence between logically closed sets of gambles and convex sets of probability functions). A to the belief set but, if necessary, remove some of K so that the revised belief set KA is consistent. He advances postulates for both these operations. This work trivially generalises to expanding and revising K by a nite set of propositions ;, by adding the extra condition that K + = ; K+ A and K ; = KA where A is the conjunction of the elements in ;. Given this, Gardenfors' postulates can be expressed as follows: Postulates for Expansion (K + 1) Th(K + ; )=K+. ; (K + 2) ; K +. ; (K + 3) K K +. ; (K + 4) If ; K then K + = K. ; (K + 5) If K H then K + ; H +. ; (K + 6) For all logically closed K and all ;, K + ; is the smallest set satisfying (K + 1){(K + 5). Postulates for Revision (K 1) Th(K;)=K ;. (K 2) ; K;. (K 3) K; K +. ; (K 4) If K [ ; is consistent then K + ; K;. (K 5) K; is inconsistent if and only if ; is inconsistent. (K 6) If Th(;) = Th() then K; = K. (K 7) K;[ (K;) +. (K 8) If K; [ is consistent then (K;) + K;[. The postulates in this form can be applied to expanding and revising a logically closed set of gambles K by another set of gambles ; (which we will allow to be innite). Furthermore, the justications of the above postulates [11] may also be used for this case. The postulates for expansion determine a unique expansion operator, and, not surprisingly, we get the same result as for the propositional case. Theorem 3 There is a unique expansion operator satisfying (K + 1){(K + 6) (which sends pairs (K ;) to K + ; ) and it is given by K + ; = Th(K [ ;). The result also holds if we only allow nite ;. As in the propositional case, revision is more complex. It turns out that total pre-orders on K lead to a method of revision which satises the above postulates. A relation on a set W is said to be a total pre-order if it is reexive, transitive and for all v w 2W, either v w or w v (or both). A subset G of W is said to respect if [w 2Gand v w ) v 2G]. For each logically closed set of gambles, K let K be a total pre-order on K. For ; Ldene K; by X 2 K; if and only if either (i) ; is inconsistent, or (ii) there exists GK such that G respects K, G[; is consistent and G[; ` X. Theorem 4 The revision operator which maps pairs (K ;) to K; satises the belief revision postulates (K 1){(K 8). For classical belief revision there is a representation theorem (Theorem 4.30 of [11]) which shows (roughly speaking) that any revision operator satisfying the postulates can be represented using total pre-orderings on each belief set K. It is not clear that such a representation theorem is possible in this framework. However, if we were to dene propositions to be sets of probability functions, dene entailment as, then Theorem 1 of Spohn [13] suggests that there will be such a representation theorem between belief revision operators (or Knowledge Representation 388 N. Wilson and S. Moral

4 non-monotonic inference relations) and total pre-orders on the set of probability functions (with an appropriate well-ordering condition). Unfortunately it seems that this does not lead to a representation theorem for the gambles logic (using the correspondence between logically closed sets of gambles and convex sets of probability functions) because the `spheres' [11] may not be convex. Non-monotonic inference relations Makinson and Gardenfors [12] have shown that the belief revision postulates can be translated into properties of nonmonotonic inference relations between propositions. Such a non-monotonic inference relation j can be trivially extended to allow nite sets of propositions on the left hand side, by dening, for nite ;, ; j X () A j X where A is the conjunction of the propositions in ;. Let C(;) = fx :;j Xg. Equivalent versions of these properties of non-monotonic inference relations can be reached from the belief revision postulates (K 1){(K 8) by replacing K; by C(;), so that K = K gets replaced by C( ) (and using theorem 3). For example, ( j 8) is the property If C(;) [ is consistent then Th(C(;) [ ) C(; [ ), which is known as Rational Monotony. Again, in this form these properties can be interpreted as desirable properties for a non-monotonic inference relation on gambles. Theorem 5 Let be a total pre-order on L. Dene inference relation j as follows. For (possibly innite) ; Land X 2L, ; j X holds if and only if (i) ; is inconsistent or (ii) there exists GLsuch that G respects, G[; is consistent and G[; ` X. Then j satises non-monotonic inference relation postulates ( j 1){( j 8). Total pre-orders on sets of gambles are very closely related to graded sets of gambles. From graded set of gambles g on WLwecan dene a total pre-order on W by X Y () g(x) g(y ). (Conversely, if is a total pre-order on W, then dening equivalence relation by X Y () X Y and Y X, and letting D = W=, the total preorder induces a total order on D, and we can dene graded set of gambles g by g(x) = () X 2.) Therefore graded sets of gambles lead to well-behaved belief revision operators and non-monotonic inference relations. 5 DEFAULT PROBABILITY Imprecise probability is very conservative so that the conclusions can be disappointingly weak (especially after conditioning), giving us little information about which propositions are likely or unlikely. For example, constraints P(bja) = 1 and P(cjb) 0:999 lead to P (cja) = 0 since there is a probability function P which satises the two constraints and P(cja) = 0. If, to counter this, the agent makes very bold probability statements then there is a danger of inconsistency, which is even less useful. It is therefore desirable to have a theory of default probability where some of the probability statements are labelled as defaults, and could be retracted if they lead to inconsistency. It is also important to be able to make default independence assumptions, for example, if an expert does not know of any dependencies between two variables it is sometimes natural to assume, by default, that they are independent. A default logic We use an amended version of Reiter's default logic [14] because it has some nicer properties. 5 A default rule is a string of the form A : B=C with A B C nite subsets of L. This rule is intended to mean something like `if all of the elements of A are known and B is consistent with what we know then deduce C'. A default theory is a pair (D W) where WLis known as the facts and D is a set of default rules, which we will assume to be labelled, for some set, A i : B i : i 2 : C i For any dene Th (W) to be the (unique) smallest set ; Lsuch that ; W, Th(;) = ;, and if i 2 and ; A i then ; C i. For, if we allow ourselves to use inference rules A i=c i for i 2, then we can deduce any formula in Th (W) (and no others). However, if S Bi is now inconsistent then this i2 would seem to contradict the intention of the default rules. This motivates the denition of -consistent. Let = (D W) be a default theory. is said to be -consistent if Th (W) [ S i2 Bi is consistent. Dene C = f : is -consistentg. E is said to be an extension of if E =Th (W) for some maximal in C. In default logic the extensions are intended to be the different possible completions, using the default rules, of an incomplete set of facts about the world. In practice, extensions would not usually be calculated, but instead we might generate pairs (X ) where X 2 Th (W ), and we are interested in only those where is -consistent a simple monotonic logic governs the generation of such pairs, see [15]. Extensions could also be dened using j= instead of `. The corollary to Almost Completeness implies that C will be the same, so the subsequent extensions will be almost the same. A type of ordering on the defaults can easily be represented with this approach, which both increases the expressiveness of the default logic, and cuts down the number of extensions. Let be a pre-order (i.e., a reexive and transitive relation) on. Let C = f : is -consistent and respects g, where respects i for all i j 2, such that i j, [j 2 implies i 2 ]. Extensions can be dened as before. 6 If is a total pre-order, then there is always a unique extension. This system can then be seen to generalise the non-monotonic inference relations generated in section 4. Applications of default probability W will contain the gambles of which the agent is condent. Less reliable gambles are represented using default rules with A i = B i =. For example, suppose one wanted to combine the probabilistic judgements of a number (n) of experts, where we elicit from expert i (for each i =1... n) a set of gambles C i that they nd acceptable. This would give rise to a set D 5 In particular, it has a default proof theory, the sceptical inference relation is cumulative, it is semi-monotonic and any default theory has an extension for details and motivation see [15,16]. 6 Semi-monotonicity now does not usually hold, but Cumulativity does and it is still the case that every default theory has an extension. Knowledge Representation 389 N. Wilson and S. Moral

5 of default rules f : =fc ig : i =1... ng. In this way, the judgements of an expert are viewed as being of the same degree of reliability, and the judgements of dierent experts as being of incomparable degrees of reliability. If we had extra information about the relative reliabilities of the dierent experts (or of the dierent gambles that a single expert nds acceptable) then that could be incorporated in. Default inference rules can be represented by default rules with B i =. These are useful for default structural judgements, such as independence assumptions. A single independence assumption requires a schema of inference rules it seems natural to put each of these rules at an equivalent position in the pre-order (i j for each pair of rules i j in the schema) so that if one of these inference rules is rebutted, they all are. Rules with B i 6= might be used to express default statements such as `assume Pr(a) 0:6 unless we nd that Pr(c) < 0:1', using the default rule : fc ; 0:1g=fa ; 0:6g. 6 CONCLUSIONS AND DISCUSSION We have dened a very simple, but powerful, logic of probability. It would be interesting to explore connections with other, more complex, logics of probability such as those in [17,18,19,20], and to look at ways in which this logic could be made more expressive. One way is to allow to be innite, and many of the properties do still follow from results in [5]. It has been shown that theories of belief revision and nonmonotonic reasoning can be extended easily to this logic of probability statements. We have not, however, used any of the special structure of this logic. For example, there are natural metrics that can be put on the set of probability functions, and these might be used to help generate grades in a graded set of gambles. Alternatively, grades for gambles might be calculated from a conditional convex set of probabilities, as in [21], where each probability function is assigned a degree of possibility. Most importantly, for any of these systems to be of practical use, tractable subsystems must be identied for example, we need to look for natural and tractable types of default assumptions, and types of graded gambles that lead to ecient methods of probabilistic belief revision. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The rst author is supported by a SERC postdoctoral fellowship. This work was also partially supported by ESPRIT II basic research action 3085, DRUMS II. We are also grateful for the use of the computing facilities of the school of CMS, Oxford Brookes University. REFERENCES [1] G. Boole, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on which are founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities, Macmillan, London, Reprinted in 1958 by Dover. [2] I. J. Good, The Measure of a Non-Measurable Set, Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (edited by Ernest Nagel, Patrick, and Alfred Tarski), Stanford Univ. Press, 319{ 329, [3] J. R. Quinlan, INFERNO: A Cautious Approach to Uncertain Inference, The Computer Journal 26: , [4] N. J. Nilsson, Probabilistic Logic. Articial Intelligence 28, No. 1: 71{87, [5] P. Walley, Statistical Reasoning with Imprecise Probabilities, Chapman and Hall, London, [6] C. A. B. Smith, Consistency in statistical inference and decision, Journal Royal Statistical Society, ser. B 23:1{37, [7] P. Williams, Indeterminate Probabilities, in: M. Przelecki, K. Szaniawski and R. Wojcicki, eds. Formal Methods in the Methodology of Empirical Sciences, Reidel, Dordrecht, 229{ 246, [8] S. Amarger, D. Dubois and H. Prade, Constraint Propagation with Imprecise Conditional Probabilities, in Proc. 7th Conference on Uncertainty in Articial Intelligence, B. D'Ambrosio, P. Smets and P. Bonissone (eds.), Morgan Kaufmann, 26-34, [9] H. Thone, U. Gunter and W. Kiebling, Towards Precision of Probabilistic Bounds Propagation, in Proc. 8th Conference on Uncertainty in Articial Intelligence, D. Dubois, M. P. Wellman, B. D'Ambrosio, and P. Smets (eds.), Morgan Kaufmann, 315{322, [10] P. Gardenfors, and N.-E. Sahlin, Unreliable Probabilities, Risk Taking, and Decision Making, in P. Gardenfors, P., and N.-E. Sahlin, (eds.) Decision, Probability and Utility: Selected Readings, Cambridge University Press, [11] P. Gardenfors, Knowledge in Flux Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass, [12] D. Makinson, and P. Gardenfors, Relations between the Logic of Theory Change and Nonmonotonic Logic, in G. Brewka and H. Freitag (eds.), Arbeitspapiere der GMD no. 443: Proceedings of the Workshop on Nonmonotonic Reasoning, 7{ 27, Also in A. Fuhrmann and M. Morreau (eds.) The Logic of Theory Change, Berlin: Springer Verlag, Lecture Notes in Articial Intelligence no. 465, 185{205. [13] W. Spohn, Ordinal conditional functions: a dynamic theory of epistemic states, in: Causation in Decision, Belief Change and Statistics (W. Harper, B. Skyrms, eds.), 105{134, [14] R. Reiter, A Logic for Default Reasoning, Articial Intelligence 13 (1, 2), 81{132, [15] N. Wilson, Some Theoretical Aspects of the Dempster-Shafer Theory, PhD thesis, Oxford Polytechnic, May [16] N. Wilson, Default Logic and Dempster Shafer, in M. Clarke, R. Kruse and S. Moral (eds.), Proceedings of ECSQARU'93, Granada, November 93, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 372{379, [17] D. Scott and P. Krauss, Assigning Probabilities to Logical Formulas, in Aspects of inductive logic, J. Hintikka and P. Suppes (eds.), North Holland, Amsterdam, 219{264, [18] F. Bacchus, Representing and Reasoning with Probabilistic Knowledge, MIT-Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, [19] J. Y. Halpern, An Analysis of First-Order Logics of Probability, in Proceedings of the International Joint Conference on Articial Intelligence (IJCAI), 1375{1381, [20] J. B. Paris and A. Vencovska, A Proof Theory for Probabilistic Uncertain Reasoning, submitted for publication, July [21] J. E. Cano, S. Moral and J. F. Verdegay-Lopez, Combination of Upper and Lower Probabilities, Proc. 7th Conference on Uncertainty in Articial Intelligence, B. D'Ambrosio, P. Smets and P. Bonissone (eds.), Morgan Kaufmann, 61{68, Knowledge Representation 390 N. Wilson and S. Moral

Belief revision: A vade-mecum

Belief revision: A vade-mecum Belief revision: A vade-mecum Peter Gärdenfors Lund University Cognitive Science, Kungshuset, Lundagård, S 223 50 LUND, Sweden Abstract. This paper contains a brief survey of the area of belief revision

More information

Independence Concepts for Convex Sets of Probabilities. Luis M. De Campos and Serafn Moral. Departamento de Ciencias de la Computacion e I.A.

Independence Concepts for Convex Sets of Probabilities. Luis M. De Campos and Serafn Moral. Departamento de Ciencias de la Computacion e I.A. Independence Concepts for Convex Sets of Probabilities Luis M. De Campos and Serafn Moral Departamento de Ciencias de la Computacion e I.A. Universidad de Granada, 18071 - Granada - Spain e-mails: lci@robinson.ugr.es,smc@robinson.ugr

More information

Default Reasoning and Belief Revision: A Syntax-Independent Approach. (Extended Abstract) Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Default Reasoning and Belief Revision: A Syntax-Independent Approach. (Extended Abstract) Department of Computer Science and Engineering Default Reasoning and Belief Revision: A Syntax-Independent Approach (Extended Abstract) Dongmo Zhang 1;2, Zhaohui Zhu 1 and Shifu Chen 2 1 Department of Computer Science and Engineering Nanjing University

More information

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Soft Computing manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Leen Gilbert, Gert de Cooman 1, Etienne E. Kerre 2 1 Universiteit Gent,

More information

NON-MONOTONIC FUZZY REASONING J.L. CASTRO, E. TRILLAS, J.M. ZURITA. Technical Report #DECSAI-951

NON-MONOTONIC FUZZY REASONING J.L. CASTRO, E. TRILLAS, J.M. ZURITA. Technical Report #DECSAI-951 NON-MONOTONIC FUZZY REASONING J.L. CASTRO, E. TRILLAS, J.M. ZURITA Technical Report #DECSAI-951 NOVEMBER, 1995 Non-Monotonic Fuzzy Reasoning J.L Castro, E. Trillas, J.M. Zurita Depto. Ciencias de la Computacion

More information

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Leen Gilbert Gert de Cooman Etienne E. Kerre October 12, 2000 Abstract Probability assessments of events are often linguistic in nature.

More information

Imprecise Probability

Imprecise Probability Imprecise Probability Alexander Karlsson University of Skövde School of Humanities and Informatics alexander.karlsson@his.se 6th October 2006 0 D W 0 L 0 Introduction The term imprecise probability refers

More information

A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions

A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions Enrique Miranda Abstract This paper presents a summary of Peter Walley s theory of coherent lower previsions. We introduce three representations of coherent

More information

Comparing normative argumentation to other probabilistic systems. Simon Parsons. Mile End Road. London E1 4NS.

Comparing normative argumentation to other probabilistic systems. Simon Parsons. Mile End Road. London E1 4NS. Comparing normative argumentation to other probabilistic systems Simon Parsons Department of Electronic Engineering Queen Mary and Westeld College Mile End Road London E1 4NS S.Parsons@qmw.ac.uk Abstract

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016 SKLAR S THEOREM IN AN IMPRECISE SETTING IGNACIO MONTES, ENRIQUE MIRANDA, RENATO PELESSONI, AND PAOLO VICIG arxiv:1601.02121v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016 Abstract. Sklar s theorem is an important tool that connects

More information

PROBABILISTIC LOGIC. J. Webster (ed.), Wiley Encyclopedia of Electrical and Electronics Engineering Copyright c 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.

PROBABILISTIC LOGIC. J. Webster (ed.), Wiley Encyclopedia of Electrical and Electronics Engineering Copyright c 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. J. Webster (ed.), Wiley Encyclopedia of Electrical and Electronics Engineering Copyright c 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. PROBABILISTIC LOGIC A deductive argument is a claim of the form: If P 1, P 2,...,andP

More information

A Preference Semantics. for Ground Nonmonotonic Modal Logics. logics, a family of nonmonotonic modal logics obtained by means of a

A Preference Semantics. for Ground Nonmonotonic Modal Logics. logics, a family of nonmonotonic modal logics obtained by means of a A Preference Semantics for Ground Nonmonotonic Modal Logics Daniele Nardi and Riccardo Rosati Dipartimento di Informatica e Sistemistica, Universita di Roma \La Sapienza", Via Salaria 113, I-00198 Roma,

More information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Ignacio Montes, Enrique Miranda, Susana Montes University of Oviedo, Dep. of Statistics and Operations Research. Abstract Stochastic dominance, which is

More information

Maximal Introspection of Agents

Maximal Introspection of Agents Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 70 No. 5 (2002) URL: http://www.elsevier.nl/locate/entcs/volume70.html 16 pages Maximal Introspection of Agents Thomas 1 Informatics and Mathematical Modelling

More information

Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting

Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting Ignacio Montes a,, Enrique Miranda a, Renato Pelessoni b, Paolo Vicig b a University of Oviedo (Spain), Dept. of Statistics and O.R. b University of Trieste (Italy),

More information

2 C. A. Gunter ackground asic Domain Theory. A poset is a set D together with a binary relation v which is reexive, transitive and anti-symmetric. A s

2 C. A. Gunter ackground asic Domain Theory. A poset is a set D together with a binary relation v which is reexive, transitive and anti-symmetric. A s 1 THE LARGEST FIRST-ORDER-AXIOMATIZALE CARTESIAN CLOSED CATEGORY OF DOMAINS 1 June 1986 Carl A. Gunter Cambridge University Computer Laboratory, Cambridge C2 3QG, England Introduction The inspiration for

More information

Laboratoire d'informatique Fondamentale de Lille

Laboratoire d'informatique Fondamentale de Lille Laboratoire d'informatique Fondamentale de Lille Publication IT { 314 Operators with Memory for Iterated Revision Sebastien Konieczny mai 1998 c L.I.F.L. { U.S.T.L. LABORATOIRE D'INFORMATIQUE FONDAMENTALE

More information

Computing the acceptability semantics. London SW7 2BZ, UK, Nicosia P.O. Box 537, Cyprus,

Computing the acceptability semantics. London SW7 2BZ, UK, Nicosia P.O. Box 537, Cyprus, Computing the acceptability semantics Francesca Toni 1 and Antonios C. Kakas 2 1 Department of Computing, Imperial College, 180 Queen's Gate, London SW7 2BZ, UK, ft@doc.ic.ac.uk 2 Department of Computer

More information

Independence in Generalized Interval Probability. Yan Wang

Independence in Generalized Interval Probability. Yan Wang Independence in Generalized Interval Probability Yan Wang Woodruff School of Mechanical Engineering, Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA 30332-0405; PH (404)894-4714; FAX (404)894-9342; email:

More information

This second-order avor of default logic makes it especially useful in knowledge representation. An important question is, then, to characterize those

This second-order avor of default logic makes it especially useful in knowledge representation. An important question is, then, to characterize those Representation Theory for Default Logic V. Wiktor Marek 1 Jan Treur 2 and Miros law Truszczynski 3 Keywords: default logic, extensions, normal default logic, representability Abstract Default logic can

More information

HELP US REMOVE OUTDATED BELIEFS?

HELP US REMOVE OUTDATED BELIEFS? CAN INFORMATION THEORY HELP US REMOVE OUTDATED BELIEFS? Erik J. Olsson Lund University Cognitive Science Kungshuset, Lundagård S-222 22 Lund, Sweden E-mail Erik.Olsson@filosofi.uu.se Abstract: It is argued

More information

Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances

Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances Thomas Weiler and Ulrich Bodenhofer Software Competence Center Hagenberg A-4232 Hagenberg, Austria e-mail: {thomas.weiler,ulrich.bodenhofer}@scch.at

More information

An Egalitarist Fusion of Incommensurable Ranked Belief Bases under Constraints

An Egalitarist Fusion of Incommensurable Ranked Belief Bases under Constraints An Egalitarist Fusion of Incommensurable Ranked Belief Bases under Constraints Salem Benferhat and Sylvain Lagrue and Julien Rossit CRIL - Université d Artois Faculté des Sciences Jean Perrin Rue Jean

More information

Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication

Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication Sanjay Modgil Department of Informatics, King s College London Outline Logic and Argumentation - Dung s Theory of Argumentation - The Added

More information

Basic Probabilistic Reasoning SEG

Basic Probabilistic Reasoning SEG Basic Probabilistic Reasoning SEG 7450 1 Introduction Reasoning under uncertainty using probability theory Dealing with uncertainty is one of the main advantages of an expert system over a simple decision

More information

A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models

A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models and their behavioural interpretation Gert de Cooman gert.decooman@ugent.be SYSTeMS research group, Ghent University A gentle introduction to imprecise

More information

Evidence with Uncertain Likelihoods

Evidence with Uncertain Likelihoods Evidence with Uncertain Likelihoods Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853 USA halpern@cs.cornell.edu Riccardo Pucella Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853 USA riccardo@cs.cornell.edu Abstract

More information

Argumentation and rules with exceptions

Argumentation and rules with exceptions Argumentation and rules with exceptions Bart VERHEIJ Artificial Intelligence, University of Groningen Abstract. Models of argumentation often take a given set of rules or conditionals as a starting point.

More information

Encoding formulas with partially constrained weights in a possibilistic-like many-sorted propositional logic

Encoding formulas with partially constrained weights in a possibilistic-like many-sorted propositional logic Encoding formulas with partially constrained weights in a possibilistic-like many-sorted propositional logic Salem Benferhat CRIL-CNRS, Université d Artois rue Jean Souvraz 62307 Lens Cedex France benferhat@criluniv-artoisfr

More information

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm Franz Huber Department of Philosophy University of Toronto franz.huber@utoronto.ca http://huber.blogs.chass.utoronto.ca/ July 7, 2014; final

More information

An Order of Magnitude Calculus

An Order of Magnitude Calculus 548 An Order of Magnitude Calculus Nic Wilson Department of Computer Science Queen Mary and Westfield College Mile End Rd., London El 4NS, UK nic@dcs.qmw.ac.uk Abstract This paper develops a simple calculus

More information

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University Computer Science Department Ithaca, NY 14853 halpern@cs.cornell.edu http://www.cs.cornell.edu/home/halpern August 15, 2018

More information

ESSENCE 2014: Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication

ESSENCE 2014: Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication ESSENCE 2014: Argumentation-Based Models of Agent Reasoning and Communication Sanjay Modgil Department of Informatics, King s College London Outline Logic, Argumentation and Reasoning - Dung s Theory of

More information

Imprecise Bernoulli processes

Imprecise Bernoulli processes Imprecise Bernoulli processes Jasper De Bock and Gert de Cooman Ghent University, SYSTeMS Research Group Technologiepark Zwijnaarde 914, 9052 Zwijnaarde, Belgium. {jasper.debock,gert.decooman}@ugent.be

More information

On iterated revision in the AGM framework

On iterated revision in the AGM framework On iterated revision in the AGM framework Andreas Herzig, Sébastien Konieczny, Laurent Perrussel Institut de Recherche en Informatique de Toulouse 118 route de Narbonne - 31062 Toulouse - France {herzig,konieczny,perrussel}@irit.fr

More information

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm Franz Huber Abstract: Weisberg (2009) introduces a phenomenon he terms perceptual undermining He argues that it poses a problem for Jeffrey

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato June 23, 2015 This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a more direct connection

More information

Halpern situations incomparable as far as normality or likelihood goes. For example, one situation may be better in one dimension but worse in another

Halpern situations incomparable as far as normality or likelihood goes. For example, one situation may be better in one dimension but worse in another Journal of Articial Intelligence Research 7 (1997) 1{24 Submitted 2/97; published 7/97 Dening Relative Likelihood in Partially-Ordered Preferential Structures Joseph Y. Halpern Cornell University, Computer

More information

Revising Nonmonotonic Theories: The Case of Defeasible Logic

Revising Nonmonotonic Theories: The Case of Defeasible Logic Revising Nonmonotonic Theories: The Case of Defeasible Logic D. Billington, G. Antoniou, G. Governatori, and M. Maher School of Computing and Information Technology Griffith University, QLD 4111, Australia

More information

Splitting a Default Theory. Hudson Turner. University of Texas at Austin.

Splitting a Default Theory. Hudson Turner. University of Texas at Austin. Splitting a Default Theory Hudson Turner Department of Computer Sciences University of Texas at Austin Austin, TX 7872-88, USA hudson@cs.utexas.edu Abstract This paper presents mathematical results that

More information

Conflict-Based Belief Revision Operators in Possibilistic Logic

Conflict-Based Belief Revision Operators in Possibilistic Logic Conflict-Based Belief Revision Operators in Possibilistic Logic Author Qi, Guilin, Wang, Kewen Published 2012 Conference Title Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence

More information

Tutorial: Nonmonotonic Logic (Day 2)

Tutorial: Nonmonotonic Logic (Day 2) Tutorial: Nonmonotonic Logic (Day 2) Christian Straßer Institute for Philosophy II, Ruhr-University Bochum Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Ghent University http://homepage.ruhr-uni-bochum.de/defeasible-reasoning/index.html

More information

Outline. 1 Plausible Reasoning. 2 Preferential / Selection Semantics (KLM, Shoham) 3 Bibliography

Outline. 1 Plausible Reasoning. 2 Preferential / Selection Semantics (KLM, Shoham) 3 Bibliography Outline Tutorial: Nonmonotonic Logic (Day 2) 1 Plausible Reasoning Christian Straßer Institute for Philosophy II, Ruhr-University Bochum Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Ghent University http://homepage.ruhr-uni-bochum.de/defeasible-reasoning/index.html

More information

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University hcosta@andrew.cmu.edu Logical preliminaries Let L 0 be a language containing a complete set of Boolean connectives, including

More information

Argumentative Characterisations of Non-monotonic Inference in Preferred Subtheories: Stable Equals Preferred

Argumentative Characterisations of Non-monotonic Inference in Preferred Subtheories: Stable Equals Preferred Argumentative Characterisations of Non-monotonic Inference in Preferred Subtheories: Stable Equals Preferred Sanjay Modgil November 17, 2017 Abstract A number of argumentation formalisms provide dialectical

More information

A Preference Logic With Four Kinds of Preferences

A Preference Logic With Four Kinds of Preferences A Preference Logic With Four Kinds of Preferences Zhang Zhizheng and Xing Hancheng School of Computer Science and Engineering, Southeast University No.2 Sipailou, Nanjing, China {seu_zzz; xhc}@seu.edu.cn

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

your eyes is more reliable than the information about the position of the object coming from your ears. But even reliable sources such as domain exper

your eyes is more reliable than the information about the position of the object coming from your ears. But even reliable sources such as domain exper A logic for reasoning with inconsistent knowledge Nico Roos Research Institute for Knowledge Systems Tongersestraat 6 P. O. Box 463, 6200 AL Maastricht The Netherlands This paper has been published in

More information

Ordinal and Probabilistic Representations of Acceptance

Ordinal and Probabilistic Representations of Acceptance Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research 22 (2004) 23-56 Submitted 05/03; published 07/04 Ordinal and Probabilistic Representations of Acceptance Didier Dubois Helene Fargier Henri Prade Institut de

More information

The Assumptions Behind Dempster's Rule

The Assumptions Behind Dempster's Rule The Assumptions Behind Dempster's Rule 527 The Assumptions Behind Dempster's Rule Nic Wilson Department of Computer Science Queen Mary and Westfield College Mile End Rd., London El 4NS, UK Abstract This

More information

1) Totality of agents is (partially) ordered, with the intended meaning that t 1 v t 2 intuitively means that \Perception of the agent A t2 is sharper

1) Totality of agents is (partially) ordered, with the intended meaning that t 1 v t 2 intuitively means that \Perception of the agent A t2 is sharper On reaching consensus by groups of intelligent agents Helena Rasiowa and Wiktor Marek y Abstract We study the problem of reaching the consensus by a group of fully communicating, intelligent agents. Firstly,

More information

INDEPENDENT NATURAL EXTENSION

INDEPENDENT NATURAL EXTENSION INDEPENDENT NATURAL EXTENSION GERT DE COOMAN, ENRIQUE MIRANDA, AND MARCO ZAFFALON ABSTRACT. There is no unique extension of the standard notion of probabilistic independence to the case where probabilities

More information

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University hcosta@andrew.cmu.edu Bayesian Epistemology Radical probabilism doesn t insists that probabilities be based on certainties;

More information

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS CAPSTONE MATT LUTHER 1 INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS 2 1. Introduction This paper will summarize many of the ideas from logic and set theory that are

More information

A unified view of some representations of imprecise probabilities

A unified view of some representations of imprecise probabilities A unified view of some representations of imprecise probabilities S. Destercke and D. Dubois Institut de recherche en informatique de Toulouse (IRIT) Université Paul Sabatier, 118 route de Narbonne, 31062

More information

COHERENCE AND PROBABILITY. Rosangela H. Loschi and Sergio Wechsler. Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais e Universidade de S~ao Paulo ABSTRACT

COHERENCE AND PROBABILITY. Rosangela H. Loschi and Sergio Wechsler. Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais e Universidade de S~ao Paulo ABSTRACT COHERENCE AND PROBABILITY Rosangela H. Loschi and Sergio Wechsler Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais e Universidade de S~ao Paulo ABSTRACT A process of construction of subjective probability based on

More information

A Strong Relevant Logic Model of Epistemic Processes in Scientific Discovery

A Strong Relevant Logic Model of Epistemic Processes in Scientific Discovery A Strong Relevant Logic Model of Epistemic Processes in Scientific Discovery (Extended Abstract) Jingde Cheng Department of Computer Science and Communication Engineering Kyushu University, 6-10-1 Hakozaki,

More information

A BEHAVIOURAL MODEL FOR VAGUE PROBABILITY ASSESSMENTS

A BEHAVIOURAL MODEL FOR VAGUE PROBABILITY ASSESSMENTS A BEHAVIOURAL MODEL FOR VAGUE PROBABILITY ASSESSMENTS GERT DE COOMAN ABSTRACT. I present an hierarchical uncertainty model that is able to represent vague probability assessments, and to make inferences

More information

Rough Sets for Uncertainty Reasoning

Rough Sets for Uncertainty Reasoning Rough Sets for Uncertainty Reasoning S.K.M. Wong 1 and C.J. Butz 2 1 Department of Computer Science, University of Regina, Regina, Canada, S4S 0A2, wong@cs.uregina.ca 2 School of Information Technology

More information

Comment on Leitgeb s Stability Theory of Belief

Comment on Leitgeb s Stability Theory of Belief Comment on Leitgeb s Stability Theory of Belief Hanti Lin Kevin T. Kelly Carnegie Mellon University {hantil, kk3n}@andrew.cmu.edu Hannes Leitgeb s stability theory of belief provides three synchronic constraints

More information

Using qualitative uncertainty in protein

Using qualitative uncertainty in protein Using qualitative uncertainty in protein topology prediction Simon Parsons 1 Advanced Computation Laboratory, Imperial Cancer Research Fund, P.O. Box 123, Lincoln's Inn Fields, London WC2A 3PX, United

More information

Restricted truth predicates in first-order logic

Restricted truth predicates in first-order logic Restricted truth predicates in first-order logic Thomas Bolander 1 Introduction It is well-known that there exist consistent first-order theories that become inconsistent when we add Tarski s schema T.

More information

U-Sets as a probabilistic set theory

U-Sets as a probabilistic set theory U-Sets as a probabilistic set theory Claudio Sossai ISIB-CNR, Corso Stati Uniti 4, 35127 Padova, Italy sossai@isib.cnr.it Technical Report 05/03 ISIB-CNR, October 2005 Abstract A topos of presheaves can

More information

On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory

On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory 6th International Symposium on Imprecise Probability: Theories and Applications, Durham, United Kingdom, 2009 On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory Jiřina Vejnarová Institute of Information Theory

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

var D (B) = var(b? E D (B)) = var(b)? cov(b; D)(var(D))?1 cov(d; B) (2) Stone [14], and Hartigan [9] are among the rst to discuss the role of such ass

var D (B) = var(b? E D (B)) = var(b)? cov(b; D)(var(D))?1 cov(d; B) (2) Stone [14], and Hartigan [9] are among the rst to discuss the role of such ass BAYES LINEAR ANALYSIS [This article appears in the Encyclopaedia of Statistical Sciences, Update volume 3, 1998, Wiley.] The Bayes linear approach is concerned with problems in which we want to combine

More information

Desire-as-belief revisited

Desire-as-belief revisited Desire-as-belief revisited Richard Bradley and Christian List June 30, 2008 1 Introduction On Hume s account of motivation, beliefs and desires are very di erent kinds of propositional attitudes. Beliefs

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Confirmation Theory. Pittsburgh Summer Program 1. Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017

Confirmation Theory. Pittsburgh Summer Program 1. Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017 Confirmation Theory Pittsburgh Summer Program 1 Center for the Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh July 7, 2017 1 Confirmation Disconfirmation 1. Sometimes, a piece of evidence, E, gives reason

More information

Hempel s Logic of Confirmation

Hempel s Logic of Confirmation Hempel s Logic of Confirmation Franz Huber, California Institute of Technology May 21, 2007 Contents 1 Hempel s Conditions of Adequacy 3 2 Carnap s Analysis of Hempel s Conditions 4 3 Conflicting Concepts

More information

Finite information logic

Finite information logic Finite information logic Rohit Parikh and Jouko Väänänen April 5, 2002 Work in progress. Please do not circulate! Partial information logic is a generalization of both rst order logic and Hintikka-Sandu

More information

Nested Epistemic Logic Programs

Nested Epistemic Logic Programs Nested Epistemic Logic Programs Kewen Wang 1 and Yan Zhang 2 1 Griffith University, Australia k.wang@griffith.edu.au 2 University of Western Sydney yan@cit.uws.edu.au Abstract. Nested logic programs and

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Executable Temporal Logic for Non-monotonic Reasoning

Executable Temporal Logic for Non-monotonic Reasoning J. Symbolic Computation (1996) 22, 615 625 Executable Temporal Logic for Non-monotonic Reasoning JOERI ENGELFRIET AND JAN TREUR Free University Amsterdam, Department of Mathematics and Computer Science

More information

An assumption-based framework for. Programming Systems Institute, Russian Academy of Sciences

An assumption-based framework for. Programming Systems Institute, Russian Academy of Sciences An assumption-based framework for non-monotonic reasoning 1 Andrei Bondarenko 2 Programming Systems Institute, Russian Academy of Sciences Pereslavle-Zalessky, Russia andrei@troyka.msk.su Francesca Toni,

More information

A Unifying Semantics for Belief Change

A Unifying Semantics for Belief Change A Unifying Semantics for Belief Change C0300 Abstract. Many belief change formalisms employ plausibility orderings over the set of possible worlds to determine how the beliefs of an agent ought to be modified

More information

Representing Beliefs in the Fluent Calculus

Representing Beliefs in the Fluent Calculus Representing Beliefs in the Fluent Calculus Yi Jin and Michael Thielscher 1 Abstract. Action formalisms like the uent calculus have been developed to endow logic-based agents with the abilities to reason

More information

Coherent Predictive Inference under Exchangeability with Imprecise Probabilities (Extended Abstract) *

Coherent Predictive Inference under Exchangeability with Imprecise Probabilities (Extended Abstract) * Coherent Predictive Inference under Exchangeability with Imprecise Probabilities (Extended Abstract) * Gert de Cooman *, Jasper De Bock * and Márcio Alves Diniz * IDLab, Ghent University, Belgium Department

More information

Reasoning with Inconsistent and Uncertain Ontologies

Reasoning with Inconsistent and Uncertain Ontologies Reasoning with Inconsistent and Uncertain Ontologies Guilin Qi Southeast University China gqi@seu.edu.cn Reasoning Web 2012 September 05, 2012 Outline Probabilistic logic vs possibilistic logic Probabilistic

More information

09 Modal Logic II. CS 3234: Logic and Formal Systems. October 14, Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor

09 Modal Logic II. CS 3234: Logic and Formal Systems. October 14, Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor Martin Henz and Aquinas Hobor October 14, 2010 Generated on Thursday 14 th October, 2010, 11:40 1 Review of Modal Logic 2 3 4 Motivation Syntax and Semantics Valid Formulas wrt Modalities Correspondence

More information

Reasoning with Uncertainty

Reasoning with Uncertainty Reasoning with Uncertainty Representing Uncertainty Manfred Huber 2005 1 Reasoning with Uncertainty The goal of reasoning is usually to: Determine the state of the world Determine what actions to take

More information

ALDO FRANCO DRAGONI AND PAOLO GIORGINI REVISING BELIEFS RECEIVED FROM MULTIPLE SOURCES

ALDO FRANCO DRAGONI AND PAOLO GIORGINI REVISING BELIEFS RECEIVED FROM MULTIPLE SOURCES REVISING BELIEFS RECEIVED FROM MULTIPLE SOURCES REVISING BELIEFS RECEIVED FROM MULTIPLE SOURCES ABSTRACT: Since the seminal, philosophical and inuential works of Alchourron, Gardenfors and Makinson, ideas

More information

Modus Tollens Probabilized

Modus Tollens Probabilized Modus Tollens Probabilized CARL G. WAGNER University of Tennessee, U. S. A. Abstract We establish a probabilized version of modus tollens, deriving from p(e H) = a and p(ē) = b the best possible bounds

More information

Merging Stratified Knowledge Bases under Constraints

Merging Stratified Knowledge Bases under Constraints Merging Stratified Knowledge Bases under Constraints Guilin Qi, Weiru Liu, David A. Bell School of Electronics, Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Queen s University Belfast Belfast, BT7 1NN,

More information

2 1. INTRODUCTION We study algebraic foundations of semantics of nonmonotonic knowledge representation formalisms. The algebraic framework we use is t

2 1. INTRODUCTION We study algebraic foundations of semantics of nonmonotonic knowledge representation formalisms. The algebraic framework we use is t Chapter 1 APPROXIMATIONS, STABLE OPERATORS, WELL-FOUNDED FIXPOINTS AND APPLICATIONS IN NONMONOTONIC REASONING Marc Denecker Department of Computer Science, K.U.Leuven Celestijnenlaan 200A, B-3001 Heverlee,

More information

On 3-valued paraconsistent Logic Programming

On 3-valued paraconsistent Logic Programming Marcelo E. Coniglio Kleidson E. Oliveira Institute of Philosophy and Human Sciences and Centre For Logic, Epistemology and the History of Science, UNICAMP, Brazil Support: FAPESP Syntax Meets Semantics

More information

Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models

Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models Mark Strong 1, Hazel Pilgrim 1, Jeremy Oakley 2, Jim Chilcott 1 December 2009 1. School of Health and Related Research, University of Sheffield,

More information

The Limitation of Bayesianism

The Limitation of Bayesianism The Limitation of Bayesianism Pei Wang Department of Computer and Information Sciences Temple University, Philadelphia, PA 19122 pei.wang@temple.edu Abstract In the current discussion about the capacity

More information

On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory

On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory 131 On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory Jiřina Vejnarová Institute of Information Theory and Automation of the ASCR & University of Economics, Prague vejnar@utia.cas.cz

More information

Independence for Full Conditional Measures, Graphoids and Bayesian Networks

Independence for Full Conditional Measures, Graphoids and Bayesian Networks Independence for Full Conditional Measures, Graphoids and Bayesian Networks Fabio G. Cozman Universidade de Sao Paulo Teddy Seidenfeld Carnegie Mellon University February 28, 2007 Abstract This paper examines

More information

Epistemic independence for imprecise probabilities

Epistemic independence for imprecise probabilities International Journal of Approximate Reasoning 24 (2000) 235±250 www.elsevier.com/locate/ijar Epistemic independence for imprecise probabilities Paolo Vicig Dipartimento di Matematica Applicata ``B. de

More information

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos armandobcm@yahoo.com February 5, 2014 Abstract This note is for personal use. It

More information

Inference for Stochastic Processes

Inference for Stochastic Processes Inference for Stochastic Processes Robert L. Wolpert Revised: June 19, 005 Introduction A stochastic process is a family {X t } of real-valued random variables, all defined on the same probability space

More information

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization

In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization In Defense of Jeffrey Conditionalization Franz Huber Department of Philosophy University of Toronto Please do not cite! December 31, 2013 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Weisberg s Paradox 3 3 Jeffrey Conditionalization

More information

A probability logic for reasoning about quantum observations

A probability logic for reasoning about quantum observations A probability logic for reasoning about quantum observations Angelina Ilic Stepic, Zoran Ognjanovic LAP 2017, Dubrovnik Outline 1 Quantum mechanics -basic concepts 2 Existing logical approaches 3 Logic

More information

Bayesian Reasoning. Adapted from slides by Tim Finin and Marie desjardins.

Bayesian Reasoning. Adapted from slides by Tim Finin and Marie desjardins. Bayesian Reasoning Adapted from slides by Tim Finin and Marie desjardins. 1 Outline Probability theory Bayesian inference From the joint distribution Using independence/factoring From sources of evidence

More information

Conditional Logic and Belief Revision

Conditional Logic and Belief Revision Conditional Logic and Belief Revision Ginger Schultheis (vks@mit.edu) and David Boylan (dboylan@mit.edu) January 2017 History The formal study of belief revision grew out out of two research traditions:

More information

Three contrasts between two senses of coherence

Three contrasts between two senses of coherence Three contrasts between two senses of coherence Teddy Seidenfeld Joint work with M.J.Schervish and J.B.Kadane Statistics, CMU Call an agent s choices coherent when they respect simple dominance relative

More information

Technical R e p o r t. Merging in the Horn Fragment DBAI-TR Adrian Haret, Stefan Rümmele, Stefan Woltran. Artificial Intelligence

Technical R e p o r t. Merging in the Horn Fragment DBAI-TR Adrian Haret, Stefan Rümmele, Stefan Woltran. Artificial Intelligence Technical R e p o r t Institut für Informationssysteme Abteilung Datenbanken und Artificial Intelligence Merging in the Horn Fragment DBAI-TR-2015-91 Adrian Haret, Stefan Rümmele, Stefan Woltran Institut

More information