Resource-monotonicity and Population-monotonicity in Cake-cutting

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Resource-monotonicity and Population-monotonicity in Cake-cutting"

Transcription

1 Resource-monotonicity and Population-monotonicity in Cake-cutting Erel Segal-Halevi Bar-Ilan University, Ramat-Gan , Israel. Balázs Sziklai Centre for Economic and Regional Studies, Hungarian Academy of Sciences, December 22, 2015 Abstract We study the monotonicity properties of solutions in the classic problem of fair cake-cutting - dividing a single heterogeneous resource among agents with dierent preferences. Resource- and populationmonotonicity relate to scenarios where the cake, or the number of participants who divide the cake, changes. It is required that the utility of all participants change in the same direction: either all of them are better-o (if there is more to share) or all are worse-o (if there is less to share). We formally introduce these concepts to the cake-cutting setting and present a meticulous axiomatic analysis. We show that classic fair cake-cutting protocols, like the Cut and Choose, Banach-Knaster, Dubins-Spanier and many other fail to be monotonic. We then present monotonic division rules in two utility models. When the utility functions are additive, there are several proportional and Pareto-optimal division rules that satisfy one or both monotonicity axioms. In contrast, when the utility functions have a connectivity constraint such as in land division, no proportional and Pareto-optimal rule can satisfy any monotonicity axiom. Assuming weak-pareto-optimality (no other allocation is better for all agents), we provide a proportional resourcemonotonic protocol for two agents and some population-monotonic rules for n agents. 1

2 1 Introduction Two siblings, Ann and Miriam, inherit a piece of land from their father. Just as soon as they agree on how to share the land, they learn that their father recently bought another strip of land. They re-divide the whole estate. However Miriam ends up with a more valuable piece of land while Ann is worse o. Ann feels that they should try another division protocol. After a little reasoning Ann and Miriam manage to divide the estate. Just as soon as they settle the issue, they discover that they have a little step-brother. They decide to divide the land three-ways by using the same division rule as before. However Ann ends up with a more valuable piece of land while Miriam is worse o. Miriam feels that they should try another division protocol. These two examples motivate the so called resource-monotonicity (RM) and population-monotonicity (PM) axioms. Resource-monotonicity, sometimes known as aggregate monotonicity, requires that when new resources are added, and the same division rule is used consistently, the welfare of the participants should weakly increase. Population-monotonicity is concerned with changes in the number of participants. It requires that when someone leaves the division process and abandons his share, the welfare of the remaining participants should weakly increase. Conversely, when a new agent joins the process, the welfare of the existing participants should weakly decrease. We study the two monotonicity requirements in the framework of the classic fair cake-cutting problem (Steinhaus, 1948), where a single heterogeneous resource - such as land or time - has to be divided fairly. Fair cake-cutting protocols can be applied in inheritance cases and divorce settlements. They can be also used to divide broadcast time of advertisements and priority access time for customers of an Internet service provider (Caragiannis et al., 2011; Procaccia, 2015). The notion of fairness in cake-cutting is commonly restricted to two properties: proportionality means that each of the n agents should receive a value of at least 1/n of the total cake value; envy-freeness means that each agent weakly prefers his share over the share of any other agent. We argue that monotonicity is as important fairness axiom as proportionality and envy-freeness, since the principle stems from solidarity. If there is less to share, some agents will necessarily lose. Hence it is only fair to require that the loss is (weakly) shared by all agents. On the other hand, if there is more to share, it is fair to require that the gain is (weakly) enjoyed by all agents. Additionally, economic growth might be objected if the benets are 2

3 not shared by everyone. 1 Experimental studies show that people value certain fairness criteria more than others. Herreiner and Puppe (2009) demonstrated that people are willing to sacrice Pareto-eciency in order to reach an envy-free allocation. To our knowledge no study was ever conducted to unfold the relationship between monotonicity and eciency or proportionality. However some indirect evidence points toward that monotonicity of the solution is in some cases as important as proportionality. In the apportionment problem there is a parliament with a xed number of seats and administrative regions with dierent number of voters. The question is assuming that electoral districts are of equal size within each of the administrative regions how to distribute the seats among the administrative regions to minimize the dierences between the voters inuences. The problem is analogous to cake-cutting where the cake corresponds to the parliamentary seats which have to be distributed. During the 1880 US census C.W. Seaton, a Chief Clerk of the Census Oce, noted that an enlargement of the House of Representatives from 299 to 300 would result in a loss of seat for State Alabama. This anomaly together with the later discovered population and new state paradoxes pressed the legislators to adopt newer and newer apportionment rules. The currently used seat distribution method is free from such anomalies, however it does not satisfy the so called Hare-quota, a basic guarantee of proportionality (Balinski and Young, 1975). Here we present a systematic analysis of the relationship of resource- and population-monotonicity and classical axioms such as Pareto-eciency and proportionality. To the best of our knowledge, this is the rst paper that studies these properties in a cake-cutting setting Results We survey many traditional cake-cutting protocols and show that they do not satisfy either of the monotonicity axioms. In particular, all methods based on the Cut and Choose scheme violate resource-monotonicity. This motivates a search for division rules that are both fair in the conventional sense and 1 A recurring theme in recent social movements like the "99%" and "Occupy Wall Street" is that although the current economic system indeed brings economic growth, it does only to a small fraction of the population, while the other 99% becomes poorer. 2 We found a single mention of these properties in the concluding comments of Berliant et al. (1992): "...there are a number of important issues that should be tackled next pertaining, in particular, to the existence of selections from the no-envy solution satisfying additional properties, Examples are monotonicity with respect to the amount to be divided (all agents should benet from such an increase), and with respect to changes in the number of claimants (all agents initially present should lose in such circumstances)." 3

4 monotonic. This search is done under two dierent assumptions regarding the agents' utility functions, both of which are common in the cake-cutting literature. In both models, each agent has a value measure dened over the cake. In the additive model, the utility of a piece of cake is just the value measure of that piece; the geometry of the piece has no importance. In the connected model, the utility of a piece of cake is the value of the most valuable connected component of the piece. Connected utility functions make sense in many applications. E.g., when dividing land, a large connected piece can be used for building a house, but a collection of small disconnected pieces is virtually useless. Note that when the agents' utility functions are connected, eciency dictates that each agent should be given a single connected piece, since he will not be able to use the other pieces. In the additive model, our results are positive. There are several Paretooptimal proportional division rules that satisfy one or both monotonicity axioms. The Nash-optimal rule, maximizing the product of values, is envy-free (hence also proportional), resource-monotonic and population-monotonic. The leximin-optimal division rules, which are motivated by the egalitarian justice criterion, are population-monotonic. There are two leximin rules: the rule using relative values is proportional but not resource-monotonic and the rule using absolute values is resource-monotonic but not proportional. In the connected model, the situation is not so positive. Each of the monotonicity properties is incompatible with proportionality and Paretooptimality. That is, no Pareto-optimal proportional division rule can be either resource- or population-monotonic. Thus the fair divider has to choose between Pareto-optimality and monotonicity. While from an economics perspective, Pareto-optimality is crucial, public opinion may not always agree. As explained above, in some cases people are willing to sacrice eciency to get fairness. As a compromise, we suggest several division rules which are proportional and weakly-pareto-optimal (no other allocation is strictly preferred by all agents; see e.g. Varian (1974)) while satisfying one of the monotonicity axioms. The max-equitable-connected rules, which give equally-valuable pieces to each agent while maximizing this value, are both population monotonic. Analogously to the leximin-optimal rules, there are two such rules: the rule equalizing the relative values (normalized such that the entire cake value is 1) is proportional but not resource-monotonic, and the rule equalizing the absolute (not normalized) values is resource-monotonic but not proportional. Additionally, we present a proportional and resource-monotonic division protocol for two agents. It is an open question whether there exists a proportional and resource-monotonic rule for n agents. The equitable and leximin rules belong to the cardinal welfarism frame- 4

5 work (cf. chapter 3 of Moulin (2004)). They rely on inter-agent utility comparison, and make sense if and when such a comparison is feasible. For example, suppose the agents are rms, each of which wants to use the land to a pre-specied purpose (e.g. one rm plans to dig for oil, another rm wants to build housing complexes, etc.). Then, economic models can be used to estimate the monetary utility of each rm for each piece of land and the estimates can be used to calculate leximin/equitable divisions (see the conclusion of Chambers (2005) for further discussion of the additive utility model). Although these two rules have several drawbacks, such as high computational complexity and strategic issues that make them hard to implement in real life, their mere existence shows that it is possible to combine monotonicity with certain fairness axioms. The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 reviews the related literature. Section 3 formally presents the cake-cutting problem and the monotonicity axioms. Section 4 examines classic cake-cutting protocols and shows that they are not monotonic. Section 5 presents our results for agents with additive utilities (and no connectivity constraints). Section 6 presents our results for agents that want connected pieces. Section 7 concludes and presents a table summarizing the various rules' properties. 2 Related Work The cake-cutting problem originates from the work of the polish mathematician Hugo Steinhaus and his students Banach and Knaster (Steinhaus, 1948). Their primary concern was how to divide the cake in a fair way. Since then, game theorists analyzed the strategic issues related to cake-cutting, while computer scientists were focusing mainly on how to implement solutions, i.e. the computational complexity of cake-cutting protocols. Monotonicity issues have been extensively studied with respect to cooperative game theory (Calleja et al., 2012), political representation (Balinski and Young, 1982), computer resource allocation (Ghodsi et al., 2011) and other fair division problems. Extensive reviews of monotonicity axioms can be found in chapters 3, 6 and 7 of (Moulin, 2004) and in chapter 7 of Thomson (2011). Thomson (1997) denes the replacement principle, which requires that, whenever any change happens in the environment, the welfare of all agents not responsible for the change should be aected in the same direction - they should all be made at least as well o as they were initially or they should all be made at most as well o. This is the most general way of expressing the 5

6 idea of solidarity among agents. The PM and RM axioms are special cases of this principle. The consistency axiom (cf. Young (1987) or Thomson (2012)) is related to population-monotonicity, but it is fundamentally dierent as in that case the leaving agents take their fair shares with them. Arzi et al. (2011) study the "dumping paradox" in cake-cutting. They show that, in some cakes, discarding a part of the cake improves the total social welfare of any envy-free division. This implies that enlarging the cake might decrease the total social welfare. This is related to resourcemonotonicity; the dierence is that in our case we are interested in the welfare of the individual agents and not in the total social welfare. Chambers (2005) studies a related cake-cutting axiom called "division independence": if the cake is divided into sub-plots and each sub-plot is divided according to a rule, then the outcome should be identical to dividing the original land using the same rule. He proves that the only rule which satises Pareto-optimality and division independence is the utilitarian-optimal rule - the rule which maximizes the sum of the agents' utilities. The rule is only feasible when the utilities are additive (with no connectivity constraints). Unfortunately, this rule does not satisfy fairness axioms such as proportionality. Walsh (2011) studies the problem of "online cake-cutting", in which agents arrive and depart during the process of dividing the cake. He shows how to adapt classic procedures like cut-and-choose and the Dubins-Spanier in order to satisfy online variants of the fairness axioms. Monotonicity properties are not studied, although the problem is similar in spirit to the concept of population-monotonicity. 3 Model 3.1 Cake-cutting A cake-cutting problem is a triple Γ(N, C, (ˆv C i ) i N ) where: N = {1, 2,..., n} denotes the set of agents who participate in the cakecutting process. In examples with a small number of agents, we often refer to them by names (Alice, Bob, Carl...). C is the cake. For simplicity we assume that C is a interval, C = [0, c] for some real number c. We call a Borel subset of C a slice. 6

7 ˆv i C is the value measure of agent i, which is a real-valued function on the slices of C. When it does not cause confusion we will omit C from the upper index, and simply write ˆv i. A slice with zero Lebesgue-measure is referred to as a zero slice while a slice with positive Lebesgue-measure as a positive slice. A slice that is allotted to an agent is called a piece. As the term "measure" implies, the value measures of all agents are countably additive: the value measures of a union of disjoint slices is the sum of the values of the slices. Moreover, we assume that the value measures are nonnegative and bounded. That is, ˆv i assigns a non-negative, but nite number to each slice of C. We also assume that the value measures are non-atomic: this means that a zero slice has zero value to anyone. In particular any point on the interval is worthless for the agents. Without loss of generality we also assume that every positive slice has positive value to at least one agent. All these assumptions are standard in the cake-cutting literature. The utility of an agent is based on its value measure in one of two ways: In the additive utilities model, the utility is just the value: u i (X) = ˆv i (X) In the connected utilities model, the agent can use only a single connected piece, so the utility of a piece is the value of the most valuable connected interval in that piece: u i (X) = sup ˆv i (I) I X where the supremum is over all connected intervals I that are subsets of X. Both these models are common in the classic cake-cutting literature. In fact, many papers explicitly assume that each agent must be allocated a single connected piece. Our model diverges from the standard cake-cutting setup in that we do not require the value measures to be normalized. That is, the value of the entire cake is not necessarily the same for all agents. This is important because we examine scenarios where the cake changes, so the cake value might become higher or lower. Hence, we dierentiate between absolute and relative value measures: The absolute value measure of the entire cake, ˆv i (C), can be any positive value and it can be dierent for dierent agents. 7

8 The relative value of the entire cake is 1 for all agents. Relative value measures are denoted by vi C and dened by: vi C (S) = ˆv i C (S)/ˆv i C (C). Again, for convenience's sake we will write simply v i (S) when there is only one cake. It is also common to assume that value measures are private information of the agents. This question leads us to whether agents are honest about their preferences. As we noted before cake-cutting problems can be studied from a strategic angle. Here, however, we will not analyze the strategic behavior of the agents. The aim is to divide the cake into n pairwise-disjoint slices. A division rule is a function that takes a cake-cutting problem as input and returns a division X = (X 1,..., X n ), or a set of divisions. Note that a division does not necessarily compose a partition of C (i.e. free disposal is assumed). A division rule R is called essentially single-valued (ESV) if X, Y R(Γ) implies that for all i N, ˆv i (X i ) = ˆv i (Y i ). That is, even if R returns a set of divisions, all agents are indierent between these divisions. The classic requirements of fair cake-cutting are the following. A division X is called: Pareto-optimal (PO) if there is no other division which is weakly better for all agents and strictly better for at least one agent. Weakly-Pareto-optimal (WPO) if there is no other division which is strictly better for all agents. Proportional (PROP) if each agent gets at least 1/n fraction of the cake according to his own evaluation, i.e. for all i N, v i (X i ) 1/n. Note that the denition uses relative values. Envy-free (EF) if each agent gets a piece which is weakly better, for that agent, than all other pieces: for all i, j N, v i (X i ) v i (X j ). Note that here it is irrelevant whether absolute or relative values are used. Note also that PO+EF imply PROP. A division rule is called Pareto-optimal (PO) if it returns only whole divisions. The same applies to weak-pareto-optimality, proportionality and envy-freeness. 3.2 Monotonicity We now dene the two monotonicity properties. In the introduction we dened them informally for the special case in which the division rule returns 8

9 a single division. Our formal denition is more general and applicable to rules that may return a set of divisions. Denition 3.1. Let N be a xed set of agents, C = [0, c], C = [0, c ] two cakes where c < c, and let (ˆv i C ) i N, (ˆv i C ) i N be two value measures such that (ˆv i C ) i N coincides with (ˆv i C ) i N on the slices of C. The cake-cutting problem Γ = (N, C, (ˆv i C ) i N ) is called a cake-enlargement of the problem Γ = (N, C, (ˆv i C ) i N ). By denition the cake is always enlarged on the right hand side. This might be critical for some protocols. For instance in the Dubins-Spanier moving knife protocol the cake is processed from left to right (Dubins and Spanier, 1961). However, most of our results (except that of Subsection 6.4) are valid whenever C C, regardless of whether the cake is enlarged from the left, right or middle. Denition 3.2. (a) A division rule R is called upwards resource-monotonic, if for all pairs (Γ, Γ ), where Γ is a cake-enlargement of Γ, for every division X R(Γ) there exists a division Y R(Γ ) such that ˆv i (Y i ) ˆv i (X i ) for all i N (i.e all agents are weakly better-o in the new division). (b) A division rule R is called downwards resource-monotonic, if for all pairs (Γ, Γ), where Γ is a cake-enlargement of Γ, for every division Y R(Γ ) there exists a division X R(Γ) such that ˆv i (X i ) ˆv i (Y i ) for all i N (i.e all agents are weakly worse-o in the new division). (c) A division rule is resource-monotonic (RM), if it is both upwards and downwards resource-monotonic. Denition 3.3. Let C be a xed cake, N and N two sets of agents such that N N and (ˆv i ) i N their value measures. The cake-cutting problem Γ = (N, C, (ˆv i ) i N ) is called a population-reduction of the problem Γ = (N, C, (ˆv i ) i N ). Denition 3.4. (a) A division rule R is called upwards population-monotonic, if for all pairs (Γ, Γ) such that Γ is a population-reduction of Γ, for every division Y R(Γ ) there exists a division X R(Γ) such that ˆv i (X i ) ˆv i (Y i ) for all i N (all the original agents are weakly worse-o in the new division). (b) A division rule R is called downwards population-monotonic, if for all pairs (Γ, Γ ) such that Γ is a population-reduction of Γ, for every division X R(Γ) there exists a division Y R(Γ ) such that ˆv i (Y i ) ˆv i (X i ) for all i N (all remaining agents are weakly better-o in the new division). (c) A division rule is population-monotonic (PM), if it is both upwards and downwards population-monotonic. 9

10 Remark 3.1. As usual in the literature, the monotonicity axioms care only about absolute values (e.g., if the relative value of an agent decreases when the cake grows, this is not considered a violation of RM). Remark 3.2. For essentially-single-valued solutions, downwards resource (or population) monotonicity implies upwards resource (or population) monotonicity and vice versa. Set valued solutions, however, may satisfy only one direction of these axioms. Remark 3.3. The monotonicity axioms in Thomson (2011) require that all divisions in R(Γ) be weakly better/worse than all divisions in R(Γ ). In contrast, our denition only requires that there exists such a division. This is closer to the denition of aggregate monotonicity, which originates from cooperative game theory Peleg and Sudhölter (2007). The rationale is that even if a set-valued solution is used, only a single allocation will be implemented. Hence, the divider can be faithful to the monotonicity principles even if the rule suggests many non-monotonic allocations as well. Because our monotonicity requirements are weaker, any impossibility result in our model is valid in Thomson's model, too. This is not true in general for positive results; however, the specic positive results in the present paper are all based on essentially-single-valued rules. Hence, by the previous remark, they are valid in Thomson's model, too. 4 Monotonicity and eciency of classical protocols Although resource and population-monotonicity are well established axioms in various elds of fair division, the cake-cutting literature has not adopted these ideas so far. Moreover, classical division methods like the Banach- Knaster (Steinhaus, 1948), Cut and Choose, Dubins-Spanier (Dubins and Spanier, 1961), Even-Paz (Even and Paz, 1984), Fink (Fink, 1964) or the Selfridge-Conway protocol do not satisfy these axioms. A detailed explanation for most of these can be found in (Brams and Taylor, 1996). Admittedly this list is incomplete, still it illustrates our point well. All the counterexamples below feature piecewise homogeneous cakes. These are nite unions of disjoint intervals, such that on each interval the value densities of all agents are constant (although dierent agents may evaluate the same piece dierently). In such cases, the function ˆv i ([0, x]) which displays the value (for Agent i) of the piece which lies left to the point x R is a piecewise-linear function (see Figure 1). We stress that our division rules, 10

11 ˆv ([0, x]) ˆv([0, x]) ˆv A ([0, x]) ˆv B ([0, x]) } {{ } cake x } {{ } cake x Figure 1: Piecewise homogeneous cake with two players. The derivative of ˆv([0, x]) indicates the density of the value. Note that the value measures are not normalized, hence ˆv A ([0, c]) ˆv B ([0, c]). presented in the next section, hold for arbitrary cakes - not only piecewisehomogeneous. Piecewise homogeneous cakes can be represented by a simple table containing the value densities of the agents on the dierent slices. For example the cake in Figure 1 has the following representation. ˆv A ˆv B Resource-monotonicity First let us examine why Cut and Choose is not resource-monotonic. In the next couple of examples the sign over a column indicates the enlargement. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv A ˆv B Table 1: Colored cells indicate the pieces of the agents. Consider the cake described in Table 1. While the extra piece is not present, Agent A (Alice) cuts the cake after the second slice, allowing Agent B (Bob) to choose the piece worth 5 for him. However if we enlarge the cake, Alice cuts after the third slice and no matter which piece Bob chooses, he 11

12 loses utility. This simple counterexample implies that the Banach-Knaster, Dubins-Spanier, Even-Paz and the Fink methods are not resource-monotonic either, as they all produce the same division on the above cake as the Cut and Choose. 3 Note that the fact that we enlarge the cake on the right-hand side is not an issue here. As the next example shows the Dubins-Spanier method violates resource-monotonicity even if we reverse its order, i.e. we move the knives and execute the cuts from right to left. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C Before the enlargement, Bob got the rightmost slice and Carl got the middle slice, leaving Alice with a piece worth 4 for her. With the extra piece present, Alice picks the rightmost slice 4. Similar reasoning shows that the reverse Even-Paz is not resource-monotonic either. Finally, the Selfridge-Conway protocol - the only envy-free method we survey here - is not resource-monotonic either. Consider the following cake. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C In the smaller cake, Alice cuts the cake into three parts that worth 6 to her, each made of two adjacent slices. The two most valuable parts for Bob are worth the same (6) so he passes. Then the agents choose in the order Carl, Bob, Alice and each obtain 6 units of utility. In the larger cake, Alice cuts three parts worth 8 to her, made of 3, 2 and 2 slices. The leftmost part is most valuable for Bob, so he trims it to make it equal to the middle part. Carl takes the uncut part, which is worth 4 for him. Now, Carl divides the remainder to 3 equal pieces and the agents choose in order: Bob, Alice, Carl. Regardless of how this is done, Carl ends up with at most A more recent protocol, the Recursive Cut and Choose, proposed by Tasnádi (2003), violates resource-monotonicity for the same reason. 4 Here we rely on the assumption that the value measures are private information, otherwise Alice would be prompted to act strategically. 12

13 4.2 Population-monotonicity Population-monotonicity is not applicable to protocols with xed number of agents, such as Cut and Choose and Selfridge-Conway. For symmetry reasons, reversing the direction of how a protocol processes the cake has no consequence on whether the protocol violates population-monotonicity or not. In the next couple of examples the cells of the leaving player are colored gray. Our rst example shows that the Banach-Knaster, Dubins-Spanier and the Even-Paz protocols are not population monotonic. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C Suppose we proceed by the Dubins-Spanier method. When all three agents are present Alice is the rst to stop the knife. Then Bob and Carl are the next cutters in that order. Carl manages to obtain a piece that worth 4 to him. However if Bob is not present then Carl will be the rst to cut and he has to content himself with a piece of value 3. Notice that the Even-Paz method and the Banach-Knaster protocol with order Alice-Bob- Carl produces the same allocations. Thus, neither of these three methods are population-monotonic. Consider now the Fink procedure. This procedure was specically designed with upwards-population-monotonicity in mind: when a new agent joins an existing division, he takes a proportional share from each of the existing agents, so all existing agents are weakly worse o (they all participate in supporting the new agent, which is what PM is all about). However, the Fink procedure is not downwards-pm, as the following example shows: ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C Suppose that initially Alice and Bob use Cut and Choose and Bob is the chooser. He is able to salvage the whole cake according to his own evaluation. Now they divide their pieces into three equal parts, and Carl gets to choose one slice from each of them. Hence, Bob ends up with a piece worth at least 8 for him. But if Alice leaves, then Bob and Carl have to redivide the cake using Cut and Choose. Then, no matter who cuts, Bob ends up with only 6. The above example seemingly contradicts our claim that upwards-pm implies downwards-pm and vice versa for single valued solutions. However 13

14 there is a subtle dierence here. The Fink procedure is based on a predened order of the agents, and it is only upwards monotonic if the new agent is the last in the order. An alternative explanation is to treat the Fink rule as a set-valued rule, which returns n! possible allocations, for all n! possible orderings of the agents. Under this denition, the Fink rule is upwards-pm, but not downwards-pm as shown in the example. 4.3 Weak Pareto-optimality It is a well-known fact that the classical protocols that we discuss here are not Pareto-optimal. Now we show that with the exception of Cut and Choose they are not even weakly Pareto-optimal. In the following example the Banach-Knaster, Dubins-Spanier and Even-Paz protocols coincide. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C Alice gets the rst slice as it composes 1/3 of her cake value, while Bob and Carl perform a Cut and Choose on the rest of the cake. The table on the right presents an alternative allocation (still with connected pieces) which is strictly better for all agents. The Fink method is not contiguous, hence we can obtain an improvement by composing the pieces from more slices. ˆv A ˆv B ɛ ˆv A ˆv B ɛ For two agents the Fink method proceeds as the Cut and Choose: Alice cuts in the middle and Bob chooses the piece on the right. The second cake is a Pareto-improvement with four slices where every agent is strictly better o. The same example shows that the Cut and Choose is not WPO for additive utilities. However it is a contiguous protocol, thus it makes sense to investigate whether we could improve it with connected pieces. Lemma 4.1. The Cut and Choose method is weakly Pareto-optimal whenever the agents have connected utilities. Proof. Suppose Alice cuts at point x [0, c] and Bob chooses. The cake is divided into the left piece (L) and the right piece (R). Without loss of 14

15 generality we may assume that Alice receives the left piece. Alice's utility can be improved in only two ways: (a) Cut at some point x > x and give the left piece to Alice. But then Bob would receive R R, which obviously cannot be strictly better than R. (b) Cut at some point x < x and give Alice the right piece R R. Then Bob receives L L. Since Bob preferred R to L he did not gain utility by this swap. So it is impossible to strictly increase the utility of Alice and Bob simultaneously. Finally we show that the Selfridge-Conway does not satisfy WPO either. Consider the following cake. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C Alice cuts the cake into three equal parts. Since the two most valuable slices have equal value for Bob he passes. The agents choose in the Carl-Bob- Alice order and obtain the pieces shown by the table on the left. However, as the table on the right shows, there is an allocation where every agent is strictly better o. 5 Additive Utilities In this section we assume that for every agent, the utility of a piece is just that agent's value measure of that piece, regardless of whether the piece is connected or not. With additive utilities, there are several Pareto-optimal fair division rules satisfying monotonicity axioms. 5.1 Leximin-optimal divisions: PO+PM Lexicographic optimization as a solution concept is used in various elds of fair division (Moulin, 2004). Dubins and Spanier (1961) were the rst to employ it in a cake-cutting setting. Later, Dall'Aglio (2001); Dall'Aglio and Hill (2003); Dall'Aglio and Di Luca (2012) presented various properties and approximation algorithms for nding such leximin divisions (they call such divisions Dubins-Spanier-optimal ). The leximin idea is simple: First we narrow down the solution set to divisions that maximize the utility of the poorest agent. Then among those solutions that satisfy this criterion, we select those which maximize the utility of the second poorest agent. We repeat this process with the third, fourth, 15

16 etc. poorest agent. To introduce this concept formally rst we dene lexicographical ordering of real vectors. We say that vector y R n is lexicographically greater than x R n (denoted by x y) if x y and there exists a number 1 j n such that x i = y i if i < j and x j < y j. Denition 5.1. (a) For a cake division X, dene the relative-leximin-welfare vector as a vector of length n which contains the relative values of the agents under division X in a non-decreasing order. (b) A cake division Y is said to be relative-leximin-better than X if the relative-leximin-welfare vector of Y is lexicographically greater than the relative-leximin-welfare vector of X. (c) A cake division X is called relative-leximin-optimal if no other division is relative-leximin-better than X. (d) We dene the relative-leximin division rule as the rule that returns all relative-leximin-optimal divisions of the cake. The terms absolute-leximin-welfare vector, absolute-leximin-better and absoluteleximin-optimal and the absolute-leximin division rule are dened analogously. Example 5.1. In the following cake, the absolute-leximin division rule splits the leftmost slice between Alice and Bob, giving each of them 6. The rightmost slice is given to Carl. Thus, the absolute-leximin-optimal vector is (6,6,9). The relative value vector of the above division is (6/12, 6/12, 9/30). ˆv A 12 0 ˆv B 12 0 ˆv C 21 9 The corresponding relative-leximin welfare vector is (9/30, 6/12, 6/12) = (3/10, 1/2, 1/2), which is not optimal. The relative-leximin rule divides the leftmost slice between all three agents, giving 1/6 to Carl (absolute value 3.5) and 5/12 to Alice and Bob (absolute value 5). The rightmost slice is given to Carl. The relative-leximin-optimal vector is (5/12, 5/12, 5/12). Dubins and Spanier (1961) use the compactness of the space of valuematrices to prove that leximin-optimal cake divisions always exist. The proof is equally valid for absolute and relative leximin-optimal divisions. Hence, both the absolute- and the relative- leximin division rules are well-dened. The leximin rules are closely related to the equitable rules presented in Subsection 6.3. The relations between them are explored by Dall'Aglio 16

17 (2001). In particular, he proves that the smallest value that an agent receives in a leximin-optimal division is equal to the max-equitable value. This means that a leximin-optimal division is a Pareto-improvement of a maxequitable division. In fact, it is a Pareto-optimal improvement. Lemma 5.1. The absolute- and the relative-leximin division rules are both Pareto-optimal. Proof. By denition, if a division Y Pareto-dominates a division X, then both the absolute and the relative leximin-welfare vectors of Y are larger than those of X. Given a division X, we say that agent i is relatively-poorer than agent j if v i (X i ) < v j (X j ) and relatively-richer if v i (X i ) > v j (X j ). We say that i is weakly-relatively-poorer than j if v i (X i ) v j (X j ) and weakly-relativelyricher if v i (X i ) v j (X j ). The terms (weakly-)absolutely-poorer and (weakly- )absolutely-richer are dened analogously based on the absolute values ˆv i, ˆv j. Lemma 5.2. For every absolute/relative-leximin-optimal division X, if agent j is strictly absolutely/relatively poorer than agent i then agent j believes that the piece of agent i is worthless: ˆv j (X i ) = v j (X i ) = 0. Proof. If this were not the case, then we could take a small bit of X i and give it to agent j, thus achieving an absolute/relative-leximin-better division. But this contradicts the leximin-optimality of X. In Example 5.1, in case of the absolute-leximin-optimal division, Carl is absolutely-richer than Alice and Bob, and indeed his share is worthless for both of them. Suppose X is an old division and Y is a new division of the same cake. We say that an agent i conceded a slice to agent j if there is a positive slice that belonged to agent i in X and belongs to agent j in Y (in other words, X i Y j has a positive Lebesgue-measure). If X and Y are both absolute/relativeleximin-optimal, then by Pareto-optimality, X i Y j has positive value to both the agent who concedes the slice (i) and the recipient (j). Hence, we have the following corollary of Lemma 5.2, which is true both for relative- and absolute-values: Corollary 5.1. Let X and Y be two leximin-optimal divisions. If, when switching from X to Y, agent i conceded a slice to agent j, then in division X, agent i is weakly-poorer than j, and in division Y, agent i is weakly-richer than j. 17

18 Lemma 5.3. The absolute and the relative leximin division rules are essentially single-valued. Proof. The proof is the same for the absolute and the relative leximin rules, so the adjectives are omitted. Suppose X and Y are two dierent leximin-optimal divisions. By switching from X to Y, some agents may have lost value; call these agents unlucky. Similarly, call the agents who gained value lucky. We are going to prove that there are neither unlucky nor lucky agents; this implies that all agents have exactly the same value in both divisions. Suppose by contradiction that agent i is unlucky. Then, he must have conceded a slice to at least one other agent, say j. By Corollary 5.1, i is weakly-poorer than j in X and weakly-richer in Y. But this means that j is also unlucky. So, all slices conceded by unlucky agents are held by other unlucky agents. Suppose the unlucky agents take back all the slices that they conceded. This has no eect on the lucky agents, but strictly increases the value of the unlucky agents, since they now have at least the value that they had in X. But this contradicts the optimality of Y. Hence, there are no unlucky agents. If Y had a lucky agent without having any unlucky agent that would contradict the optimality of X. Since X and Y were arbitrary leximin-optimal divisions it follows that all leximin-optimal divisions have the same value vector. Lemma 5.4. The absolute- and relative-leximin division rules are populationmonotonic. Proof. Again the proof is the same for the absolute and the relative leximin rules. Thanks to Lemma 5.3 it is sucient to prove downwards-pm. Let X be a leximin-optimal division of C. Suppose that agent i leaves and abandons his share X i. So X is now a division of C \ X i among the agents N \ {i}. If X i is divided arbitrarily among N \ {i}, the result is X +, a division of C which is weakly leximin-better than X. Let Y be a leximinoptimal division of C among N \ {i}. Y is weakly leximin-better than X + and hence weakly leximin-better than X. The rest of the proof is very similar to the proof of Lemma 5.3. Call the agents that lost value in the move from X to Y, unlucky. Suppose by contradiction that agent i is unlucky. Then he must have conceded a slice to an agent j, who must also be unlucky. All slices conceded by unlucky agents, are held by other unlucky agents. If those took back all the slices that they conceded, then all of them would be strictly better o while the lucky ones would remain unaected. This contradicts the optimality of Y. Hence there are no unlucky agents and PM is proved. 18

19 The following subsections are devoted to uncovering the main dierences between the absolute- and relative- leximin rules Absolute-leximin rule: PO+PM+RM Theorem 5.1. The absolute-leximin division rule is Pareto-optimal, populationmonotonic and resource-monotonic. Proof. PO follows from Lemma 5.1 and PM from Lemma 5.4. The proof of RM is essentially the same as of 5.4. The cake enlargement can be treated as a piece that was acquired from an agent who left the scene. 5 Unfortunately, the absolute-leximin rule is not PROP. For instance, in Example 5.1, the absolute-leximin-optimal division gives Carl a value of 9, which is only 3 of his total cake value. Hence it is also not envy-free Relative-leximin rule: PO+PM+PROP Theorem 5.2. The relative-leximin division rule is proportional, Paretooptimal and population-monotonic. Proof. PO follows from Lemma 5.1 and PM from Lemma 5.4. PROP holds because proportional divisions exist. The relative-leximinwelfare of a proportional division is at least ( 1,..., 1 ), hence the optimal n n relative-leximin-welfare vector must be at least ( 1,..., 1 ). n n Example 5.2. The following cake shows that the relative-leximin rule is not RM. The largest value that can be given to both Alice and Bob is 9. ˆv A ˆv B ˆv C ˆv D ˆv E Hence, in the smaller cake, the optimal relative-leximin-welfare vector is (9/18, 9/18, 10/18, 10/18, 10/18). It is attained by halving the two leftmost 5 Note that this argument does not work for the relative-leximin division rule, from essentially the same reason as in Theorem 6.3. It is possible that the relative-leximinoptimal division of the enlarged cake is lexicographically smaller than the relative-leximinoptimal division of the smaller cake. 19

20 slices between Alice and Bob, and giving the three slices at their right to Carl, David and Eve, in that order. In the larger cake, the largest value that can be given to Carl, David and Eve from the additional slice at the right is 6. So the largest value that can be given to them from the four rightmost slices is 16. However, the total cake value has doubled for them. Hence, if Alice and Bob keep their share of 9, the relative-leximin-welfare vector changes to 16/36, 16/36, 16/36, 9/18, 9/18. Note that Alice and Bob are now relatively-richer than Carl, David and Eve, and their pieces have a positive value for them. Thus, by Lemma 5.2, the division in which Alice and Bob keep their current shares cannot be relative-leximin-optimal. Remark 5.1. The equitable and leximin rules are closely related to the egalitarian-equivalent solution of Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975). It is known that this rule is population-monotonic in other division problems (e.g. Moulin (2004), chapter 7). Above we extended this result to cake-cutting. Remark 5.2. Instead of leximin principle, we could have used another welfare-optimization criterion such as the utilitarian criterion - maximizing the sum of utilities. The absolute- and relative-utilitarian rules are both Pareto-optimal and population-monotonic, and absolute-utilitarian is also resource-monotonic. However, in contrast to our leximin rules, they are not essentially-single-valued and not proportional. Remark 5.3. The leximin rules are not envy-free. Examples can be found in Dall'Aglio and Hill (2003). 5.2 Nash-optimal divisions: EF+PROP+PO+PM+RM The Nash-welfare of a division X is the product of the values of the agents: n v i (X i ) i=1 It is named after the bargaining solution of Nash (1950). The Nash-optimal division rule selects all the divisions in which the Nashwelfare is maximal. Such divisions exist by the Dubins-Spanier compactness theorem (Dubins and Spanier, 1961). 6 6 In the denition of Nash welfare, it is irrelevant whether absolute or relative values are used, since the product of absolute values is maximized if and only if the product of relative values is maximized. 20

21 In general fair division problems, the Nash-optimal rule is considered a compromise between the utilitarian and leximin rules (see e.g. chapter 3 of Moulin (2004)). We found no mentions of this rule in the cake-cutting literature. Surprisingly, this under-represented rule has all the properties that we desire from a division rule except connectivity. Pareto-optimality is obvious. The other properties are proved in a somewhat indirect way: rst, it is proved that a Nash-optimal division is also Competitive Equilibrium with Equal Incomes (CEEI); then, it is proved that any CEEI division is envy-free, population-monotonic and resource-monotonic. Denition 5.2. (Weller, 1985) Let C be a cake and X an allocation of the cake. Let P be a measure on C (called the "price measure") such that P (Z) = 0 when Z is a zero-slice and P (Z) > 0 when Z is a positive-slice. We say that the pair (P, X) is a CEEI if it satises the following conditions: CE: For every agent i, every positive-slice Z i X i and every positiveslice Z C: v i (Z i )/P (Z i ) v i (Z)/P (Z). 7 EI: For every agent i: P (X i ) = 1. CE is Competitive Equilibrium; it says that every agent receives only slices on which his value/price ratio is maximal. EI is Equal Incomes; it says that every agents receives a piece with the same total price. Lemma 5.5. Let X be a Nash-optimal division. Then, there exists a price measure P such that (P, X) is CEEI. Proof. Dene P as follows (Weller, 1985): Z i X i : P (Z i ) = v i(z i ) v i (X i ) Because proportional divisions exist, the optimal Nash-welfare is necessarily positive. Hence, all agents have a strictly positive value in X, so P is well-dened. The value of P on other subsets of C, that are not contained in any X i, can be easily calculated based on the additivity of P. Note that, by the non-atomicity of the v i, the measure P is also nonatomic and the price of zero-slices is 0. Moreover, since X is Nash-optimal, it is Pareto-optimal. Hence, v i (Z i ) is positive when Z i is a positive-slice and the same is true for P (Z i ). The pair (P, X) clearly satises the EI condition, since by denition P (X i ) = v i (X i )/v i (X i ) = 1. 7 Again it does not matter whether absolute or relative values are used, since only values of the same agent are compared. 21

22 It remains to prove that (P, X) satises the CE condition. Suppose by contradiction that CE is not satised. This means that, for some agent i, there is a positive-slice Z i X i and another positive-slice Z C such that: v i (Z i) P (Z i ) < v i(z) P (Z) Note that, by denition of P, the left-hand side of the above inequality is independent of Z i and always equals to v i (X i ). The subset Z can be written as a disjoint union of n subsets: Z = n j=1z j, such that for every j, Z j = Z X j. Hence: v i (X i ) < v i(z) P (Z) = We claim that there exists a k such that n j=1 v i(z j ) n j=1 P (Z j). v i (X i ) < v i(z k ) P (Z k ). (1) By contradiction, suppose that v i (X i ) v i (Z j )/P (Z j ) is true for every j N. Then we get a contradiction with n j=1 v i (X i ) < v i(z j ) n n j=1 P (Z j) j=1 v i(x i )P (Z j ) n j=1 P (Z = v i (X i ). j) So let k be an index for which (1) holds. We now prove that the Nash-welfare (the product of values) can be increased by taking some of Z k from agent k and giving it to agent i; this contradicts the assumption that the division X is Nash-optimal. Because Z k X k, we can apply the denition of P (Z k ) = v k (Z k )/v k (X k ). After some rearrangement, we get: v i (Z k ) v k (X k ) > v i (X i ) v k (Z k ) Hence, there exists a small positive value ɛ 1 such that: 0 < ɛ < v i(z k ) v k (X k ) v i (X i ) v k (Z k ) v i (Z k ) v k (Z k ) By Dubins and Spanier (1961); Stromquist and Woodall (1985), there exists a subset of Z k whose relative value, for both agent i and agent k, is exactly ɛ. Take this subset from agent k and give it to agent i. The new values of these two agents are now: 22

23 The product of the new values is: v k = v k (X k ) ɛ v k (Z k ) v i = v i (X i ) + ɛ v i (Z k ) v k v i = v k (X k ) v i (X i )+ɛ [v i (Z k ) v k (X k ) v i (X i ) v k (Z k ) ɛ (v i (Z k ) v k (Z k ))] By the selection of ɛ, the bracketed term in the right-hand side is positive. Hence: v k v i > v k (X k ) v i (X i ) The values of other agents have not changed. Hence, the Nash-welfare in the division X is not maximal - a contradiction. Example 5.3. In the following cake: ˆv A ˆv B The Nash-optimal solution gives the two central slices to Bob and the four peripheral slices to Alice. The Nash-welfare is 8*8=64. This is also a CEEI allocation, when the price of a central slice is 1/2 and the price of a peripheral slice is 1/4. Lemma 5.6. Every CEEI allocation is envy-free. Proof. Substituting the EI condition into the CE condition yields that for every i, j: v i (X i ) v i (X j ). We are now going to prove that the CEEI rule the rule which returns all CEEI divisions is both essentially-single-valued and monotonic. Let (P, X) be a CEEI on the cake C and (Q, Y ) a CEEI on an enlarged cake C E. By denition of CEEI, the price measures P and Q are absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure. Thus, they have Radon-Nikodym derivatives with respect to the Lebesgue measure. Call them p, q, such that for every slice Z C: P (Z) = p(x)dx ; Q(Z) = q(x)dx. x Z x Z 23

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra

More information

Lecture 12. Applications to Algorithmic Game Theory & Computational Social Choice. CSC Allan Borodin & Nisarg Shah 1

Lecture 12. Applications to Algorithmic Game Theory & Computational Social Choice. CSC Allan Borodin & Nisarg Shah 1 Lecture 12 Applications to Algorithmic Game Theory & Computational Social Choice CSC2420 - Allan Borodin & Nisarg Shah 1 A little bit of game theory CSC2420 - Allan Borodin & Nisarg Shah 2 Recap: Yao s

More information

8. Cake cutting. proportionality and envy-freeness. price of fairness. approximate envy-freeness. Cake cutting 8-1

8. Cake cutting. proportionality and envy-freeness. price of fairness. approximate envy-freeness. Cake cutting 8-1 Cake cutting 8-1 8. Cake cutting proportionality and envy-freeness price of fairness approximate envy-freeness Cake cutting model a cake is the interval [0; 1] a peice of cake is X [0; 1] each of n agents

More information

The efficiency of fair division

The efficiency of fair division The efficiency of fair division Ioannis Caragiannis Christos Kaklamanis Panagiotis Kanellopoulos Maria Kyropoulou Research Academic Computer Technology Institute and Department of Computer Engineering

More information

2 A 3-Person Discrete Envy-Free Protocol

2 A 3-Person Discrete Envy-Free Protocol Envy-Free Discrete Protocols Exposition by William Gasarch 1 Introduction Whenever we say something like Alice has a piece worth α we mean it s worth α TO HER. The term biggest piece means most valuable

More information

Envy-free cake divisions cannot be found by finite protocols

Envy-free cake divisions cannot be found by finite protocols Envy-free cake divisions cannot be found by finite protocols Walter Stromquist Department of Mathematics and Statistics Swarthmore College, Swarthmore, PA 19081 wstromq1@swarthmore.edu Submitted: Oct 21,

More information

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Axiomatic bargaining. theory Axiomatic bargaining theory Objective: To formulate and analyse reasonable criteria for dividing the gains or losses from a cooperative endeavour among several agents. We begin with a non-empty set of

More information

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment Umut Mert Dur North Carolina State University Thayer Morrill North Carolina State University May 2017 Abstract Top Trading Cycles

More information

Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice

Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice Ron Cytron (Computer Science) Maggie Penn (Political Science) Lecture 1: Introduction 1 Some things to watch for on these slides Definition 1 definition: A concept that

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation

Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation Elliot Anshelevich and Bugra Caskurlu Computer Science Department, RPI, 110 8th Street, Troy, NY 12180 {eanshel,caskub}@cs.rpi.edu Abstract.

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

The Adjusted Winner Procedure : Characterizations and Equilibria

The Adjusted Winner Procedure : Characterizations and Equilibria The Adjusted Winner Procedure : Characterizations and Equilibria Simina Brânzei Aarhus University, Denmark Joint with Haris Aziz, Aris Filos-Ratsikas, and Søren Frederiksen Background Adjusted Winner:

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information

Fair Public Decision Making

Fair Public Decision Making 1 Fair Public Decision Making VINCENT CONITZER, Duke University RUPERT FREEMAN, Duke University NISARG SHAH, Harvard University We generalize the classic problem of fairly allocating indivisible goods

More information

Truth, Justice, and Cake Cutting

Truth, Justice, and Cake Cutting Truth, Justice, and Cake Cutting Yiling Chen John K. Lai David C. Parkes Ariel D. Procaccia Superman: I m here to fight for truth, justice, and the American way. Lois Lane: You re gonna wind up fighting

More information

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems

Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Resource-Monotonicity for House Allocation Problems Lars Ehlers Bettina Klaus This Version: March 2004 Abstract We study a simple model of assigning indivisible objects (e.g., houses, jobs, offices, etc.)

More information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Ignacio Montes, Enrique Miranda, Susana Montes University of Oviedo, Dep. of Statistics and Operations Research. Abstract Stochastic dominance, which is

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Can everyone benefit from innovation? Can everyone benefit from innovation? Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi June 16, 2017 Abstract We study a resource allocation problem with variable technologies, and ask if there is an allocation

More information

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Elliot Anshelevich Bugra Caskurlu Received: January 2010 / Accepted: Abstract We study the survivable

More information

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment

The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment The Impossibility of Restricting Tradeable Priorities in School Assignment Umut Mert Dur North Carolina State University Thayer Morrill North Carolina State University February 2016 Abstract Ecient school

More information

Optimal Envy-Free Cake-Cutting

Optimal Envy-Free Cake-Cutting Optimal Envy-Free Cake-Cutting A thesis presented by Yuga Cohler to Computer Science in partial fulfillment of the honors requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts Harvard College Cambridge, Massachusetts

More information

Fairness Criteria for Fair Division of Indivisible Goods

Fairness Criteria for Fair Division of Indivisible Goods Sylvain Bouveret LIG (STeamer) Ensimag / Grenoble INP Michel Lemaître Formerly Onera Toulouse Séminaire de l équipe ROSP du laboratoire G-SCOP Grenoble, March 24, 2016 Introduction A fair division problem...

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Fair allocation of indivisible goods

Fair allocation of indivisible goods Fair allocation of indivisible goods Gabriel Sebastian von Conta Technische Universitt Mnchen mrgabral@gmail.com November 17, 2015 Gabriel Sebastian von Conta (TUM) Chapter 12 November 17, 2015 1 / 44

More information

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement Shiran Rachmilevitch September 23, 2012 Abstract A unique bargaining solution satisfies restricted monotonicity, independence of

More information

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Ioannis Caragiannis RACTI & Department of Computer Engineering and Informatics University of Patras, Greece caragian@ceid.upatras.gr

More information

Two Desirable Fairness Concepts for Allocation of Indivisible Objects under Ordinal Preferences

Two Desirable Fairness Concepts for Allocation of Indivisible Objects under Ordinal Preferences Two Desirable Fairness Concepts for Allocation of Indivisible Objects under Ordinal Preferences HARIS AZIZ and SERGE GASPERS and SIMON MACKENZIE and TOBY WALSH Data61 and UNSW Fair allocation of indivisible

More information

Two-Sided Matching. Terence Johnson. December 1, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Two-Sided Matching December 1, / 47

Two-Sided Matching. Terence Johnson. December 1, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Two-Sided Matching December 1, / 47 Two-Sided Matching Terence Johnson University of Notre Dame December 1, 2017 Terence Johnson (ND) Two-Sided Matching December 1, 2017 1 / 47 Markets without money What do you do when you can t use money

More information

Equilibrium Analysis in Cake Cutting

Equilibrium Analysis in Cake Cutting Equilibrium Analysis in Cake Cutting Simina Brânzei and Peter Bro Miltersen Department of Computer Science Aarhus University, Denmark {simina,bromille}@cs.au.dk ABSTRACT Cake cutting is a fundamental model

More information

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences Daniela Saban and Jay Sethuraman March 7, 2014 Abstract We consider the problem of allocating m objects to n agents. Each agent has unit demand,

More information

Optimal Proportional Cake Cutting with Connected Pieces

Optimal Proportional Cake Cutting with Connected Pieces Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence Optimal Proportional Cake Cutting with Connected Pieces Xiaohui Bei Institute for Interdisciplinary Information Sciences Tsinghua

More information

Setting Lower Bounds on Truthfulness

Setting Lower Bounds on Truthfulness Setting Lower Bounds on Truthfulness Ahuva Mu alem Michael Schapira Abstract We present and discuss general techniques for proving inapproximability results for truthful mechanisms. We make use of these

More information

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5 Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5 Eric Pacuit and Rohit Parikh August 17, 2007 Eric Pacuit and Rohit Parikh: Introduction to Formal Epistemology, Lecture 5 1 Plan for the Course Introduction,

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

Degradable Agreement in the Presence of. Byzantine Faults. Nitin H. Vaidya. Technical Report #

Degradable Agreement in the Presence of. Byzantine Faults. Nitin H. Vaidya. Technical Report # Degradable Agreement in the Presence of Byzantine Faults Nitin H. Vaidya Technical Report # 92-020 Abstract Consider a system consisting of a sender that wants to send a value to certain receivers. Byzantine

More information

Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints

Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints Battal Doğan Serhat Doğan Kemal Yıldız May 14, 2017 Abstract In several matching markets, in order to achieve diversity, agents priorities are allowed

More information

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University {kenshin,sandholm}@cscmuedu Abstract The Muller-Satterthwaite

More information

Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities

Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities Online Appendix to Strategy-proof tie-breaking in matching with priorities Lars Ehlers Alexander Westkamp December 12, 2017 Section 1 contains the omitted proofs of Lemma 5, Lemma 6 and Lemma 7 Subsection

More information

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) Contents 1 Vector Spaces 1 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space.................................. 1 1.2 Subspaces...................................................

More information

Ahlswede Khachatrian Theorems: Weighted, Infinite, and Hamming

Ahlswede Khachatrian Theorems: Weighted, Infinite, and Hamming Ahlswede Khachatrian Theorems: Weighted, Infinite, and Hamming Yuval Filmus April 4, 2017 Abstract The seminal complete intersection theorem of Ahlswede and Khachatrian gives the maximum cardinality of

More information

Online Appendixes for \A Theory of Military Dictatorships"

Online Appendixes for \A Theory of Military Dictatorships May 2009 Online Appendixes for \A Theory of Military Dictatorships" By Daron Acemoglu, Davide Ticchi and Andrea Vindigni Appendix B: Key Notation for Section I 2 (0; 1): discount factor. j;t 2 f0; 1g:

More information

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY by arxiv:170109087v1 [mathca] 9 Jan 017 MAGNUS D LADUE 0 Abstract In [1] Grossman Turett define the Cantor game In [] Matt Baker proves several results

More information

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions Department Discussion Paper DDP0702 ISSN 1914-2838 Department of Economics Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

More information

What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems?

What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems? Markets without money What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems? Matching: heterosexual men and women marrying in a small town, students matching to universities, workers to jobs where

More information

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad Unlinked llocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One ad Chiaki Hara Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge Institute of Economic Research, Hitotsubashi University pril 16,

More information

Towards a General Theory of Non-Cooperative Computation

Towards a General Theory of Non-Cooperative Computation Towards a General Theory of Non-Cooperative Computation (Extended Abstract) Robert McGrew, Ryan Porter, and Yoav Shoham Stanford University {bmcgrew,rwporter,shoham}@cs.stanford.edu Abstract We generalize

More information

COSTLY STATE VERIFICATION - DRAFT

COSTLY STATE VERIFICATION - DRAFT COSTLY STTE VERIFICTION - DRFT SIMCH BRKI I am writing this note in order to explain under what circumstances debt contracts are optimal; more importantly, to explain why debt contracts are optimal. For

More information

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games Deeparnab Chakrabarty, Gagan Goel 2, Vijay V. Vazirani 2, Lei Wang 2 and Changyuan Yu 3 Department of Combinatorics and Optimization, University

More information

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Iian B. Smythe October 20, 2015 Abstract Does there exist a reasonable method of voting that when presented with three or more alternatives avoids the undue

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

An Algorithm For Super Envy-Free Cake Division

An Algorithm For Super Envy-Free Cake Division Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications 239, 175-179 (1999) Article ID jrnaa. 1999.6581, available online at http://www.idealibrary.coni on I DE hl3 An Algorithm For Super Envy-Free Cake Division

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 Complete Characterization of Functions Satisfying the Conditions of Arrow s Theorem Elchanan Mossel and Omer Tamuz arxiv:0910.2465v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 April 15, 2011 Abstract Arrow s theorem implies

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002)

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002) A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, 811-823, (2002) Nir Dagan Oscar Volij Eyal Winter August 20, 2001 Abstract We characterize the Nash bargaining

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation

Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation Noname manuscript No. will be inserted by the editor) Exact and Approximate Equilibria for Optimal Group Network Formation Elliot Anshelevich Bugra Caskurlu Received: December 2009 / Accepted: Abstract

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Klaus Nehring Clemens Puppe January 2017 **** Preliminary Version ***** Not to be quoted without permission from the

More information

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005 SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION By Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson December 2005 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION AER NO. 1542 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE

More information

What are Axioms of Set Theory?

What are Axioms of Set Theory? Set-theorists use the term Axiom (of Set Theory) quite freely. What do they mean by it? Examples Axioms of ZFC: Axiom of Extensionality Pairing Axiom Separation Axiom Union Axiom Powerset Axiom Axiom of

More information

Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults. a System Can Withstand Without Repairs. Cambridge, MA 02139

Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults. a System Can Withstand Without Repairs. Cambridge, MA 02139 Upper and Lower Bounds on the Number of Faults a System Can Withstand Without Repairs Michel Goemans y Nancy Lynch z Isaac Saias x Laboratory for Computer Science Massachusetts Institute of Technology

More information

Proportional Division Exposition by William Gasarch

Proportional Division Exposition by William Gasarch 1 Introduction Proportional Division Exposition by William Gasarch Whenever we say something like Alice has a piece worth 1/ we mean worth 1/ TO HER. Lets say we want Alice, Bob, Carol, to split a cake

More information

Fairly Allocating Many Goods with Few Queries

Fairly Allocating Many Goods with Few Queries Fairly Allocating Many Goods with Few Queries Hoon Oh Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University Ariel D. Procaccia Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University Warut Suksompong Department

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems

Lecture 4. 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems CSCI699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Lecture 4 Lecturer: Shaddin Dughmi Scribes: Haifeng Xu,Reem Alfayez 1 Examples of Mechanism Design Problems Example 1: Single Item Auctions. There is a single

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Two-Player Kidney Exchange Game

Two-Player Kidney Exchange Game Two-Player Kidney Exchange Game Margarida Carvalho INESC TEC and Faculdade de Ciências da Universidade do Porto, Portugal margarida.carvalho@dcc.fc.up.pt Andrea Lodi DEI, University of Bologna, Italy andrea.lodi@unibo.it

More information

Games and Economic Behavior

Games and Economic Behavior Games and Economic Behavior 77 (2013) 284 297 Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect Games and Economic Behavior www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Truth, justice, and cake cutting Yiling Chen a,johnk.lai

More information

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about 0368.4170: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen Lecture 7 02 December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about Two-Player zero-sum games (min-max theorem) Mixed

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION. Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION. Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar Working Paper 12804 http://www.nber.org/papers/w12804 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts

More information

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Mariagiovanna Baccara Leeat Yariv August 19, 2012 1 Introduction In this Appendix we study the information sharing application analyzed

More information

Exhaustive Classication of Finite Classical Probability Spaces with Regard to the Notion of Causal Up-to-n-closedness

Exhaustive Classication of Finite Classical Probability Spaces with Regard to the Notion of Causal Up-to-n-closedness Exhaustive Classication of Finite Classical Probability Spaces with Regard to the Notion of Causal Up-to-n-closedness Michaª Marczyk, Leszek Wro«ski Jagiellonian University, Kraków 16 June 2009 Abstract

More information

Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series

Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series Estimates for probabilities of independent events and infinite series Jürgen Grahl and Shahar evo September 9, 06 arxiv:609.0894v [math.pr] 8 Sep 06 Abstract This paper deals with finite or infinite sequences

More information

A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation

A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation Krzysztof R. Apt and Andreas Witzel Abstract We propose an abstract approach to coalition formation by focusing on partial preference relations between partitions

More information

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 David Pérez-Castrillo 2 Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona David Wettstein 3 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev April 2005 1 We gratefully

More information

Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson. April, This Revision: January Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior.

Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson. April, This Revision: January Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior. The Stability of Hedonic Coalition Structures Anna Bogomolnaia and Matthew O. Jackson April, 1998 This Revision: January 2001 Forthcoming: Games and Economic Behavior Abstract We consider the partitioning

More information

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2011 Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach Bargaining problem Nash s (1950) work is the starting point for formal bargaining

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie**

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie** Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie** Published as: John P. Conley and Simon Wilkie Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution

More information

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting 1

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting 1 Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting 1 Ioannis Caragiannis, Dimitris Kalaitzis, and Evangelos Markakis Abstract We consider approval voting elections in which each

More information

Richard DiSalvo. Dr. Elmer. Mathematical Foundations of Economics. Fall/Spring,

Richard DiSalvo. Dr. Elmer. Mathematical Foundations of Economics. Fall/Spring, The Finite Dimensional Normed Linear Space Theorem Richard DiSalvo Dr. Elmer Mathematical Foundations of Economics Fall/Spring, 20-202 The claim that follows, which I have called the nite-dimensional normed

More information

Merging and splitting endowments. in object assignment problems. Nanyang Bu, Siwei Chen, and William Thomson. Working Paper No.

Merging and splitting endowments. in object assignment problems. Nanyang Bu, Siwei Chen, and William Thomson. Working Paper No. Merging splitting endowments in object assignment problems Nanyang Bu, Siwei Chen, William Thomson Working Paper No 587 December 2014 Merging splitting endowments in object assignment problems Nanyang

More information

An Equivalence result in School Choice

An Equivalence result in School Choice An Equivalence result in School Choice Jay Sethuraman May 2009 Abstract The main result of the paper is a proof of the equivalence of single and multiple lottery mechanisms for the problem of allocating

More information

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory 1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory 1.1 Basic definitions What we have seen from all these examples, is that we take a bargaining situation and we can describe the utilities possibility set that arises from

More information

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence

Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence Other-Regarding Preferences: Theory and Evidence June 9, 2009 GENERAL OUTLINE Economic Rationality is Individual Optimization and Group Equilibrium Narrow version: Restrictive Assumptions about Objective

More information

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101 3 Tournaments 3.1 Motivation General idea Firms can use competition between agents for 1 incentive and 2 selection purposes We mainly focus on incentives 3 / 101 Main characteristics Agents fulll similar

More information

On the Complexity of Computing an Equilibrium in Combinatorial Auctions

On the Complexity of Computing an Equilibrium in Combinatorial Auctions On the Complexity of Computing an Equilibrium in Combinatorial Auctions Shahar Dobzinski Hu Fu Robert Kleinberg April 8, 2014 Abstract We study combinatorial auctions where each item is sold separately

More information

Recap Social Choice Functions Fun Game Mechanism Design. Mechanism Design. Lecture 13. Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 1

Recap Social Choice Functions Fun Game Mechanism Design. Mechanism Design. Lecture 13. Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 1 Mechanism Design Lecture 13 Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Social Choice Functions 3 Fun Game 4 Mechanism Design Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 2 Notation N is the

More information

Matching. Terence Johnson. April 17, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Matching April 17, / 41

Matching. Terence Johnson. April 17, University of Notre Dame. Terence Johnson (ND) Matching April 17, / 41 Matching Terence Johnson University of Notre Dame April 17, 2018 Terence Johnson (ND) Matching April 17, 2018 1 / 41 Markets without money What do you do when you can t use money to solve your problems?

More information

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero Chapter Limits of Sequences Calculus Student: lim s n = 0 means the s n are getting closer and closer to zero but never gets there. Instructor: ARGHHHHH! Exercise. Think of a better response for the instructor.

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

For general queries, contact

For general queries, contact PART I INTRODUCTION LECTURE Noncooperative Games This lecture uses several examples to introduce the key principles of noncooperative game theory Elements of a Game Cooperative vs Noncooperative Games:

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015 CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS CEWP 7/2015 Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof by Miklós Pintér http://unipub.lib.uni-corvinus.hu/1659 Young s axiomatization of the Shapley value

More information