The greatest unhappiness of the least number

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The greatest unhappiness of the least number"

Transcription

1 The greatest unhappiness of the least number Walter Bossert Centre Interuniversitaire de Recherche en Economie Quantitative (CIREQ) P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada and Kotaro Suzumura School of Political Science and Economics Waseda University Nishi-Waseda Shinjuku-ku, Tokyo Japan This version: January 27, 2016 Abstract. We propose an alternative articulation of the Benthamite greatest-happinessof-the-greatest-number principle. With ordinally measurable and interpersonally noncomparable utilities, the rule chooses those feasible alternatives that maximize the number of individuals who end up with their greatest element. This rule is tantamount to the plurality rule. Furthermore, in the spirit of Rawls s maximin principle, we propose the greatest-unhappiness-of-the-least-number principle. In analogy to the greatest-happiness principle, the least-unhappiness principle is formally equivalent to the anti-plurality rule. Our main result is a characterization of the least-unhappiness principle. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Nos.: D71, D72. We thank Thierry Marchant and several seminar audiences for their comments and suggestions. Financial support from a Grant-in-Aid for Specially Promoted Research from the Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology of Japan for the Project on Economic Analysis of Intergenerational Issues (grant number ), the Fonds de Recherche sur la Société et la Culture of Québec, and the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada is gratefully acknowledged.

2 1 Introduction In this paper, we consider an ordinal and interpersonally non-comparable interpretation of Bentham s well-known principle that It is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and wrong, as formulated in the preface to the first edition of Bentham (1776); the phrase can be found in Bowring (1843, p. 227). In a setting that uses ordinal and interpersonally non-comparable information on individual well-being only, this principle can be expressed in terms of a collective choice correspondence that is equivalent to the plurality voting rule. According to the standard understanding, the Benthamite decision rule, which seeks to attain the greatest happiness of the greatest number, is construed to maximize the social sum-total of individual utilities. This decision rule is clearly based on the informational basis of cardinal and interpersonally unit-comparable individual utilities. In the wake of the ordinalist revolution in the 1930s, which was initiated in the positive branch of economics by Hicks (1939a/1946) and Samuelson (1938a,b, 1947/1983) and adopted in normative economics by Robbins (1932/1935), Hicks (1939b, 1940), Kaldor (1939) and Samuelson (1950), the conventional informational basis of the Benthamite utilitarianism received harsh criticism. This criticism resulted in the arrival of new welfare economics that is based on ordinal and interpersonally non-comparable individual utilities, initiated by Bergson (1938) and Samuelson (1947/1983, 1981). We propose an alternative articulation of the Benthamite decision rule, that is, the greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number rule, which is based on ordinal and interpersonally non-comparable utilities. For each feasible social alternative, say x, we count the number g(x) of individuals who rank x at the top of their preference rankings over all feasible social alternatives. The ordinalist Benthamite decision rule chooses those feasible alternatives x such that g(x) g(y) holds for all feasible alternatives y. It is true that the ordinalist Benthamite decision rule, thus defined, is tantamount to the well-known plurality voting rule; see, for instance, Richelson (1978), Ching (1996), Yeh (2008) and Sekiguchi (2012). Although the plurality voting rule per se has been discussed extensively in the literature, it has never been recognized as the ordinalist articulation of Bentham s greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number principle. Going one step further, and more in the spirit of the Rawlsian principle of maximin justice (Rawls, 1971), this paper also proposes an alternative social decision rule that may be labeled the greatest-unhappiness-of-the-least-number rule. Just as is the case for the greatest-happiness principle and the plurality rule, the least-unhappiness principle turns out to be formally equivalent to the anti-plurality (or inverse plurality) rule. The new result of this paper is a characterization of the least-unhappiness principle. The anti-plurality rule has been axiomatized in earlier contributions such as Baharad and Nitzan (2005) and Barberà and Dutta (1982) but the characterization presented here is quite different from those that are already available; a more detailed discussion can be found in the section following the statement and proof of our result. To the best of our knowledge, Bentham s greatest-happiness principle and its leastunhappiness counterpart have not been investigated so far in the context of ordinal measurability and interpersonal non-comparability. In contrast, theories of justice based on variants of Bentham s (1789) original formulation of utilitarian principles have been an- 1

3 alyzed quite extensively in the context of cardinal measurability and interpersonal unit comparability; see, for example, Blackorby, Bossert and Donaldson (2002). Likewise, the discussion of Rawls s (1971) notion of maximin justice has been restricted to informational requirements that assume individual utilities to be ordinally measurable and interpersonally level-comparable. 2 Definitions There is a non-empty and finite set of alternatives X and we use X to denote the set of all non-empty subsets of X. The set of potential agents is the set N of positive integers. As is the case for much of the literature on the (anti-)plurality voting rule and similar group-decision mechanisms, we assume that a collective choice correspondence is capable of being applied to different populations of possibly different size; see also Smith (1973) for a variable-electorate approach to voting problems. Thus, the set of possible societies under consideration is the set N of all non-empty and finite subsets of N. For all i N, R i is the set of all reflexive, complete, transitive and antisymmetric relations on X with typical element R i. Likewise, for all N N, R N = i N R i is the set of all profiles of such relations for population N with typical element R N = (R i ) i N. Furthermore, we define R = N N R N. A collective choice correspondence is a mapping f: R X X such that, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, f(r N, S) S. In order to formulate the classical Benthamite greatest-happiness principle and its leastunhappiness counterpart in an ordinal setting without interpersonal comparability, we define, for all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X and for all x S, and g(r N, S, x) = {i N xr i y for all y S} l(r N, S, x) = {i N yr i x for all y S}. Clearly, g(r N, S, x) is the number of individuals for whom x is the greatest element in S according to the profile R N, whereas l(r N, S, x) is the corresponding number of those who have x as their least element. As mentioned earlier, we consider an informational environment in which individual well-being is ordinally measurable and interpersonally non-comparable. In such a setting, the greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number principle f H is defined by letting, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, f H (R N, S) = {x S g(r N, S, x) g(r N, S, y) for all y S}. Analogously, the greatest-unhappiness-of-the-least-number principle can be expressed by means of the collective choice correspondence f U defined by letting, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, f U (R N, S) = {x S l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, y) for all y S}. It is straightforward to verify that f H is the well-known plurality rule and f U is its counterpart the anti-plurality rule, also referred to as the inverse plurality rule. 2

4 We now introduce the axioms that we employ in our characterization of f U. Our first property is the well-known anonymity axiom. It requires that the collective choice correspondence f is impartial, paying no attention to the identities of the individuals. Let Π be the set of all permutations π: N N. For all π Π and for all N N, let N π = {j N i N such that j = π(i)}. Thus, we have R Nπ = ( R π(i) )i N for all π Π, for all N N and for all R N R N. Anonymity. For all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X and for all π Π, f(r Nπ, S) = f(r N, S). Next, we define the property of neutrality, which is similar in spirit to anonymity in that it demands that the alternatives are treated symmetrically by f in the sense that the label we attach to them are irrelevant. Let Σ be the set of all permutations σ: X X. For all i N, for all R i R i and for all σ Σ, define the relation σ i (R i ) by letting σ(x) σ i (R i ) σ(y) xr i y for all x, y X. For all N N and for all R N R N, let σ N (R N ) = (σ i (R i )) i N. Neutrality. For all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X and for all σ Σ, f (σ N (R N ), S) = σ (f(r N, S)). Reinforcement is yet another standard axiom in the context of collective choice correspondences. It imposes a restriction that involves different societies. Suppose that there are two disjoint groups of agents N and N with preference profiles R N and R N. Furthermore, suppose that, for a given feasible set S of alternatives, there are some alternatives that are chosen by both groups. The reinforcement axiom requires that if the two groups are merged, the choice from S for the expanded group coincide with the non-empty intersection that contains the common choices of the original smaller groups. Reinforcement. For all N, N N such that N N =, for all R N R N R N and for all S X, if f(r N, S) f(r N, S), then R N, for all f ((R N, R N ), S) = f(r N, S) f(r N, S). The following axiom ensures that if an agent i s preference ordering R i changes to a preference ordering R i without changing the alternatives that are chosen from a feasible 3

5 set S in the single-agent society composed of individual i, then the choice from S of any society N that contains i is unchanged as well. Individual-equality independence. For all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X, for all i N and for all R i R i, if f(r i, S) = f(r i, S), then f ( (R N\{i}, R i), S ) = f(r N, S). The remaining two properties are very limited in scope because they apply to singleagent societies only. The first of these two requires that, in choice situations involving a single agent and two alternatives, the better of the two alternatives is chosen and the worse alternative is not. Single-agent monotonicity. For all i N, for all R i R i, for all distinct x, y X, if xr i y, then f(r i, {x, y}) = {x}. All of the above axioms are rather un-controversial and are satisfied by a variety of collective choice correspondences. In contrast, our last property is what sets the greatestunhappiness-of-the-least-number principle f U apart from all others. Again, it is silent when considering societies with more than one agent and, thus, is limited in scope. If there is a single agent and there are at least two alternatives, the axiom requires that if an alternative x is added that is preferred to all alternatives in the original (smaller) set S, then this new alternative x should be chosen from S {x} in addition to the alternatives that are chosen from the smaller set S. Clearly, this axiom imposes an additional restriction for example, the greatest-happiness-of-the-greatest-number rule f H fails to satisfy it. Single-agent expansion. For all i N, for all R i R i, for all S X such that S > 1 and for all x X \ S, if xr i y for all y S, then f(r i, S {x}) = f(r i, S) {x}. We conclude this section with a statement of an axiom employed by Ching (1996) in his characterization of the greatest-happiness principle f H. The property demands that if an alternative y in a feasible set S is dominated by another alternative x in S in the sense that all individuals prefer x to y, then the set of chosen alternatives is unchanged if y is removed from S. Unlike the greatest-happiness principle, the least-unhappiness principle f U does not satisfy this axiom. Independence of dominated alternatives. For all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X and for all y S, if there exists x S \ {y} such that xr i y for all i N, then f(r N, S \ {y}) = f(r N, S). 4

6 3 Greatest unhappiness of the least number In order to facilitate a comparison with our result, we first state Ching s (1996) characterization of the plurality rule that is, the greatest-happiness principle f H. Ching s (1996) theorem generalizes a result by Richelson (1978) by dropping one of the axioms in the original characterization. The reason why the additional property a continuity requirement is needed in Richelson s (1978) result is that his proof proceeds by employing a well-known earlier theorem on scoring functions established by Young (1975). Other characterizations of the plurality rule include that of Yeh (2008) and its strengthening by Sekiguchi (2012). The results of Yeh (2008) and Sekiguchi (2012) and that of Ching (1996) are independent. Theorem 1 A collective choice correspondence f satisfies anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement and independence of dominated alternatives if and only if f = f H. Proof. See Ching (1996). We now characterize f U by means of the requisite axioms introduced in the previous section. That the axioms are independent is shown in the appendix. Theorem 2 A collective choice correspondence f satisfies anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, individual-equality independence, single-agent monotonicity and single-agent expansion if and only if f = f U. Proof. If. That f U satisfies anonymity and neutrality is immediate because neither the identities of the individuals nor the labels of the alternatives play any role in the definition of the rule. To establish reinforcement, suppose that N, N N, R N R N, R N R N and S X are such that N N = and f U (R N, S) f U (R N, S). For future reference, note that l ((R N, R N ), S, z) = l(r N, S, z) + l(r N, S, z) (1) for all z S because N N =. Suppose first that x f U (R N, S) f U (R N, S). By definition of f U, we have l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, y) and l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, y) for all y S. Combined with (1), it follows that l ((R N, R N ), S, x) l ((R N, R N ), S, y) for all y S. Using the definition of f U again, we obtain x f U ((R N, R N ), S). Now suppose that x f U ((R N, R N ), S). Thus, for all y S and, using (1), it follows that l ((R N, R N ), S, x) l ((R N, R N ), S, y) l(r N, S, x) + l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, y) + l(r N, S, y) (2) 5

7 for all y S. Let z f U (R N, S) f U (R N, S). Such an alternative z exists because this intersection is non-empty. Thus, l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, y) and l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, y) (3) for all y S. Clearly, (3) is satisfied for the special case in which y = x. Thus, l(r N, S, z) + l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, x) + l(r N, S, x). (4) Analogously, (2) applies when y = z and, thus, Combined with (4), it follows that l(r N, S, x) + l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, z) + l(r N, S, z). l(r N, S, x) + l(r N, S, x) = l(r N, S, z) + l(r N, S, z). (5) If l(r N, S, z) < l(r N, S, x), (5) implies l(r N, S, z) > l(r N, S, x), contradicting (3) with y = x. Analogously, if l(r N, S, z) < l(r N, S, x), (5) implies l(r N, S, z) > l(r N, S, x), again contradicting (3) with y = x. Therefore, l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, y) and l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, y) for all y S, hence x f U (R N, S) and x f U (R N, S) and thus x f U (R N, S) f U (R N, S). Next, we prove that individual-equality independence is satisfied by f U. Let N N, R N R N, S X, i N and R i R i be such that f U (R i, S) = f U (R i, S). Thus, for all x S, x f U ( (R N\{i}, R i), S ) l(r N\{i}, S, x) + l(r i, S, x) l(r N\{i}, S, y) + l(r i, S, y) for all y S l(r N\{i}, S, x) + l(r i, S, x) l(r N\{i}, S, y) + l(r i, S, y) for all y S x f U (R N, S). Single-agent monotonicity follows because, by definition, f U (R i, {x, y}) = {x} whenever i N, R i R i and x, y X with x y and xr i y. Finally, single-agent expansion is satisfied because, by definition, f U (R i, S {x}) = f U (R i, S) {x} for all i N, for all R i R i, for all S X such that S > 1 and for all x X \ S such that xr i y for all y S. Only if. Now suppose that f is a collective choice correspondence that satisfies the axioms. Let N N, R N R N and S X. First, consider the case N = 1 where N = {i} with i N. If S = 1 with S = {x}, we obtain f(r i, {x}) = {x} = f U (R i, {x}) because f(r i, {x}) is non-empty. If S = 2, suppose that S = {x, y} and xr i y. By single-agent monotonicity, it follows that f(r i, S) = f(r i, {x, y}) = {x} = f U (R i, S). 6

8 If S > 2, let S = {x 1,..., x k 1, x k } be such that x 1 R i... R i x k 1 R i x k. By single-agent monotonicity, we obtain f(r i, {x k 1, x k }) = {x k 1 }. By (repeated if necessary) application of single-agent expansion, it follows that f(r i, S) = {x 1,..., x k 1 } = {x S l(r i, S, x) l(r i, S, y) for all y S} = f U (R i, S). This completes the proof in the single-agent case. Now suppose that N > 1. If there exists x S such that, for all i N, there exists y i S \ {x} such that xr i y i, it follows that l(r N, S, x) = 0 and, thus, l(r N, S, x) l(r N, S, y) for all y S. Using the argument employed in the case N = 1, it follows that f(r i, S) = {z S l(r i, S, z) l(r i, S, y) for all y S} = f U (R i, S) for all i N. By assumption, there exists at least one alternative x that is in f(r i, S) for all i N and, thus, it follows that i N f(r i, S). Furthermore, all z S such that, for all i N, there exists y i S \ {z} such that zr i y i are elements of this intersection. By (repeated if necessary) application of reinforcement, f(r N, S) = i N f(r i, S) = i N {z S l(r i, S, z) l(r i, S, y) for all y S} = {z S l(r N, S, z) l(r N, S, y) for all y S} = f U (R N, S). To complete the proof, consider the case in which N > 1 and, for all x S, there exists i N such that yr i x for all y S \ {x} that is, every alternative in S is located at the bottom of at least one individual ranking which, in turn, implies that l(r N, S, x) > 0 for all x S. Furthermore, note that this implies that we must have at least S agents that is, N S. Select a subset N 1 of S individuals from N such that, for each x S, there is exactly one i x N 1 such that yr ix x for all y S \ {x}. Define a profile R 1 N = (R 1 1 i ) i N 1 so that the restriction of this profile to S has the following properties. For all x S, let yri 1 x x for all y S \ {x} and, moreover, let the profile be fully symmetric in the sense that each element of S appears in each position exactly once that is, for each x S and for each rank k {1,..., S }, there exists an individual j x N 1 such that x appears in the k th position in Rj 1 x. By the argument used in the N = 1 case, it follows that f(ri 1, S) = f(r i, S) = f U (R i, S) for all i N 1. By repeated application of individualequality independence, we obtain f(r N 1, S) = f(r 1 N 1, S). (6) Because of the full symmetry in R 1 N 1, anonymity and neutrality together imply that f(r 1 N 1, S) = S 7

9 and, by (6), it follows that f(r N 1, S) = S. If N 1 = N, it follows immediately that f(r N, S) = f(r N 1, S) = S = f U (R N, S) and we are done. If N 1 N, consider the set N \ N 1. If, for all x S, there exists i N \ N 1 such that yr i x for all y S \ {x}, select a subset N 2 of N \ N 1 in the same way N 1 was selected from N, and define a corresponding profile R 2 N = (R 2 2 i ) i N 2 analogously. Again, we obtain f(r N 2, S) = S by applying individual-equality independence, anonymity and neutrality as required. Because N is finite, this process can be repeated until we reach a number K N \ {1} and pairwise disjoint sets N 1,..., N K N such that f(r N 1, S) =... = f(r N K, S) = S and not all alternatives in S appear at the bottom of some individual preference R i with i N \ K k=1 N k. If K k=1 N k = N, it follows that K k=1 f(r N k, S) = S and, by repeated application of reinforcement, we obtain f(r N, S) = K k=1f(r N k, S) = S = f U (R N, S) and we are done. If K k=1 N k N, the above procedure can be applied as many times as necessary with successively smaller subsets of S to arrive at a number M N and sets N K+1,..., N K+M such that K+M k=1 N k = N and S = f(r N 1, S)... f(r N K+M, S) = K+M k=1 f(r N k, S) and, by repeated application of reinforcement, it follows that which completes the proof. f(r N, S) = f(r N K+M, S) = K+M k=1 f(r N k, S) = f U (R N, S) Considering the complexity of the last case in this proof (where N > 1 and l(r N, S, x) > 0 for all x S), it may be useful to illustrate the requisite steps by means of an example. Example 1 Suppose that S = {x, y, z, w}, N = {1,..., 10} and the restriction of the profile R N to S is such that individuals 1, 2 and 9 have x at the bottom of their ranking; individuals 3 and 4 have y at the bottom of their ranking; individuals 5 and 6 have z at the bottom of their ranking; individuals 7, 8 and 10 have w at the bottom of their ranking. Clearly, in this example, every element of S appears at least once at the bottom of an individual preference. In accordance with the above proof, we define N 1 = {1, 3, 5, 7} so that each alternative in S appears exactly once at the bottom of one of the preferences in R N 1. Define R 1 N = (R 1 1 i ) i N 1 to be fully symmetric; for instance, let yp 1 1 zp 1 1 wp 1 1 x; zp 1 3 wp 1 3 xp 1 3 y; wp 1 5 xp 1 5 yp 1 5 z; xp 1 7 yp 1 7 zp 1 7 w. 8

10 By anonymity and neutrality, it follows that f(r 1 N 1, S) = S = {x, y, z, w}. Furthermore, using the result for the one-agent case, we have f(r i, S) = f(r 1 i, S) = f U (R i, S) for all i N 1. By repeated application of individual-equality independence, it follows that f(r N 1, S) = f(r 1 N 1, S) = S. (7) The set N \N 1 is given by {2, 4, 6, 8, 9, 10} and, again, every element in S appears at least once at the bottom of one of the requisite individual relations. Letting N 2 = {2, 4, 6, 8}, the same argument as above can be employed to conclude that f(r N 2, S) = f(r 2 N 2, S) = S. (8) We obtain N \ (N 1 N 2 ) = {9, 10} and, this time, there exist two alternatives (namely, y and z) that do not appear at the bottom of R 9 or of R 10. Let N 3 = {9, 10}. By definition, and l(r N 3, S, y) = l(r N 3, S, z) = 0 l(r N 3, S, x) = l(r N 3, S, w) = 1. Furthermore, f(r 9, S) = {y, z, w} and f(r 10, S) = {x, y, z} by the one-agent result. Therefore, f(r 9, S) f(r 10, S) = {y, z} and, by reinforcement, it follows that We have N = N 1 N 2 N 3 and, combining (7), (8) and (9), f(r N 3, S) = {y, z}. (9) f(r N 1, S) f(r N 2, S) f(r N 3, S) = S S {y, z} = {y, z}. Repeated application of reinforcement yields as desired. f(r N, S) = f(r N 1, S) f(r N 2, S) f(r N 3, S) = {y, z} = f U (R N, S) 4 Discussion The primary objective of this paper is to formulate the Benthamite greatest-happiness principle in an informational framework that involves ordinal and interpersonally noncomparable utilities only. Moreover, by phrasing its least-unhappiness counterpart in the same informational setting, we are able to allow for a clear-cut comparison of these two fundamentally conflicting principles. Note that, according to the traditional interpretation of Bentham s phrase, utilitarianism results as a consequence of the greatest-happiness principle, whereas the closest analogue to the least-unhappiness principle amounts to the Rawlsian maximin criterion. The reason why a comparison of these two principles is by no means a straightforward task is that they are based on rather different assumptions regarding the measurability and interpersonal comparability of individual utilities. Utilitarianism 9

11 is well-defined if utilities are cardinally measurable and interpersonally unit-comparable, whereas the maximin criterion is well-defined in the presence of ordinal level comparability. The common informational assumption of ordinal measurability and interpersonal non-comparability that we employ in this paper allows us to phrase both principles in the same informational setting. From a formal perspective, the greatest-happiness principle and its least-unhappiness counterparts are not new; they correspond to the well-known plurality rule and the antiplurality rule. However, the road that we take to arrive at these rules is quite different from what has been done in the earlier literature. In addition, while there are some formal similarities, both our characterization of f U and its proof are new and rather different from what can be found in the literature on the anti-plurality rule. To illustrate how our approach differs from the earlier contributions, we conclude this paper by analyzing the features that set our observations apart from those that are currently available. Baharad and Nitzan (2005) use anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement, a continuity property employed by Richelson (1978) and a minimal-veto condition in order to arrive at the anti-plurality (or inverse plurality) rule which corresponds to our rule f U. The continuity property is required because Baharad and Nitzan (2005) invoke Young s (1975) theorem on scoring functions, as does Richelson (1978) in his result; see also our earlier discussion of Ching s (1996) improvement upon Richelson s (1978) characterization. We proceed without continuity and, moreover, the remaining axioms we use differ from the minimal-veto property. Barberà and Dutta (1982) also employ anonymity, neutrality and reinforcement in a characterization of the anti-plurality rule. Their result is quite different in nature from ours in that they focus on additional properties that are related to the implementation of collective choice correspondences. In addition to anonymity, neutrality and reinforcement, they use a monotonicity axiom akin to Maskin monotonicity (Maskin, 1999) and a topinvariance property to arrive at f U. As observed by Merlin (2003), a parallel result for f H is obtained by Merlin and Naeve (1999) who use a bottom-invariance property to characterize the plurality rule; see Merlin (2003) for details. Thus, the common axioms of the two results are anonymity, neutrality, reinforcement and monotonicity. Adding topinvariance characterizes the anti-plurality rule, whereas adding bottom-invariance to the common set of axioms leads to the plurality rule. We chose our specific sets of axioms to illustrate what we think of as an intuitively appealing partition of the constituent parts of the least-unhappiness rule. Our proof technique, which differs from those employed in earlier contributions, may be useful in characterizing alternative collective choice rules in a similar setting; this is a task that we suggest for further work in this area. Appendix In this appendix, we show that the axioms of our theorem are independent. For each of the six properties, we define a collective choice rule that violates this property and satisfies the remaining five. 10

12 Anonymity. Define, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, { f f(r N, S) = U (R 1, S) if N = {1, 2} and S = 2, f U (R N, S) otherwise. To see that this collective choice correspondence violates anonymity, consider the following example. Let S = {x, y} with x y and let N = {1, 2}. The preferences R 1 and R 2 restricted to S are xr 1 y and yr 2 x. Let π Π be such that π(2) = 3, π(3) = 2 and π(i) = i for all i N \ {2, 3}. Thus, we have N π = {1, 3}, R π(1) = R 1 and R π(2) = R 3. We obtain f(r N, S) = f U (R 1, S) = {x} and f(r Nπ, S) = f U ((R 1, R 3 ), S) = {x, y} {x}, a contradiction to anonymity. Neutrality is satisfied because the labels attached to the alternatives are irrelevant. To show that reinforcement is satisfied, suppose that N, N N, R N R N, R N R N and S X are such that N N = and f(r N, S) f(r N, S). If N and N both differ from {1, 2} or if S 2, the conclusion follows immediately because f U satisfies reinforcement. In all remaining cases, one of the sets N and N is equal to {1, 2}, the other set has an empty intersection with {1, 2}, and S = 2. Without loss of generality, suppose that N = {1, 2}, N N = and S = {x, y}. Furthermore, without loss of generality, suppose that xr 1 y so that f(r N, {x, y}) = f U (R 1, {x, y}) = {x}. It follows that l(r N, {x, y}, x) l(r N, {x, y}, y) (10) because agent 1 considers x to be better than y and there are only two agents in N. Also, we must have f(r N, {x, y}) f(r N, {x, y}) = {x} because this intersection is non-empty. This, in turn, implies that x f(r N, {x, y}) and thus l(r N, {x, y}, x) l(r N, {x, y}, y) (11) because f(r N, {x, y}) = f U (R N, {x, y}) by definition of f. Combining (10) and (11) and using the assumption that the intersection of N and N is empty, it follows that l ((R N, R N ), {x, y}, x) l ((R N, R N ), {x, y}, y) and, because f ((R N, R N ), {x, y}) = f U ((R N, R N ), {x, y}) by definition of f, we obtain f ((R N, R N ), {x, y}) = f U ((R N, R N ), {x, y}) = {x} = f(r N, {x, y}) f(r N, {x, y}) as was to be proven. Individual-equality independence is satisfied because all relevant comparisons according to f involve the respective comparisons according to f U. Finally, single-agent monotonicity and single-agent expansion are satisfied because f coincides with f U for single-agent societies. 11

13 Neutrality. Let x X and define, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, {x} if S = {x, x} for some x X \ {x } and N 2 and l(r f(r N, S) = N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0, f U (R N, S) otherwise. To see that this correspondence does not satisfy neutrality, let N = {1, 2}, S = {x, x} for some x X \ {x }, x R 1 x and xr 2 x. Furthermore, let y X \ {x, x} and consider the permutation σ Σ such that σ(x ) = y, σ(y) = x and σ(z) = z for all z X \ {x, x}. By definition, we have y = σ(x ) σ 1 (R 1 ) σ(x) = x and x = σ(x) σ 2 (R 2 ) σ(y) = x. It follows that f(r N, {x, x}) = {x} and f(r N, {x, y}) = f U (R N, {x, y}) = {x, y}, in contradiction to neutrality. Anonymity is satisfied because the identities of the individuals are irrelevant in the definition of this collective choice correspondence. To prove that f satisfies reinforcement, note first that we only have to consider cases in which S = {x, x} for some x X \ {x }; in all other cases, only the second branch of the above definition applies and the conclusion of reinforcement follows because the axiom is satisfied by f U. Moreover, we can restrict attention to cases in which the first branch of the definition applies for N or for N. So suppose that S = {x, x} for some x X \ {x } and, moreover, that N, N N, R N R N and R N R N are such that N N = and f(r N, S) f(r N, S). Up to exchanging the roles of N and N, we have the following two cases left to examine. Case 1. In this case, it follows that N 2 and l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0 N 2 and l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0. f(r N, {x, x}) = f(r N, {x, x}) = f(r N, {x, x}) f(r N, {x, x}) = {x} by definition of f. Because l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0 and l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0, it follows that and l ((R N, R N ), {x, x}, x) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) + l(r N, {x, x}, x) = l(r N, {x, x}, x ) + l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l ((R N, R N ), {x, x}, x ) > 0 (recall that N N = ). Thus, because we also have N N 2, the first branch of the definition of f applies and we obtain f ((R N, R N ), {x, x}, x ) = {x} = f(r N, {x, x}) f(r N, {x, x}). 12

14 Case 2. N 2 and l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) > 0 N = 1 or l(r N, {x, x}, x ) l(r N, {x, x}, x) or l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = 0. We now obtain and f(r N, {x, x}) = {x} = f(r N, {x, x}) f(r N, {x, x}) = {x} by definition of f and because the above intersection is assumed to be non-empty. Thus, x f(r N, {x, x}) and it follows that l(r N, {x, x}, x) l(r N, {x, }, x ). Hence, l ((R N, R N ), {x, x}, x) = l(r N, {x, x}, x) + l(r N, {x, x}, x) l(r N, {x, x}, x ) + l(r N, {x, x}, x ) = l ((R N, R N ), {x, x}, x ). If l(r N, {x, x}, x) = l(r N, {x, x}, x ), it follows that f ((R N, R N ), {x, x}) = {x} = f(r N, {x, x}) f(r N, {x, x}) irrespective of whether the first or the second branch applies to (R N, R N ). If l(r N, {x, x}, x) < l(r N, {x, x}, x ), it follows that the first branch of the definition of f applies and, as in the previous case, we obtain f ((R N, R N ), {x, x}) = {x} = f(r N, {x, x}) f(r N, {x, x}). Individual-equality independence is satisfied because the axiom only imposes restrictions when there are at least three alternatives and, thus, f coincides with f U in all relevant cases. Single-agent monotonicity and single-agent expansion are satisfied because f coincides with f U whenever only a single agent is present. Reinforcement. Define, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, { f f(r N, S) = U (R N, S) if N = 1 or S = 1, i N f U (R i, S) otherwise. This correspondence does not satisfy reinforcement. Consider the following example. Let S = {x, y, z}, N = {1}, N = {2}, xr 1 yr 1 z and xr 2 zr 2 y. By definition of f, we obtain and f(r N, S) = f(r 1, S) = f U (R 1, S) = {x, y} f(r N, S) = f(r 2, S) = f U (R N, S) = {x, z}. Thus, N N = and f(r N, S) f(r N, S) = {x}. By definition of f, we obtain f ((R N, R N ), S) = f ((R 1, R 2 ), S) = f(r 1, S) f(r 2, S) = {x, y, z} {x} = f(r N, S) f(r N, S), 13

15 contradicting reinforcement. That anonymity and neutrality are satisfied follows because neither the identities of the individuals nor the labels of the alternatives are relevant in the definition of f. Individualequality independence is satisfied because the order of non-worst alternatives in the profiles is irrelevant. Single-agent monotonicity and single-agent expansion are satisfied because f coincides with f U in the single-agent case. Individual-equality independence. For our next example, some further definitions are required. For all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, let L 0 (R N, S) = S and define the following S sets recursively. For all j {1,..., S }, let L j (R N, S) = {x L j 1 (R N, S) l(r N, L j 1 (R N, S), x) l(r N, L j 1 (R N, S), y) for all y L j 1 (R N, S)}. That is, L 1 (R N, S) contains the alternatives that minimize the number of agents i who end up with their worst alternative in S according to R i. Furthermore, if S > 1, L j (R N, S) identifies the set of alternatives that minimize the number of agents i who end up with their j-worst alternatives in L j 1 (R N, S) according to R i for all j {2,..., S }. Note that, in this iteration, alternatives that do not appear as minimizers at some stage are eliminated when moving to the following stage. Analogously, for all N N, for all R N R N, for all S X, for all z S and for all j {1,..., S }, define l j (R N, S, z) = {i N yr i z for all y L j 1 (R N, S)}. For future reference, note that, for all N, N N, for all R N R N, for all R N R N, for all S X such that N N = and f(r N, S) f(r N, S), and for all j {1,..., S }, l j ((R N, R N ), S, z) = l j (R N, S, z) + l j (R N, S, z) (12) for all z S because N N =. To define the collective choice correspondence f relevant here, we proceed as follows. (a) If there exists j {1,..., S } such that L j (R N, S) = 1, let f(r N, S) = L j (R N, S), where j = min{j {1,..., S } L j (R N, S) = 1}. (b) If L j (R N, S) > 1 for all j {1,..., S }, let f(r N, S) = L S (R N, S). This correspondence f violates individual-equality independence. Suppose S = {x, y, z}, N = {1, 2, 3}, xr 1 yr 1 z, zr 2 xr 2 y, yr 3 zr 3 x, 14

16 and yr 1xR 1z. By definition, f(r 1, S) = f(r 1, S) = {x, y}. Furthermore, we have and, thus, L 1 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = L 2 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = L 3 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = {x, y, z} by definition of f. Furthermore, f ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = L 3 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = {x, y, z} L 1 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = {x, y, z} and L 2 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = {y}. Thus, L 2 ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = 1 and it follows that f ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S) = {y} {x, y, z} = f ((R 1, R 2, R 3 ), S), contradicting individual-equality independence. That anonymity and neutrality are satisfied follows because neither the identities of the individuals nor the labels of the alternatives are relevant in the definition of f. To prove that reinforcement is satisfied, suppose that N, N N, R N R N, R N R N and S X are such that N N = and f(r N, S) f(r N, S). Up to exchanging the roles of N and N, the following three cases exhaust all possibilities. Case 1. There exist j, j {1,..., S } such that L j (R N, S) = 1 and L j (R N, S) = 1. By definition of f, it follows that f(r N, S) and f(r N, S) are singletons and, because the intersection of these two sets is non-empty, each of the two sets must have some x S as its only member. Let and j = min{j {1,..., S } L j (R N, S) = 1} j = min{j {1,..., S } L j (R N, S) = 1}. Without loss of generality, suppose that j j. It follows that f(r N, S) = L j (R N, S) = L j (R N, S) = f(r N, S) = f(r N, S) f(r N, S) = {x}. By definition of f, we have for all j {1,..., j } \ {j }, and l j (R N, S, x) l j (R N, S, y) for all y L j 1 (R N, S), (13) l j (R N, S, x) l j (R N, S, y) for all y L j 1 (R N, S) l j (R N, S, x) < l j (R N, S, y) for all y L j 1 (R N, S) \ {x}, l j (R N, S, x) l j (R N, S, y) for all y L j 1 (R N, S). Thus, using (12), we obtain l j ((R N, R N ), S, x) = l j (R N, S, x) + l j (R N, S, x), l j (R N, S, y) + l j (R N, S, y) = l j ((R N, R N ), S, y) 15

17 for all j {1,..., j }\{j } and for all y [L j 1 (R N, S) L j 1 (R N, S)]\{x} and, moreover, l j ((R N, R N ), S, x) = l j (R N, S, x) + l j (R N, S, x), < l j (R N, S, y) + l j (R N, S, y) (14) = l j ((R N, R N ), S, y) for all y [ L j 1 (R N, S) L j (R N, S) ] \ {x}. This implies that x f ((R N, R N ), S) by definition. Furthermore, because of the strict inequality in (14), no other element of S can be chosen; see also the argument employed in the if part of the proof of Theorem 2. Thus, as required. f ((R N, R N ), S) = {x} = f(r N, S) f(r N, S) Case 2. There exists j {1,..., S } such that L j (R N, S) = 1 and L j (R N, S) > 1 for all j {1,..., S }. By definition of f, it follows that there exists x S such that f(r N, S) = L j (R N, S) = x, where j = min{j {1,..., S } L j (R N, S) = 1}. Moreover, f(r N, S) = L S (R N, S) and, because f(r N, S) f(r N, S), we have x f(r N, S). Starting with (13), the remainder of the proof is identical to that of case 1. Case 3. L j (R N, S) > 1 for all j {1,..., S } and L j (R N, S) > 1 for all j {1,..., S }. By definition of f, f(r N, S) = L S (R N, S) and f(r N, S) = L S (R N, S). By assumption, f(r N, S) f(r N, S). (15) Now a slightly modified version of the argument employed in case 1 can be used; the only change required is that if the intersection in (15) contains more than one element, the strict-inequality argument applies to all members of the intersection versus all alternatives that are not in this intersection. See again the proof of Theorem 2 for details. Single-agent monotonicity and single-agent expansion are satisfied because f coincides with f U in the single-agent case. Single-agent monotonicity. Let, for all N N, for all R N R N and for all S X, f(r N, S) = S. This collective choice correspondence does not satisfy single-agent monotonicity. Let x, y X be distinct alternatives such that xr 1 y. By definition, we have f(r 1, {x, y}) = {x, y} {x}. That all other axioms are satisfied is immediate. 16

18 Single-agent expansion. The correspondence f = f H does not satisfy single-agent expansion. Let x, y, z X be distinct, let S = {y, z} and suppose that xr 1 y and xr 1 z. By definition, we have f(r 1, S) = {y} and f(r 1, S {x}) = {x} {x, y} = f(r 1, S) {x}. That f satisfies anonymity, neutrality and reinforcement follows from Ching s (1996) theorem (stated as Theorem 1 in the present paper). To see that individual-equality independence is satisfied, apply the argument employed in the if -part of the proof of Theorem 2, replacing l with g and with. That single-agent monotonicity is satisfied is straightforward to verify. References Baharad, E. and S. Nitzan (2005), The inverse plurality rule an axiomatization, Social Choice and Welfare 25, Barberà, S. and B. Dutta (1982), Implementability via protective equilibria, Journal of Mathematical Economics 10, Bentham, J. (1776), A Fragment on Government, T. Payne, London. Bentham, J. (1789), An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, T. Payne, London. Bergson, A. (1938), A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics, Quarterly Journal of Economics 52, Blackorby, C., W. Bossert and D. Donaldson (2002), Utilitarianism and the theory of justice, in: K.J. Arrow, A.K. Sen and K. Suzumura (eds.), Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 1, Elsevier, Amsterdam, Chapter 11, Bowring, J. (1843), The Works of Jeremy Bentham, published under the Superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring, William Tait, Edinburgh, Vol. 1. Ching, S. (1996), A simple characterization of plurality rule, Journal of Economic Theory 71, Hicks, J.R. (1939a; second edn. 1946), Value and Capital, Oxford University Press, London. Hicks, J.R. (1939b), The foundations of welfare economics, Economic Journal 49, Hicks, J.R. (1940), The valuation of social income, Economica 7, Kaldor, N. (1939), Welfare propositions in economics and interpersonal comparisons of utility, Economic Journal 49,

19 Maskin, E. (1999), Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality, Review of Economic Studies 66, Merlin, V. (2003), The axiomatic characterizations of majority voting and scoring rules, Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines 163, Merlin, V. and J. Naeve (1999), Implementation of social choice correspondences via demanding equilibria, in: H. de Swart (ed.), Logic, Game Theory and Social Choice: Proceedings of the International Conference LGS 99, Tilburg University Press, Tilburg, Rawls, J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Belknap, Cambridge, MA. Richelson, J.T. (1978), A characterization result for the plurality rule, Journal of Economic Theory 19, Robbins, L. (1932; second edn. 1935), An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, Macmillan, London. Samuelson, P.A. (1938a), A note on the theory of consumer s behaviour, Economica 5, Samuelson, P.A. (1938b), A note on the theory of consumer s behaviour: an addendum, Economica 5, Samuelson, P.A. (1947; enlarged second edn. 1983), Foundations of Economic Analysis, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Samuelson, P.A. (1981), Bergsonian welfare Economics, in: S. Rosenfielde (ed.), Economic Welfare and the Economics of Soviet Socialism: Essays in Honour of Abram Bergson, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA, Sekiguchi, Y. (2012), A characterization of the plurality rule, Economics Letters 116, Smith, J.H. (1973), Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate, Econometrica 41, Yeh, C.-H. (2008), An efficiency characterization of plurality rule in collective choice problems, Economic Theory 34, Young, H.P. (1975), Social choice scoring functions, SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics 28,

Single-plateaued choice

Single-plateaued choice Single-plateaued choice Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7, Canada walter.bossert@umontreal.ca and Hans Peters

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montréal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown, Montréal QC H3C 3J7, Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation

Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation 2004-10 Reference Groups and Individual Deprivation BOSSERT, Walter D'AMBROSIO, Conchita Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey

Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey Multi-profile intertemporal social choice: a survey Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism

Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism 2004-03 Anonymous Single-Profile Welfarism BLACKORBY, Charles BOSSERT, Walter DONALDSON, David Département de sciences économiques Université de Montréal Faculté des arts et des sciences C.P. 6128, succursale

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper No. 2007-12 Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University

More information

The measurement of welfare change

The measurement of welfare change The measurement of welfare change Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal walter.bossert@videotron.ca Bhaskar Dutta Department of Economics, University of Warwick B.Dutta@warwick.ac.uk

More information

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition

A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition Working Paper Series A head-count measure of rank mobility and its directional decomposition Walter Bossert Burak Can Conchita D Ambrosio ECINEQ WP 2016-424 ECINEQ 2016-424 December 2016 www.ecineq.org

More information

Distributive Justice and Economic Inequality

Distributive Justice and Economic Inequality Distributive Justice and Economic Inequality P. G. Piacquadio UiO, January 17th, 2017 Outline of the course Paolo: Introductory lecture [Today!] Rolf: Theory of income (and wealth) inequality Geir: Distributive

More information

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice Susumu Cato Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science Research Fellow First Version: January 10, 2007

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

Measuring rank mobility with variable population size

Measuring rank mobility with variable population size Measuring rank mobility with variable population size Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal, Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca Burak Can Department of Economics, Maastricht

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Social Choice and Mechanism Design Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Alexander Westkamp April 2011 Introduction Two concerns regarding our previous approach to collective decision making:

More information

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: Preference Aggregation, Judgment Aggregation, Graph Aggregation Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss

More information

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics

Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Public Economics: Chapter 9 1 Public Economics Ben Heijdra Chapter 9: Introduction to Normative Public Economics Objectives of this chapter Public Economics: Chapter 9 2 Read Atkinson & Stiglitz (1980,

More information

The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd.

The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd. The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd. Oxford University Press http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297086. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.

More information

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information by Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30303

More information

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function Claude Lamboray Abstract In this paper, we are interested in a preference function that associates to a profile of linear orders the

More information

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS Gopakumar Achuthankutty 1 and Souvik Roy 1 1 Economic Research Unit, Indian Statistical Institute, Kolkata Abstract In line with the works

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Journal of Economic and Social Research, 1 (1) 1999, 109-117 Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Ahmet Kara 1 Abstract. This paper presents a sufficient condition under which constitutional rights

More information

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach

The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach The Fundamental Theorems of Welfare Economics in a Non-Welfaristic Approach Koichi Tadenuma Faculty of Economics, Hitotsubashi University Kunitachi, Tokyo 186-8601, Japan Email: tadenuma@econ.hit-u.ac.jp

More information

Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice*

Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice* Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice* by Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert and David Donaldson August 1999 revised August 2000 Prepared as Chapter 20 of the Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare K.

More information

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Social Choice Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Summer term 2017 Version: March 15, 2018 CONTENTS Remarks 1 0 Introduction 2 1 The Case of 2 Alternatives 3 1.1 Examples for social choice rules............................

More information

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Ryo-Ichi Nagahisa y Kansai University Koichi Suga z Waseda University November 14, 2017 Abstract A social state is assumed to be chracterized by welfare

More information

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University {kenshin,sandholm}@cscmuedu Abstract The Muller-Satterthwaite

More information

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Wonki Jo Cho Biung-Ghi Ju June 27, 2018 Abstract We study the problem of determining memberships to the groups in a Boolean algebra. The Boolean algebra is composed

More information

Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities

Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities Lars Ehlers Alexander Westkamp December 12, 2017 Section 1 contains the omitted proofs of Lemma 5, Lemma 6 and Lemma 7 Subsection

More information

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia Abstract A procedure to construct a social welfare function from a social choice function is suggested

More information

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES

ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES ANDREW YOUNG SCHOOL OF POLICY STUDIES On procedures for measuring deprivation and living standards of societies in a multi-attribute framework Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University

More information

Piercing the Veil of Ignorance

Piercing the Veil of Ignorance Piercing the Veil of Ignorance Shachar Kariv UC Berkeley William R. Zame UCLA September 15, 2008 Abstract Theories of justice in the spirit of Harsanyi and Rawls argue that fair-minded people should aspire

More information

Comparing impossibility theorems

Comparing impossibility theorems Comparing impossibility theorems Randy Calvert, for Pol Sci 507 Spr 2017 All references to A-S & B are to Austen-Smith and Banks (1999). Basic notation X set of alternatives X set of all nonempty subsets

More information

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency Richard Bradley Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method London School of Economics and Political Science February 24, 2015

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Felix Brandt and Paul Harrenstein Technische Universität München 85748 Garching bei München, Germany {brandtf,harrenst}@in.tum.de Rationalizability and similar

More information

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Axiomatic bargaining. theory Axiomatic bargaining theory Objective: To formulate and analyse reasonable criteria for dividing the gains or losses from a cooperative endeavour among several agents. We begin with a non-empty set of

More information

Ordered Value Restriction

Ordered Value Restriction Ordered Value Restriction Salvador Barberà Bernardo Moreno Univ. Autònoma de Barcelona and Univ. de Málaga and centra March 1, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we restrict the pro les of preferences to be

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Mantas Radzvilas July 2017 Abstract In 1986 David Gauthier proposed an arbitration scheme

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS AN EFFICIENCY CHARACTERIZATION OF PLURALITY SOCIAL CHOICE ON SIMPLE PREFERENCE DOMAINS Biung-Ghi Ju University of Kansas

More information

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Lars Ehlers Bettina Klaus This Version: March 2004 Abstract We study a simple model of assigning indivisible objects (e.g., houses, jobs, offices, etc.)

More information

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core The Relation Between Implementability and the Core Eiichi Miyagawa Department of Economics, Columbia University 420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027, U.S.A. em437@columbia.edu June 11, 2002 Abstract

More information

Copyright Author(s) ISSN

Copyright Author(s) ISSN Copyright Author(s) ISSN 1796-3133 Printed in Uniprint Turku 2012 Hannu Salonen Aggregating and Updating Information Aboa Centre for Economics Discussion Paper No. 73 March 2012 ABSTRACT We study information

More information

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Abstract: This paper gives a non-fixed point theoretic proof of equilibrium existence when the excess demand function of an exchange

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information

Norm-Constrained Choices

Norm-Constrained Choices Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 329 339 Yongsheng Xu Norm-Constrained Choices Abstract: This paper develops a general and unified framework to discuss individual choice behaviors

More information

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction

A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM. Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE. Introduction A FAIR SOLUTION TO THE COMPENSATION PROBLEM Giacomo Valletta WORK IN PROGRESS, PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE Abstract. In this paper we deal with a fair division model concerning compensation among individuals endowed

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Remzi Sanver and Arunava Sen May 2010 Paper No. 07-2010 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE AUTHOR(S) AND

More information

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives 3.- Social Choice and Welfare Economics 3.1 Arrow s Theorem We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives Let R denote the set of all preference relations

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Volume 31, Issue 1 Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Abstract In an election contest, a losing candidate a can manipulate

More information

Measuring Economic Insecurity

Measuring Economic Insecurity Measuring Economic Insecurity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal walterbossert@umontrealca Conchita D Ambrosio Università di Milano-Bicocca, DIW Berlin and Econpubblica,

More information

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park pacuit.org epacuit@umd.edu March 4, 2014 Eric Pacuit 1 Competing desiderata

More information

Mechanism Design with Two Alternatives in Quasi-Linear Environments

Mechanism Design with Two Alternatives in Quasi-Linear Environments Mechanism Design with Two Alternatives in Quasi-Linear Environments Thierry Marchant and Debasis Mishra July 7, 2014 Abstract We study mechanism design in quasi-linear private values environments when

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

The core of voting games: a partition approach

The core of voting games: a partition approach The core of voting games: a partition approach Aymeric Lardon To cite this version: Aymeric Lardon. The core of voting games: a partition approach. International Game Theory Review, World Scientific Publishing,

More information

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Susumu Cato January 17, 2006 Abstract In actual life, we face the opportunity of many choices, from that opportunity set, we have to choose from different alternatives.

More information

Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes

Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes Condorcet Consistency and the strong no show paradoxes Laura Kasper Hans Peters Dries Vermeulen July 10, 2018 Abstract We consider voting correspondences that are, besides Condorcet Consistent, immune

More information

On the meaning of the Nash product. Walter Trockel

On the meaning of the Nash product. Walter Trockel On the meaning of the Nash product Walter Trockel Institute of Mathematical Economics (IMW), Bielefeld University and W.P. Carey School of Business, Arizona State University, Tempe AZ November 2003 Abstract

More information

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience Applied Mathematics E-Notes, 8(2008), 82-88 c ISSN 1607-2510 Available free at mirror sites of http://www.math.nthu.edu.tw/ amen/ The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models Daron Acemoglu MIT February 7 and 12, 2013. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 2 and 3 February

More information

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA MARIA GOLTSMAN Abstract. This note shows that, in separable environments, any monotonic social choice function

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University Providence, RI 02912

More information

Dividends and Weighted Values in Games with Externalities

Dividends and Weighted Values in Games with Externalities Dividends and Weighted Values in Games with Externalities Inés Macho-Stadler David Pérez-Castrillo David Wettstein August 28, 2009 Abstract In this paper, we provide further support for the family of average

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 David Pérez-Castrillo 2 Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona David Wettstein 3 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev April 2005 1 We gratefully

More information

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Preliminary version - Please do not distribute Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Kristof Bosmans a Luc Lauwers b Erwin Ooghe b a Department of Economics, Maastricht University, Tongersestraat

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics. Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics. Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 08/04 Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence y Indraneel Dasgupta June 2008 2008 DP 08/04 Contraction consistent

More information

Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context

Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context Andreas Darmann, Christian Klamler and Ulrich Pferschy Abstract This paper combines social choice theory with discrete optimization. We assume that individuals

More information

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective.

TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective. TitleNo-Envy, Efficiency, and Collective Author(s) Sakamoto, Norihito Citation Issue 2011-08 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/19289 Right Hitotsubashi University

More information

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible Bettina Klaus October 2005 Abstract We consider the generalization of Shapley and Scarf s (1974) model of

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting Daron Acemoglu MIT September 6 and 11, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2 September 6

More information

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra

More information

Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage

Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage Comparing Societies with Different Numbers of Individuals on the Basis of Their Average Advantage Nicolas Gravel, Thierry Marchant, and Arunava Sen 1 Introduction At an abstract level, one can view the

More information

Rules for Aggregating Information

Rules for Aggregating Information Rules for Aggregating Information Christopher P. Chambers and Alan D. Miller May 1, 2010 Abstract We present a model of information aggregation in which agents information is represented through partitions

More information

An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings

An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings An axiomatization of the mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare orderings Walter Bossert and Kohei Kamaga November 16, 2018 Abstract We axiomatize the class of mixed utilitarian-maximin social welfare

More information

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE M. J. ALBIZURI*, J. C. SANTOS Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new cost sharing rule-the minimal overlap cost sharing rule-which is associated with the minimal

More information

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1. INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 41, No. 2, May 2000 SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel In this article we consider

More information

Incentive-Compatible Voting Rules with Positively Correlated Beliefs

Incentive-Compatible Voting Rules with Positively Correlated Beliefs Incentive-Compatible Voting Rules with Positively Correlated Beliefs Mohit Bhargava, Dipjyoti Majumdar and Arunava Sen August 13, 2014 Abstract We study the consequences of positive correlation of beliefs

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Regular Choice and the Weak xiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Indraneel Dasgupta School of Economics, University of Nottingham, UK. and Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University of

More information

Committee Selection with a Weight Constraint Based on Lexicographic Rankings of Individuals

Committee Selection with a Weight Constraint Based on Lexicographic Rankings of Individuals Committee Selection with a Weight Constraint Based on Lexicographic Rankings of Individuals Christian Klamler 1, Ulrich Pferschy 2, and Stefan Ruzika 3 1 University of Graz, Institute of Public Economics,

More information

Combining Equity and Utilitarianism in a Mathematical Programming Model

Combining Equity and Utilitarianism in a Mathematical Programming Model Combining Equity and Utilitarianism in a athematical Programming odel J. N. Hooker Carnegie ellon University john@hooker.tepper.cmu.edu H. P. Williams London School of Economics h.p.williams@lse.ac.uk

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus This Version: April 2010 Previous Versions: November 2007 and December 2008 Abstract We consider one-to-one matching

More information

FACULTY FEATURE ARTICLE 5 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions

FACULTY FEATURE ARTICLE 5 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions FACULTY FEATURE ARTICLE 5 Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Two Simple Single-Profile Versions Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics Brown University Providence, RI 02912 Allan_Feldman@Brown.edu http://www.econ.brown.edu/fac/allan_feldman

More information

Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order

Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order Fleurbaey-Michel Conjecture on Equitable weak Paretian Social Welfare Order Ram Sewak Dubey Department of Economics, Uris Hall, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14853, USA Abstract The paper examines the

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Todd Davies Symbolic Systems Program Stanford University joint work with Raja Shah, Renee Trochet, and Katarina Ling Decision

More information

Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable

Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable John Rehbeck Department of Economics University of California-San Diego jrehbeck@ucsd.edu Abstract We extend the result from Bossert and

More information