Expected Utility Theory with Probability Grids and. Preference Formation

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Expected Utility Theory with Probability Grids and. Preference Formation"

Transcription

1 WINPEC Working Paper Series No.E1902 April 2019 Expected Utility Theory with Probability Grids and Preference Formation Mamoru Kaneko Waseda INstitute of Political EConomy Waseda University Tokyo, Japan

2 Expected Utility Theory with Probability Grids and Preference Formation Mamoru Kaneko y March 30, 2019 Abstract We reformulate expected utility theory, from the viewpoint of bounded rationality, by introducing probability grids and a cognitive bound; we restrict permissible probabilities only to decimal (`-ary in general) fractions of nite depths up to a given cognitive bound. We distinguish between measurements of utilities from pure alternatives and their extensions to lotteries involving more risks. Our theory is constructive, from the viewpoint of the decision maker. When a cognitive bound is small, the preference relation involves many incomparabilities, but these diminish as the cognitive bound is is relaxed. Similarly, the EU hypothesis would hold more for a weaker cognitive bound. The main part of the paper is a study of preferences including incomparabilities in cases with nite cogntive bounds; we give representation theorems in terms of a 2-dimensional vector-valued utility functions. We exemplify the theory with one experimental result reported by Kahneman-Tversky. JEL Classi cation Numbers: C72, C79, C91 Key Words: Expected Utility, Measurement of Utility, Bounded Rationality, Probability Grids, Cognitive Bound, Incomparabilities 1 Introduction We reconsider EU theory from the viewpoint of preference formation and of bounded rationality. We restrict permissible probabilities to decimal (`-ary, in general) fractions up to a given cognitive bound ; if is a natural number k, the set of permissible probabilities is given as = k = f 0 1 ; ; :::; k g: The decision maker makes preference comparisons step by step k k k using probabilities with small k to those with larger k 0 to obtain accurate comparisons. The derived preference relation is incomplete in general, but the EU hypothesis holds for some lotteries and would hold more when there is no cognitive bound, i.e., = 1: Our main concern is the case < 1. Since the theory involves various entangled aspects, we rst disentangle them. The concepts of probability grids and cognitive bounds are introduced based on the idea of bounded rationality. This idea can be interpreted in many ways such as bounded logical The author thanks J. J. Kline, P. Wakker, M. Lewandowski, S. Shiba, M. Cohen, O. Shulte, and Y. Rebille for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. In particular, comments given by the two referees improved the paper signi cantly and are greatly appreciated. The author is supported by Grant-in-Aids for Scienti c Research No and No.17H02258, Ministry of Education, Science and Culture. y Waseda University, Tokyo, Japan (mkanekoepi@waseda.jp) 1

3 inference, bounded perception ability, though Simon s [29] original concept meant a relaxation of utility maximization. The mathematical components involved in EU theory are classi ed to two types; object-components used by the decision maker and meta-components used by the outside analyst and possibly by the decision maker himself. The former is primary targets in EU theory, and the latter such as highly complex rational as well as irrational probabilities is added for analytic convenience. A free use of the latter leads to a critique that the theory presumes super rationality (Simon [30]). As a signi cance level for statistical hypothesis testing is typically 5% or 1%; probability values (t = 0; :::; 2 ) are already quite accurate for ordinary people. However, the classical EU t 2 theory starts with the full real number theory and makes no separation between the viewpoints of the decision maker and the outside analyst for available probabilities. This is still a problem of degree, but it would be meaningful if they are separated in some manner. The concepts of probability grids and a cognitive bound make this separation. The set of probability grids up to depth k is given as k = f 0 1 ; ; :::; k g. The decision k k k maker thinks about his preferences with k from a small k to a larger k up to bound ; for example, when = 2; 0 ; 1 ; and 2 are only allowed. This is a constructive approach from the viewpoint of the decision maker in the sense that he nds/forms his own preferences. 1;2 We turn our attention to the development of our constructive EU theory. Constructiveness needs a start; we take a hint from von Neumann-Morgenstern [31]. They divided the motivating argument into the following two, though this separation was not re ected in their development: Step B: measurements of utilities from pure alternatives in terms of probabilities; Step E: extensions of these measurements to lotteries involving more risks. These steps di er in their natures: Step B is to measure a satisfaction, desire, etc. from a pure alternative, while Step E is to extend the measured satisfactions given by Step B to lotteries including more risks. An important di erence is that Step B is to nd the subjective preferences hidden in the mind of the decision maker, while Step E is to extend logically the preferences found in Step B to lotteries with more risks. We develop our theory based on the above two steps and also take two approaches in terms of preferences and utilities; each approach consists of Steps B and E. In this introduction, we focus mainly on the former theory, and we give a brief explanation of the latter. 3 We assume two pure alternatives y and y; called the upper and lower benchmarks; these together with the probability grids k form the benchmark scale B k (y; y) in layer k: In Step B, pure alternatives are measured by this scale. Preferences are constructed in shallow to deeper layers, where preferences are incomplete in the beginning, except for benchmark lotteries as 1 This sounds similar to constructive decision theory in Shafer [27], [28] and in Blume et al. [4]. These authors study Savage s [26] subjective utility/probability theory so as to introduce certain constructive features for decision making. Our theory is constructive more explicitly with the introduction of probability grids and a cognitive bound. The chief di erence is that we formulate how a decision maker nds/forms his own preferences, while they add new constructs like goals or frames that shape the choices of the decision maker. 2 Our concept of probability grids may be interpreted as imprecise probabilities/similarity (cf. Augustin et al. [2], Rubinstein [25]). Imprecision/similarity is de ned as an attribute of a probability/a set of probabilities, allowing all real number probabilities. In our approach, however, probability grids in k are exact; the restriction of probabilities to k expresses imprecision in cognitive acts taken by the decision maker. 3 Our theory is dual to that in terms of certainty equivalent of a lottery (cf. Kontek-Lewandowski [20] and its references). In our method, the set of benchmark lotteries forms a base scale, while the set of monetary amounts is the base scale in the latter (see Section 4.2 in [20]). 2

4 : upper benchmark : lower benchmark Benchmark lotteries Figure 1: Step B with the benchmark scale measurement units, and in deeper layers, more precise preferences may be found. In Fig.1, the benchmark scale for layer k is depicted as the right broken line with dots; x is measured exactly by the scale; y need a more precise scale within. However, z is not done within. Two di erent roles of probability grids appear in Step E for evaluation of a lottery: (i) probability grids used for measurement of a pure alternative in Step B; (ii) probability coe cients to pure alternatives. By these, relevant cognitive depths of lotteries become more complex especially with a nite cognitive bound; this leads to incomparabilities in preferences and some violation of the EU hypothesis. This is central in our development and is closely related to the issue of bounded rationality. Let us illustrate (i) and (ii) via an example. Consider one example with the upper and lower benchmarks y; y; and the third pure alternative y with strict preferences y y y. In Step B, the decision maker looks for a probability so that y is indi erent to a lottery [y; ; y] = y (1 )y with probability for y and 1 for y; this indi erence is denoted by y [y; ; y]: (1) Suppose that this is uniquely determined as = y = : Here, exact measurement of y is successful in layer 2; where Step B is enough here. We have the other source of cognitive depths. Consider lottery d = 25 y; which includes 2 the third pure alternative y. The independence condition of the classical EU theory dictates that because of (1), [y; 83 ; y] is substituted for y in d; and d is reduced to: 2 2 y 75 d = 25 2 y 75 2 y 25 2 [y; 83 2 ; y] 75 2 y = y y: (2) Thus, y is evaluated as being indi erent to [y; 83 ; y] in Step B, but y also has a probability 2 coe cient 25 in d, which is taken into account in Step E. These steps leads to probability 2075 ; which is much more precise than either of and 25 : 2 2 As indicated in (i) and (ii), lottery d = 25 y 75 y has two types of cognitive depths; one 2 2 is simply a probability coe cient 25 and the other is 2 y = 83 from (1). Although d itself is 2 expressed as a lottery of depth 2; the total depths including these two types is 4; which is beyond the cognitive bound = 2: One point is that the resulting probability may be very precise with a relatively small cognitive bound, and the other is that this is intimately related to the EU 3

5 hypothesis. When is small, the EU hypothesis does not typically hold, while it would hold more as is getting larger. The preference formation by Steps B and E is formulated as a form of mathematical induction; Step B is the inductive base and Step E is the inductive step. Step B is spread out to layers of various depths, i.e., the induction base is spread too. These steps are described in Table 1.1: the relation D k for layer k of row B expresses preferences measured in Steps B. In layer k; % k is derived from D k and % k 1 ; the former is a part of the inductive base and the latter is the inductive step. This is a weak form of independence condition : Table 1.1 Layers 0 1 ::: k 1 k ::: B: base relations D 0 D 1 ::: D k 1 D k ::: D # # # # # E : constructed relations % 0! % 1! :::! % k 1! % k! :::! % We also provide another approach in terms of a 2-dimensional vector-valued utility functions h k i k<+1 = h[ k ; k ]i k<+1 and hu k i k<+1 = h[u k ; u k ]i k<+1 with Fishburn s [7] interval order I. In each of Steps B and E, this approach is entirely equivalent to the preference approach, depicted in Table 1.2. This may be interpreted as what von Neumann- Morgenstern [31], p.29 indicated. 4 The approaches in terms of preferences and utilities enable us to view Steps B and E in di erent ways as well as serve di erent analytic tools for studies of incomparabilities/comparabilities involved: Table 1.2 Preference theory Utility theory Step B (B0 to B3) () (Sec.3) Step B (b0 to b3) Extension (Sec.4) Extension (Sec.5) Step E (E0 to E3) () (Sec.5) Step E (e0 to e3) Our theory enjoys a weak form of the expected utility hypothesis. This will be discussed in Section 6. In the case of = 1; restricting our attention to the set of measurable pure alternatives, in Section 7, we show that our theory exhibits a form of the classical EU theory. We provide a further extension of % 1 to have the full form of classical EU theory; this extension involves some unavoidable non-constructive step, which may be interpreted as the criticism of super rationality by Simon [30]. We apply our theory to the Allais paradox, speci cally, to an experimental result from Kahneman-Tversky [14]. We show that the paradoxical results remains when the cognitive bound 3. However, when = 2; the resultant preference relation % is compatible with their experimental result, where incomparabilities play crucial roles in explaining them. A remark is on the relationship between k and exhibiting a layer and a cognitive bound. The former is a variable in our theory and the latter is a parameter of the theory. We talk about the sequences h% k i k<+1 and hu k i k<+1 describing the process of preference formation 4 Aumann [3] and Fishburn [8] considered one-way representation theorem (i.e., the only-if of (3)), dropping completeness. See Fishburn [9] for further studies. Dubra, et al. [6] developed a representation theorem in terms of utility comparisons based on all possible expected utility functions for the relation without completeness. In this literature, incomparabilities are given in the preference relation. In contrast, in our approach, incomparabilities are changing with a cognitive bound and may disappear when there are no cognitive bounds. 4

6 layer to layer up to : Nevertheless, the nal target preferences and utilities are % and u : This remark leads to the view that our theory is a generalization of the classical EU theory, which is discussed in Section 7.1. The paper is organized as follows: Section 2 explains the concept of probability grids and other basic concepts. Section 3 formulates Step B in terms preferences and utilities, and states their equivalence. Section 4 discusses Step E in terms of preferences and Section 5 does it in terms of utilities. Section 6 discusses the measurable/non-measurable lotteries, and shows that the expected utility hypothesis holds for the measurable lotteries. Section 7 discusses the connection from our theory to the classical EU theory. In Section 8, we exemplify our theory with an experimental result in Kahneman-Tversky [14]. Section 9 concludes this paper with comments on further possible studies. Proofs of all the results in each section are given in a separate subsection; only proof of Lemma 2.1 is given in Section. 2 Preliminaries Our theory is about preference formation in the context of EU theory. The classical EU theory is the reference point, but our theory deviates from it in various manners. To have clear relations between the classical EU theory and our development, we rst mention the classical theory (cf. Herstein-Milnor [12], Fishburn []), and then, we start our development. In Section 2.2, we give various basic concepts for our theory and one basic lemma. In Section 2.3, we give de nitions of preferences, indi erences, incomparabilities, and their counterparts in terms of vector-valued utility functions. 2.1 Classical EU theory Let X be a given set of pure alternatives with cardinality jxj 2. A lottery f is a function over X taking real values in [0; 1] with P x2s f(x) = 1 for some nite subset S of X: This subset S is called a support of f: We de ne L [0;1] (X) = ff : f : X! [0; 1] is a lotteryg: The set L [0;1] (X) is uncountable: We de ne compound lotteries: for any f; g 2 L [0;1] (X) and 2 [0; 1]; f (1 )g is a lottery in L [0;1] (X) de ned by (f (1 )g)(x) = f(x) + (1 )g(x) for all x 2 X. Let % E be a binary relation over L [0;1] (X); and we assume NM0 to NM2 on % E : This system is one among various equivalent systems. Axiom NM0 (Complete preordering): % E is a complete and transitive relation on L [0;1] (X): Axiom NM1 (Intermediate value): For any f; g; h 2 L [0;1] (X); if f % E g % E h; then f (1 )h E g for some 2 [0; 1]: Axiom NM2 (Independence): For any f; g; h 2 L [0;1] (X) and 2 (0; 1]; ID1: f E g implies f (1 )h E g (1 )h; ID2: f E g implies f (1 )h E g (1 )h; where the indi erence part and strict preference part of % E are denoted by E and E ; that is, f E g means f % E g & g % E f; and f E g does f % E g & not (g % E f): The following two are the key theorems in the classical EU theory. For a fruitful development of our theory, we should be conscious of how they remain in our theory. 5

7 Theorem 2.1 (Classical EU theorem). A preference relation % E satis es Axioms NM0 to NM2 if and only if there is a function u : X! R so that for any f; g 2 L [0;1] (X); where the expected utility functional E f (u) is de ned as: f % E g if and only if E f (u) E f (u); (3) E f (u) = P x2s f(x)u(x) for each f 2 L [0;1](X) with its support S: (4) Theorem 2.2 (Uniqueness up to A ne transformations). Suppose that % E satis es Axioms NM0 to NM2. If two functions u; v : X! R satisfy (3), then there are two real numbers > 0 and such that u(x) = v(x) + for all x 2 X: In these theorems, preference relation % E is given with Axioms NM0 to NM2. The theory is silent about how a decision maker nds/forms his preferences. As mentioned in Section 1, we consider this question from simple cases to more complex cases, while distinguishing between Steps B and E. In the above axiomatization, these are mixed in NM1 and NM2. We will make a clear-cut distinction between Steps B and E. In these steps, we avoid the existence of a complete preference relation dictated by Axiom NM0. Another salient restriction in our theory is on the available probabilities and is formulated by the concept of probability grids. This allows us to think about his preferences from simpler lotteries to complex ones step by step. The step-by-step consideration collapses in Axioms NM2 and NM3. The system (L [0;1] ; % E ) with Axioms NM0 to NM2 itself is not in the cetral part of our theory, but our theory is closely related to the EU hypothesis that preferences are represented by the expected utility functional E f (u). We will discuss the EU hypothesis time to time, and touch the system (L [0;1] ; % E ) only in Section Probability grids, lotteries, and decompositions Let ` be an integer with ` 2: This ` is the base for describing probability grids; we take ` = in the examples in the paper. The set of probability grids k is de ned as k = f `k : = 0; 1; :::; `kg for any nite k 0: (5) Here, 1 = f ` : = 0; :::; `g is the base set of probability grids for measurement, whereas 0 = f0; 1g is needed for technical completeness. Each k is a nite set, and 1 := [ t<1 t is countably in nite. We use the standard arithmetic rules over 1 ; sum and multiplication are needed We allow reduction by eliminating common factors; for example, is the same as 2 2 : Hence, k k+1 for k = 0; 1; ::: The parameter k is the precision of probabilities that the decision maker uses. We de ne the depth of each 2 1 by: () = k i 2 k k 1 : For example, ( 25 ) = 2 but ( 20 ) = ( ) = 1: The concept of a layer of probability grids up to a given depth k is well de ned. The decision maker thinks about his preferences along probability grids from a shallow layer to a deeper one. We use the standard equality = and strict inequality > over k : Then, trichotomy holds: for any ; 0 2 k ; either > 0 ; = 0 ; or < 0 : (6) 5 See Mendelson [22] for related basic mathematics. 6

8 Each element in k is obtained by taking the weighted sums of elements in k 1 with the equal weights: k = f `P 1 ` t : 1 ; :::; ` 2 k 1 g for any k (1 k < 1): (7) t=1 This is basic for the connection between layer k 1 to the next. A proof of (7) is not given here, but an extension will be given in Lemma 2.1 with a proof given in the Appendix. The union 1 = [ k<1 k is a proper subset of [0; 1] \ Q; where Q is the set of rational numbers. For example, when ` = ; 1 has no recurring decimals, but they are rationals: We also note that 1 depends upon the base `; for example, 1 with ` = 3 has 1 3 ; but 1 with ` = has no element corresponding to 1 3 : For any k < 1; we de ne L k (X) by L k (X) = ff : f is a function from X to k with P x2x f(x) = 1g: (8) We identify each pure alternative x with the lottery having x as its support; so X is regarded as a subset of L k (X): Speci cally, L 0 (X) = X: Since k is a nite set, every f 2 L k (X) has a nite support. Since k k+1 ; it holds that L k (X) L k+1 (X): We denote L 1 (X) = [ k<1 L k (X): As long as X is nite, L k (X) is also a nite set, but L 1 (X) is a countable set and is dense in L [0;1] (X). We de ne the depth of a lottery f in L 1 (X) by (f) = k i f 2 L k (X) L k 1 (X): We use the same symbol for the depth of a lottery and the depth of a probability. It holds that (f) = k if and only if max x2x (f(x)) = k: This is relevant in Section 6. Lottery d = 25 y 75 y 2 2 is in L 2 (X) L 1 (X) and its depth (d) = 2; but since d 0 = 20 y 80 y = y 8 y 2 L 1(X); we have (d 0 ) = 1: The decision maker thinks about preferences from shallow layers to deeper ones. This stops at a cognitive bound ; which is a natural number or in nity 1. If = k < 1; he eventually reaches the set of lotteries L (X) = L k (X); and if = 1; he has no cognitive limit; we de ne L (X) = L 1 (X) = [ k<1 L k (X): We formulate a connection from L k 1 (X) to L k (X). We say that b f = (f 1 ; :::; f`) in L k 1 (X)` = L k 1 (X) L k 1 (X) is a decomposition of f 2 L k (X) i for all x 2 X; f(x) = P` t=1 1` f t(x) and (f t (x)) (f(x)) for all t `: (9) We denote this by P` t=1 1` f t; and letting be = ( 1` ; :::; 1` ); it is written as be f: b We can regard be f b as a compound lottery connecting L k 1 (X) to L k (X) by reducing be f b to f in (9). Our theory allows only this form of a compound lotteries and reduction with the depth constraint. The next lemma states that L k (X) is generated from L k 1 (X) by taking all compound lotteries of this kind. It facilitates our induction method described in Table 1.1 reducing an assertion in layer k to layer k 1: A proof of Lemma 2.1 is given in Section : 6 Lemma 2.1 (Decomposition of lotteries). Let 1 k < 1: Then, L k (X) = ff 2 L k (X) : f has a decomposition b fg: () 6 When ` > 2; binary decompositions are not enough for Lemma 2.1, For example, consider lottery f = 3 y 3 y 4 y. This is not expressed by a binary combination of elements in L0(X) = X with weights in 1: 7

9 Furthermore, for any f 2 L k (X) with (f) > 0; there is a decomposition of b f of f so that (f t (x)) < (f(x)) for any x 2 X with f(x) > 0: (11) The right-hand side of () is the set of composed lotteries from L k 1 (X) with the equal weights: The inclusion states that the composed lotteries from L k 1 (X) belong to L k (X): The converse inclusion is essential and means that each lottery in L k (X) is decomposed to an equally weighted sum of some (f 1 ; :::; f`) in L k 1 (X)` with the depth constraint in (9). In the trivial case that f = x 2 L 0 (X) is decomposed to f b = (x; :::; x). This will be used in Proposition 4.1.(2). The latter asserts the choice of a strictly shallower decomposition for f with (f) > 0. One remark is that when f is a benchmark lottery in B k (y; y); for its decomposition b f = (f 1 ; :::; f`); each f t is a benchmark lottery in B k 1 (y; y): This fact will be used without referring. For the set of lotteries over subset X 0 of X; i.e., L k (X 0 ); we introduce the following convention. We de ne L k (X 0 ) = ff 2 L k (X) : f(x) > 0 implies x 2 X 0 g: Hence, L k (X 0 ) is a subset of L k (X): Lemma 2.1 hods for L k (X 0 ) and L k 1 (X 0 ): The lottery d = [y; 25 2 ; y] has three types of decompositions: d = t y + 5 2t [y; 5 5+t ; y] + y for t = 0; 1; 2: (12) Here, a decomposition f b = (f 1 ; :::; f ) is given as f 1 = ::: = f t = y; f t+1 = ::: = f 5 t = [y; 5 ; y] and f 5 t+1 = ::: = f = y: We use this short-hand expressions rather than a full speci cation of f b = (f 1 ; :::; f ): We should be careful about this multiplicity. The reason for explicit considerations of layers for L k (X) and also preference relation % k is to avoid collapse from a layer to a shallower one. Without them, we may have a di culty in identifying the sources for preferences. For example, the weighted sum 5 [ 25 y 75 y] [ 75 y 2 25 y] is reduced to 5 2 y 5 5 y; preferences about y 5 y may possibly come from layer 2 or from layer 0: To prohibit such collapse, we take explicitly depths of layers into account in (9). 2.3 Incomplete preference relations and vector-valued utility functions We consider two methods to represent the decision maker s desires: a preference relation and a utility function. We starts with incomplete preferences and, correspondingly, representing utility functions become vector-valued with the interval order. These are rst departures from the classical EU theory. Let % be a preference relation over a given set, say A: For f; g 2 A; the expression f % g means that f is strictly preferred to g or is indi erent to g: We de ne the strict (preference) relation ; indi erence relation ; and incomparability relation 1 by f g if and only if f % g and not g % f; (13) f g if and only if f % g and g % f; f 1 g if and only if neither f % g nor g % f: All the axioms are given on the relations %; ; ; and the relation 1 is de ned as the residual part of %. Although and 1 are sometimes regarded as closely related (cf. Shafer [27], p.469), they are well separated in Theorem 6.2 in our theory. 8

10 In the classical theory in Section 2.1, the preference relation % E is assumed to be complete. Since, however, we consider a formation of preferences, our theory should avoid this completeness assumption. Nevertheless, it appears as a result when a domain of lotteries is restricted. Another method of measurement of desires is by a vector-valued function u with the interval order introduced by Fishburn [7]. Let u(f) = [u(f); u(f)] be a 2-dimensional vector-valued function from its domain A to the set Q 2 = Q Q with u(f) u(f) for each f 2 A: The components u(f) and u(f) are interpreted as the least upper and greatest lower bounds of possible utilities from f: We say that u(f) is e ectively single-valued i u(f) = u(f); in this case, we write u(f) = u(f) = u(f); dropping the upper and lower bars. We use the interval order I over the values of u; for f; g 2 A; u(f) I u(g) if and only if u(f) u(g): (14) That is, f and g are ordered if and only if the greatest lower bound u(f) from f is larger than or equal to the least upper bound u(g) from g: This I allows incomparabilities, for example, if u(f) = [ 9 ; 7 83 ] and u(g) = [ ; 83 ]; then f and g are incomparable by 2 2 I : The relation I is transitive, but (u(f) I u(g) & u(g) I u(f)) is equivalent to u(f) = u(f) = u(g) = u(g); i.e., this is the case only when the values u(f) and u(g) are e ectively single-valued and identical. 3 Measurement Step We formulate Step B of measurement of pure alternatives up to cognitive bound : This has two sides: in terms of preference relations hd k i k<+1 and in terms of vector-valued utility h k i k<+1. We show the representation theorem on hd k i k<+1 by h k i k<+1 ; and the uniqueness theorem on h k i k<+1 up to positive linear transformations. Finally, we mention that these are well interpreted in terms of Simon s [29] satis cing/aspiration argument. 3.1 Base preference streams The set of pure alternatives X is assumed to contain two distinguished elements y and y; which we call the upper and lower benchmarks. Let k < 1: We call an f 2 L k (X) a benchmark lottery of depth (at most) k i f(y) = and f(y) = 1 for some 2 k ; which we denote by [y; ; y]: The benchmark scale of depth k is the set B k (y; y) = f[y; ; y] : 2 k g: In particular, B 0 (y; y) = fy; yg: The dots in Fig.1 express the benchmark lotteries. We de ne B 1 (y; y) = [ k<1 B k (y; y): The depth of a benchmark lottery [y; ; y] is determined to be the depth of ; i.e., ([y; ; y]) = (): We denote a cognitive bound by ; which is a natural number or = 1: We use k as a variable expressing a natural number of a layer within the theory, but as a constant parameter of it. Stipulating = 1; k < + 1 expresses the two statements k if < 1 and k < if = 1. This constant plays an active role as a small constraint such as = 2 or 3 in Example 5.1 and Section 8, and as = 1 in Section 7 for consideration of the expected utility hypothesis. Let D k be a subset of D k = B k (y; y) 2 [ f(x; g); (g; x) : x 2 X and g 2 B k (y; y)g: (15) 9

11 Thus, D k consists of the scale part of the benchmarks and the measurement part of pure alternatives. The scale part allows the decision maker to make comparisons between any grids of depth k. For a pure alternative x 2 X; he thinks about where x is located in the benchmark scale B k (y; y); it may or may not correspond to a grid, which is seen in Fig.1. For example, if (x; g) 2 D k but (g; x) =2 D k ; then x is strictly better than the grid g; and if (x; g) =2 D k and (g; x) =2 D k ; then x and g are incomparable for him. We make four axioms on hd k i k<+1. Axiom B0 requires pure alternatives be between the upper and lower benchmarks y; y: Axiom B0 (Benchmarks): y D 0 x and x D 0 y for all x 2 X: The next states that preferences over B k (y; y) are the same as the natural order on k : Axiom B1 (Benchmark scale): For ; 0 2 k ; [y; ; y] D k [y; 0 ; y] if and only if 0 It follows from Axiom B1 that for ; 0 2 k ; [y; ; y] B k [y; 0 ; y] if and only if > 0 : (16) Also, = 0 if and only if [y; ; y] and [y; 0 ; y] are indi erent: Thus, D k is a complete relation over B k (y; y) by (6). This is the scale part of D k ; and is precise up to k : Since y = [y; 1; y] and y = [y; 0; y]; it follows from (16) that y B;0 y: Measurement is required to be coherent with the scale part given by Axiom B1. Axiom B2 (Monotonicity): For all x 2 X and ; 0 2 k ; if [y; ; y] D k x and 0 > ; then [y; 0 ; y] B k x; and if x D k [y; ; y] and > 0 ; then x B k [y; 0 ; y]: This implies no reversals with Axiom B1; if [y; ; y] D k x and x D k [y; 0 ; y]; then 0 : Indeed, if < 0 ; then [y; 0 ; y] B k x by B2, which implies not x D k [y; 0 ; y]: If we assume transitivity for D k over D k ; B2 could be derived from B1, but we adopt B2 instead of transitivity, since B2 gives a more speci c property to the measurement step. The last requires the preferences in layer k be preserved in the next layer k + 1: This is expressed by the set-theoretical inclusion in Table 1.1. Axiom B3 (Preservation): For all f; g 2 D k ; f D k g implies f D k+1 g: The above axioms still allow great freedom for base preference relations hd k i k<+1 : To see this fact as well as how the measurement step B of utilities from pure alternatives goes on, we consider vector-valued utility functions with the interval order I in Section Base utility streams We consider another way of Step B in terms of vector-valued utility functions with the interval order I. Let h k i k<+1 = h[ k ; k ]i k<+1 be a sequence of vector-valued functions so that for each k < + 1; k is a function from B k (y; y) [ X to Q 2 such that k (f) k (f) for all f 2 B k (y; y) [ X: Recall that when k (f) is e ectively single-valued, we write k (f) = k (f) = k (f). The following conditions on h k i k<+1 are not exactly parallel to the axiomatic system B0 to B3, but these two systems are equivalent, which is stated in Theorem 3.1. We de ne a base (upper-lower) utility stream h k i k<+1 = h[ k ; k ]i k<+1 by b0 to b3 : b0: 0 (y) > 0 (y);

12 and for k < + 1; b1: k ([y; ; y]) = k (y) + (1 ) k (y) for all [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y); b2: for each x 2 X; k (x) = k ([y; x ; y]) and k (x) = k ([y; x ; y]) for some x and x in k ; b3: for each x 2 X; k (x) k+1 (x) k+1 (x) k (x): Condition b0 xes the utility values from the upper and lower benchmarks y and y; which corresponds to the implication of B0. Then, b1 means that for benchmark lotteries [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y); k ([y; ; y]) is e ectively single-valued and takes the expected utility value of y and y; which corresponds to B1. Here, the EU hypothesis is included. b2 states that the least upper and greatest lower utilities of x 2 X are measured by the benchmark scale B k (y; y); this does not exactly correspond to B2, but it does an implication of B2 with the help of transitivity for k implied by the interval order I. Corresponding to B3, b3 states that k (x) and k (x) are getting more accurate as k increases. These imply k (y) = 0 (y) and k (y) = 0 (y) for any k < + 1: (17) Now, we have Theorem 3.1. As stated, all proofs are given in separate subsections. Theorem 3.1 (Representation for Step B). A base preference stream hd k i k<+1 satis es Axioms B0 to B3 if and only if there is a base utility stream h k i k<+1 satisfying b0 to b3 such that for any k < + 1 and (f; g) 2 D k ; f D k g if and only if k (f) I k (g): (18) Although k is vector-valued, it satis es the EU hypothesis, since by b1; k ([y; ; y]) = k (y) + (1 ) k (y) for [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y); and by b2; k (x) = x k (y) + (1 x ) k (y) and k (x) = x k (y) + (1 x ) k (y) for x 2 X: The EU hypothesis does not hold for the representation theorem for Step E (Theorem 5.1). We have the uniqueness theorem. Theorem 3.2 (Uniqueness). Let hd k i k<+1 satisfy Axioms B0 to B3. If h k i k<+1 and h 0 k i k<+1 satisfying b0 to b3 represent hd k i k<+1 in the sense of (18), there are rational numbers > 0 and such that 0 k (x) = k(x)+ = [ k (x)+; k (x)+] for all x 2 X and k < +1: Conditions b0 to b3 require k (x) = ( k (x); k (x)) be represented essentially by two values and 0 in k with 0 (y) and 0 (y): However, 0 (y) and 0 (y) for each h k i k<+1 are allowed to take any two rational numbers in Q only with 0 (y) > 0 (y): This is the reason for the above uniqueness result. The uniqueness up to a positive linear transformation plays a crucial role in the literature of bargaining theories such as Nash [23] and the Nash welfare function theory (Kaneko- Nakamura [18]). The rational number scalars are enough for the 2-person case and the real-algebraic numbers are enough for the general n-person case (cf. Kaneko [15] for the 2-person case). It is easy to generalize Theorem 3.2 for the real numbers scalars, but the problem is how much we restrict the scalors. Theorem 3.2 is suggestive of how bounded rationality is incorporated to these theories. The processes described in terms of hd k i k<+1 and/or h k i k<+1 are thought experiments by the decision maker to search preferences/utilities in his mind. From the viewpoint of bounded 11

13 Figure 2: upper and lower utility functions rationality, he may stop his search when he is satis ed and/or is already tired. This is the same as Simon s [29] argument of satis cing/aspiration. First, we consider Example 3.1, and then we exemplify the satis cing/aspiration argument. Example 3.1. Let X = fy; y; yg; 0 (y) = [1; 1]; 0 (y) = [0; 0]; and 0 (y) = [1; 0]: Also, let 1 (y) = [ 9 ; 7 ]: Then, 1(f) = [ 8 ; 8 8 ] for f = [y; ; y] by b1: Then 1(y) I 1 (f) and 1 (f) I 1 (y); so y and f are incomparable with respect to D 1 by (18). In Fig.2, h k (y)i k<+1 = h[ k (y); k (y)]i k<+1 is described as solid lines in cases A, B, and C. Since 0 (y) = [1; 0]; we have y B 0 y B 0 y by (18). For k = 2; in A, 2 (y) = [ 77 ; 77 ] and the 2 2 decision maker prefers f = [y; 8 ; y] to y; and in B, 2(y) = [ 83 2 ; 83 k (y) = [ 9 ; 7 ]; he prefers y to f: In C, 2 ] is constant for k 2; he gives up comparisons between y and f after k = 1: Introspection Process of Simon s satis cing/aspiration: The decision maker starts evaluating of a pure alternative y 2 X with the benchmark scale B 0 (y; y): Suppose that he nds 0 (y) = [1; 0]; i.e., he attaches the upper value 1 and lower value 0 to y: If = 0; his introspection is over. Let 1: Then, he goes to layer 1 and uses the more precise scale B 1 (y; y) to measure y: In Example 3.1, y is better than [y; 7 9 ; y] but worse than [y; ; y]: Still, he has not reached a very precise measurement. If = 1; he stops introspection. Let 2: Then, he goes to layer k = 2; in A of Fig.2, he reaches precise utility values 2 (y) = [ 77 ; 77 ]; but in C, he has 2 2 still imprecise values 2 (y) = [ 9 ; 7 ] and does not improve them any more even for k > 2. In case A, there are several possible interpretations: one is that 2 (y) = [ 77 ; 77 ] expresses 2 2 his preferences precisely, and the other is that he is still unsure about the value of y; for example, the lower and upper values may be 77 and 78 ; but according his aspiration level, the di erence = 1 is tiny and he does not care about the choice between 77 and 78 : By chance, he chooses 2 (y) = [ 77 ; 77 ]: In case C, (y) = [ 9 ; 7 ] is good enough for him, and he forgets further updating. Thus, exact values may include some imprecision induced by his aspiration level. This is an attribute of cognitive acts by the decision maker, instead of an attribute of probabilities. 12

14 3.3 Proofs Proof of Theorem 3.1. (If): Suppose that h k i k<+1 satis es b0 to b3 and that (18) holds for hd k i k<+1 and h k i k<+1 B0: We have, by b0; b1 and (17), 0 (y) 0 (x) and 0 (x) 0 (y); i.e., y D 0 x D 0 y: Thus, B0. B1: By (18), b1, and (17), we have [y; ; y] D k [y; 0 ; y] if and only if k ([y; ; y]) I k ([y; 0 ; y]) if and only if 0 (y) + (1 ) 0 (y) 0 0 (y) + (1 0 ) 0 (y) if and only if 0 : That is, B1. B2: Let [y; ; y] D k x and 0 > : By b2 and (18), we have 0 k (y) + (1 0 ) k (y) > k (y)+ (1 ) k (y) k (x): Thus, by b1; k ([y; 0 ; y]) = 0 k (y) + (1 0 ) k (y) > k (x): By (18), we have [y; 0 ; y] B k x: The other case is symmetric. B3: Let f D k g: By (18), we have k (f) k (g): Let f = x 2 X and g = [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y): Then, k (g) = k+1 (g) by b1: Then, by b3, we have k+1 (f) k (f) k (g) = k+1 (g): By (18), f D k+1 g: The case f 2 B k (y; y); g = x 2 X is parallel. The case f = [y; ; y], g = [y; 0 ; y] 2 B k (y; y) is similar. (Only-if): Suppose that hd k i k<+1 satisfying Axioms B0 to B3 is given. We construct a base utility stream h k i k<+1 satisfying (18). We de ne [ k ; k ]; k < + 1; as follows: for any f 2 B k (y; y) [ X; k (f) = minf 2 k : [y; ; y] D k fg; (19) k (f) = maxf 2 k : f D k [y; ; y]g: It holds that k (f) = k (f) for f 2 B k (y; y): Consider f = [y; f ; y]; g = [y; g ; y] 2 B k (y; y): Then, f D k g if and only if [y; f ; y] D k [y; g ; y] if and only if f g ; i.e., k (f) I k (g) by B1. Let f 2 B k (y; y) and g = x 2 X: Denote k (f) = f and k (x) = x : Suppose f D k x: By (19), [y; f ; y] = f D k [y; x ; y]: By B1, f x ; i.e., k (f) I k (x): The converse is obtained by tracing this back. Thus, f D k x if and only if k (f) I k (x): The case f = x 2 X; g 2 B k (y; y) is parallel. By (16) and B0, we have b0: By (19), we have b2 and b3: Consider b1: Since k (y) = 1 and k (y) = 0; the set f k (f) : f 2 B k (y; y)g is the same as k : For any f = [y; ; y]; g = [y; 0 ; y] 2 B k (y; y); we have, by (17), k (f) > k (g) if and only if f B k g if and only if > 0 : Hence, k (f) = = k (y) + (1 ) k (y), which is b1: Proof of Theorem 3.2. Let = ( 0 0 (y) 0 0 (y))=( 0(y) 0 (y)) and = ( 0 (y) 0 0 (y) 0 0 (y) 0(y))=( 0 (y) 0 (y)): Noting (17), we have 0 k (y) = k(y) + and 0 k (y) = k(y) +. For any [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y); we have 0 k ([y; ; y]) = k(y)+ (1 ) k (y) = k ([y; ; y]) + by b1. For any x 2 X; we have x and x in k by b2 for k such that k (x) = [ k ([y; x ; y]); k ([y; x ; y])]: Let 0 x and 0 x be given by b2 for 0 k : Suppose 0 x 6= x ; say, x > 0 x: Then, k ([y; x ; y]) I k (x); but k (x) = k ([y; 0 x; y]) > k ([y; 0 x; y]): Hence, k ([y; 0 x; y]) I k (x): However, by de nition of 0 x; we have 0 k ([y; 0 x; y]) I 0 k (x): This is impossible since k and 0 k represent the same D k : The case x < 0 x is parallel. Thus, 0 x = x ; and similarly, 0 x = x ; which imply 0 k (x) = [0 k ([y; x; y]); 0 k ([y; x; y])] = [ k ([y; x ; y]); k ([y; x ; y])] + = k (x) + : 13

15 4 Extension Step: Extended Preference Streams Step B is an introspective process to nd preferences hidden in the mind of the decision maker. On the other hand, Step E is a logical process to extend base preferences found in Step B. This di erence may create some logical di culty in adopting the standard method of representing preferences in terms of a binary relation. We actually show that we can avoid this di culty. Keeping this remark in mind, we present our axiomatic system for Step E. Throughout this section, let hd k i k<+1 be a given base preference stream satisfying Axioms B0 to B Extended preference stream Here, we consider how D k is extended to L k (X) for k < + 1: Axiom E0 is to convert base preferences D k to % k for each k < + 1; depicted as the vertical arrows in Table 1.1. Axiom E0 (Extension)(i): For any (f; g) 2 D 0 ; f D 0 g if and only if f % 0 g: (ii): For any k (1 k < + 1) and (f; g) 2 D k ; if f D k g; then f % k g: This is the ultimate source for preferences for Step E. For k = 0; the base preferences are only the direct source for % 0 : For k 1; in addition to the base preferences, there is another source from the previous % k 1 ; thus, (ii) has only one direction. However, we will show that as long as the domain D k is concerned, the converse of (ii) holds for our intended preference stream h% k i k<+1. Consider the connection between layers k 1 and k: For f b = (f 1 ; :::; f`) and bg = (g 1 ; :::; g`); we write f b % k bg i f t % k g t for all t = 1; :::; `: Recall that a decomposition of f 2 L k (X) is de ned by (9): We formulate a derivation of % k from % k 1 as follows: let 1 k < + 1: Axiom E1 (Derivation from the previous layer): Let f 2 L k (X); g 2 B k (y; y); and b f; bg their decompositions: If b f % k 1 bg or bg % k 1 b f; then f %k g or g % k f; respectively. In layer k 1; each f t of f b = (f 1 ; :::; f`) is compared with the corresponding benchmark lottery g t. These preferences are extended to layer k. In Table 1.1, the horizontal arrows indicate this derivation. When = 2; the lottery d = 25 y 75 y in the example of (2) should be evaluated in 2 2 terms of lotteries in B 2 (y; y): Axiom NM2 (Independence) is much stronger in that comparisons jump from one layer to a layer of any depth. In E2, a connection from one layer to the next with equal weights describes the step-by-step extension of preferences by the decision maker. The preferences derived by the above axioms are extended by transitivity: let 0 k < + 1: Axiom E2 (Transitivity): For any f; g; h 2 L k (X); if f % k g and g % k h; then f % k h: Here, we regard Axioms E0 to E2 as inference rules, rather than properties to be satis ed by % k. This means that the decision maker constructs % 0 ; % 1 ; :::; step by step, using these axioms. As mentioned above, this view may involve some di culty; it is logically possible that Axioms E0 to E2 may lead to new unintended preferences. Theorem 4.1 states that this is not the case for the constructed preferences. These also have the following additional conditions: E0 : for all k < + 1 and (f; g) 2 D k ; f D k g if and only if f % k g; E1 : E1 holds and if the premise of E1 includes strict preferences, so does the conclusion. Condition E0 states that h% k i k<+1 is a faithful extension of hd k i k<+1 in that as long as a 14

16 pair of lotteries in D k is concerned; the extended relation % k has no super uous preferences. E1 is a strengthening of E1, too. Without these, some preferences would be added in the derivation process of % 0 ; % 1 ; :::; and also we would have inconveniences in applications. Note that E2 (transitivity) preserves strict preferences in the same way as E1 : To prove that our constructive extended stream h% k i k<+1 enjoys E0, E1 ; and E2, we rst show the following lemma using the EU hypothesis. However, this di ers from the intended stream, which enjoys the EU hypothesis only partially. For this lemma, a base utility stream h k i k<+1 satisfying (18) given in Theorem 3.1 is used. Lemma 4.1 (Consistency of E0, E1, and E2). There is a stream of binary relations h% k i k<+1 satisfying Axioms E0 ; E1, and E2. One of such a h% k i k<+1 is given as follows: for all k < + 1; we de ne % k by f % k g if and only if E f ( k ) E g ( k ): (20) A point of this lemma is that we have no problem in regarding E0 to E2 as requirements for binary relations h% k i k<+1; and also, some satis es E0 and E2 : Now, we prepare a few concepts for the main theorem, i.e., Theorem 4.1, of this section: Let h% k i k<+1 be a stream satisfying E0 to E2. We say that h% k i k<+1 is the smallest stream i for any h% 0 k i k<+1 satisfying E0 to E2, and f; g 2 L k (X); k < + 1; f % k g implies f % 0 k g: (21) Also, the set of preferences over L k (X) derived from % k 1 by E1 is denoted by (% k 1 ) E1 ; and the set of transitive closure of F L k (X) 2 is denoted by F tr ; i.e., (f; g) 2 F tr if and only if there is a nite sequence f = h 0 ; h 1 ; :::; h m = g such that (h t ; h t+1 ) 2 F for t = 0; :::; m 1: Theorem 4.1 (Smallest extended stream). The sequence h% k i k<+1 of the sets generated by the following induction: % 0 = (D 0 ) tr ; and % k = [(% k 1 ) E1 [ (D k )] tr for each k (1 k < + 1) (22) is the smallest stream satisfying E0 to E2. Also, h% k i k<+1 satis es E0 and E1 : The construction starts with % 0 = (D 0 ) tr ; which is well de ned since D 0 is a binary relation in D 0 : Then, provided that % k 1 and D k are already given, % k is de ned to be [(% k 1 ) E1 [(D k )] tr : This is a subset of L k (X) 2 ; thus, it is a binary relation. This preference stream is unique, and is the smallest among the streams satisfying E0 to E2. Furthermore, the constructed stream satis es E0 and E1 : We extract the essential addition in (22) to Axioms E0 to E2 and formulate it as Axiom E3. It states that a preference f % k g is based on comparisons with the benchmark scale B k (y; y) with either D k or % k 1 : We note that h in E3 may be the same as f or g: Axiom E3 (i): For any f; g 2 L 0 (X); if f % 0 g; then f % 0 h % 0 g for some h 2 B 0 (y; y): (ii): For any f; g 2 L k (X) (k 1); if f % k g; then there is an h 2 B k (y; y) with f % k h % k g such that for the rst pair (f; h); f D k h holds or f; h have decompositions f; b b h with b h % k and the same holds for the second pair (h; g): The key of Axiom E3 is to include the depth constraint; comparison f % k g e ectively comes from the benchmark scale B k (y; y) of the same depth k: This constraint with a nite cognitive 15 1 bg;

17 bound makes the EU hypothesis hold partially. The preference stream given by (20) of Lemma 4.1 enjoys the EU hypothesis, but since it does not take the depths of f; g into account, Axiom E3 is violated. This violation will be seen in Example 5.1. The stream h% k i k<+1 given by (22) is characterized by adding E3 to E0 to E2. Theorem 4.2 (Uniqueness by E0 to E3). Any extended stream satisfying E0 to E3 is the same as the preference stream h% k i k<+1 given by Theorem 4.1. Throughout the following, the stream given by (22) is denoted by h% k i k<+1 : Other streams may have some additional superscripts such as 0 ; : Proposition 4.1 will be used in the subsequent analyses: (1) is the horizontal arrows in Table 1.1, and (2) that % k is bounded in L k (X) by the upper and lower benchmarks y and y: Proposition 4.1. Let h% k i k<+1 satis es E0 to E3, and 1 k < + 1: (1)(Preservation of preferences): For any f; g 2 L k 1 (X); f % k 1 g implies f % k g: (2): y % k f % k y for any f 2 L k (X): Remark 4.1 (Partial EU hypothesis in the two systems). Axiom B1 and b1 assume the EU hypothesis along the benchmark scale B k (y; y); and E2 is a very weak form of Axiom NM2 (independence). The other axioms are related to it only in that preferences are considered through comparisons with B k (y; y). As mentioned above, Axiom E3 includes the depth constraint on preference comparisons; it follows from Lemma 4.1 and Theorem 4.1 that there are possibly many preference streams satisfying E0 to E2; among which the EU representation in (20) is allowed. A departure from the EU hypothesis is caused by two types of depths included in a lottery and their interactions with a cognitive bound < 1: For example, lottery d = 25 y 75 y involves the depths of coe cient 25 and of evaluation y. This and E3 make the EU hypothesis hold only for some partial domain, which is explicitly studied in Section Proofs Proof of Lemma 4.1. We show that h% k i k<+1 given by (20) satis es E0 ; E1 ; and E2. By Theorem 3.2, we can assume that k (y) = 1 and k (y) = 0: Since E f ( k ) = if f = [y; ; y] 2 B k (y; y) and E x ( k ) = k (x) if f = x 2 X: Hence, by (18) and b2; f D k x if and only if k (x) if and only if E f ( k ) E x ( k ): The other cases are symmetric. Thus, E0 holds for any (f; g) 2 D k : It remains to show that h% k i k<+1 satis es E1 and E2. Since (20) gives the interval order over the set f[e f ( k ); E f ( k )] : f 2 L k (X)g; E2 holds. We show E1 : Let f 2 L k (X); g 2 B k [y; y] and their decompositions f b and bg with f b % k 1 bg: By (20), E f t ( k ) E gt ( k ) for all t = 1; :::; `: Then, E f ( k ) = E be f b( k ) = P` t=1 1` Ef t ( k ) P` t=1 1` Eg t ( k ) = E bebg ( k ) = E g ( k ): If strict preferences are included in the decompositions, the conclusion is strict; thus we have E1 : Proof of Theorem 4.1. This has the three assertions: (a) h% k i k<+1 is a sequence of a binary relations satisfying Axioms E0 to E2; (b) it is the smallest in the sense of (21) among streams h% 0 k i k<+1 satisfying E0 to E2; and (c) E0 ; E1 hold for h% k i k<+1 : (a): E2 follow directly from (22). Consider E0. (ii) follows from (22). We show that % 0 = (D 0 ) tr satis es that for any (f; g) 2 D 0 ; f % 0 g implies f D 0 g: Since % 0 = (D 0 ) tr ; there is a sequence f = h 0 D 0 ::: D 0 h m = g. If h t 2 X B 0 (y; y); then h t 1 2 B 0 (y; y) and h t+1 2 B 0 (y; y): By B2, t 1 t+1 ; where h t 1 = [y; t 1 ; y] and h t+1 = [y; t+1 ; y]: If h t ; h t+1 2 B 0 (y; y); then 16

18 t t+1 : Hence, we can shorten the sequence to f = h 0 D 0 h m = g: Thus, f D 0 g: Consider E1. Suppose that f 2 B k [y; y] and g 2 L k (X) have decompositions f; b bg 2 L k 1 (X) with f b % k 1 bg: By (22), we have f = e f b % k e bg = g: The symmetric case, bg % k 1 f; b is similar. (b): We prove by induction on k that h% k i k<+1 satis es (21) for any h% 0 k i k<+1 satisfying E0 to E2. When k = 0; we have % 0 = (D 0 ) tr by (22): Let f % 0 g; i.e., f (D 0 ) tr g; which implies that there is a sequence f = h 0 D 0 h 1 D 0 ::: D 0 h m = g: By E0.(i), we have f = h 0 % 0 0 h 1 % 0 0 ::: % 0 0 h m = g: By E2 for % 0 0 ; we have f %0 0 g. Now, we assume that (21) holds for k 1: Let f % k g: By (22), there is a sequence f = h 0 % k ::: % k h m = g such that each h t % k h t+1 is a consequence of E1 or h t % k h t+1 is h t D k h t+1 : In the rst case, there are decompositions b h t ; b h t+1 of h t ; h t+1 such that b h t % k 1 b ht+1 : By the induction hypothesis, we have b h t % 0 b k 1 h t+1 : Thus, h t % 0 k h t+1 by E1 for % 0 k : In the second case, h t D k h t+1 implies h t % 0 k h t+1 by E0.(ii) for % 0 k : Hence, f %0 k g by E2 for %0 k : (c): Take h% k i k<+1 given by Lemma 4.1. Since h% k i k<+1 satis es E0 to E2, it holds that for all k < + 1 and f; g 2 L k (X); f % k g implies f % k g: (23) E0 : Since E0 holds for % k by Lemma 4.1, we have: for any (f; g) 2 D k; f % k g implies f D k g; thus, f % k g implies f D k g: The converse is from (22). E1 : Let f; g 2 L k (X): Let f; b bg be decompositions of f; g so that f b % k 1 bg with strict preferences for some components. Hence, by (23), the same holds for % k 1 : Hence, by E2 for % k 1 ; we have f k g: In this case, g % k f is impossible; if it was the case, we would have, by (23), f k g; a contradiction. Hence, f k g: Proof of Theorem 4.2. Let h% k i k<+1 be any extended stream satisfying E0 to E3. We prove by induction on k < + 1 that for any f; g 2 L k (X); f % k g if and only if f % k g: (24) Since h% k i k<+1 is the smallest stream satisfying E0 to E2 by Theorem 4.1, the if part holds for any k < + 1: Consider the only-if part. Let k = 0: Let f; g 2 L 0 (X) with f % 0 g: Then, by E3.(i), we have an h 2 B 0 (y; y) with f % 0 h % 0 g: But this h is either y or y: If h = y; then h D 0 f and f D 0 h by B0: Since h D 0 g by B0, we have f (D 0 ) tr g; i.e., f % 0 g by (22). The case h = y is similar. We make the induction hypothesis that the only-if part holds for k 1: Let f % k g: Then, by E3, we have h 0 := f % k h 1 % k h 2 := g for some h 1 2 B k (y; y): If h 0 = x 2 X; then, h 0 = x has no decomposition; thus, by E3.(ii), h 0 D k h 1 ; which implies h 0 % k h 1 by E0 for % k. Let h 0 =2 X: By E3.(ii), b h 0 % b k 1 h 1 for some decompositions b h 0 ; b h 1 of h 0 ; h 1 : By the induction hypothesis, we have b h 0 % k 1 b h1 : Thus, by E1 for % k ; we have h 0 % k h 1 : By the same argument, we have h 1 % k h 2 : Thus, by (22), h 0 % k h 2 ; i.e., f % k g: Proof of Proposition 4.1. (1): Let f 2 L k 1 (X) and g 2 B k 1 (y; y): Suppose f % k 1 g: Then, f; g 2 L k 1 (X) L k (X): Let f 1 = ::: = f` = f and g 1 = ::: = g` = g: Then, f = P` t=1 1` f t and f = P` t=1 1` g t: By E1, we have f % k g: The case g % k 1 f is similar. Let f; g 2 L k 1 (X) with f % k 1 g: Then, by E3.(ii) for k; f % k 1 h % k 1 g for some h 2 B k 1 (y; y): It follows from the conclusion of the above paragraph that f % k h % k g: By E2, we have f % k g: (2): Let f 2 L 0 (X) = X: By B0 and % 0 = D 0, we have the assertion for k = 0. Suppose the 17

Mean-Variance Utility

Mean-Variance Utility Mean-Variance Utility Yutaka Nakamura University of Tsukuba Graduate School of Systems and Information Engineering Division of Social Systems and Management -- Tennnoudai, Tsukuba, Ibaraki 305-8573, Japan

More information

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Alexander Zimper Working Paper Number 97 Department of Economics and Econometrics, University of Johannesburg Revisiting independence

More information

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Nonlinear Programming (NLP) Natalia Lazzati Mathematics for Economics (Part I) Note 6: Nonlinear Programming - Unconstrained Optimization Note 6 is based on de la Fuente (2000, Ch. 7), Madden (1986, Ch. 3 and 5) and Simon and Blume

More information

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Ryo-Ichi Nagahisa y Kansai University Koichi Suga z Waseda University November 14, 2017 Abstract A social state is assumed to be chracterized by welfare

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Ryo-Ichi Nagahisa y Kansai University Koichi Suga z Waseda University July 31, 2017 Abstract 1 Introduction 2 Notation and De nitions Let N = f1; 2;

More information

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem Natalia Lazzati Mathematics for Economics (Part I) Note 8: Nonlinear Programming - The Kuhn-Tucker Problem Note 8 is based on de la Fuente (2000, Ch. 7) and Simon and Blume (1994, Ch. 18 and 19). The Kuhn-Tucker

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 Cycles of length two in monotonic models José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 October 20122 JEL:

More information

1 The Well Ordering Principle, Induction, and Equivalence Relations

1 The Well Ordering Principle, Induction, and Equivalence Relations 1 The Well Ordering Principle, Induction, and Equivalence Relations The set of natural numbers is the set N = f1; 2; 3; : : :g. (Some authors also include the number 0 in the natural numbers, but number

More information

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny. These notes correspond to chapter of Jehle and Reny. Uncertainty Until now we have considered our consumer s making decisions in a world with perfect certainty. However, we can extend the consumer theory

More information

Adding an Apple to an Orange: A General Equilibrium Approach to Aggregation of Beliefs

Adding an Apple to an Orange: A General Equilibrium Approach to Aggregation of Beliefs Adding an Apple to an Orange: A General Equilibrium Approach to Aggregation of Beliefs Yi Jin y, Jianbo Zhang z, Wei Zhou x Department of Economics, The University of Kansas August 2006 Abstract This paper

More information

1 Selected Homework Solutions

1 Selected Homework Solutions Selected Homework Solutions Mathematics 4600 A. Bathi Kasturiarachi September 2006. Selected Solutions to HW # HW #: (.) 5, 7, 8, 0; (.2):, 2 ; (.4): ; (.5): 3 (.): #0 For each of the following subsets

More information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Ignacio Montes, Enrique Miranda, Susana Montes University of Oviedo, Dep. of Statistics and Operations Research. Abstract Stochastic dominance, which is

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Undecidability arising from Prediction/Decision Making in an Interdependent Situation

Undecidability arising from Prediction/Decision Making in an Interdependent Situation Undecidability arising from Prediction/Decision Making in an Interdependent Situation Tai-Wei Hu and Mamoru Kaneko 09 August 2014, preliminary Abstract Logical inference is an engine for human thinking,

More information

Desire-as-belief revisited

Desire-as-belief revisited Desire-as-belief revisited Richard Bradley and Christian List June 30, 2008 1 Introduction On Hume s account of motivation, beliefs and desires are very di erent kinds of propositional attitudes. Beliefs

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice David Autor 14.03 Fall 2004 Agenda: 1. Consumer preference theory (a) Notion of utility function (b) Axioms of consumer preference (c)

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics Topics Volume 7, Issue 1 2007 Article 29 Asymmetric Nash Bargaining with Surprised Players Eran Hanany Rotem Gal Tel Aviv University, hananye@post.tau.ac.il Tel

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Properties of the Integers

Properties of the Integers Properties of the Integers The set of all integers is the set and the subset of Z given by Z = {, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, }, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }, is the set of nonnegative integers (also called

More information

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c. Properties of the Integers The set of all integers is the set and the subset of Z given by Z = {, 5, 4, 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, }, N = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, }, is the set of nonnegative integers (also called

More information

Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity

Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity Nicolas Gravel y, Thierry Marchant z and Arunava Sen x April 8th 2009 Keywords: Ignorance, Ambiguity, Uniform

More information

Near convexity, metric convexity, and convexity

Near convexity, metric convexity, and convexity Near convexity, metric convexity, and convexity Fred Richman Florida Atlantic University Boca Raton, FL 33431 28 February 2005 Abstract It is shown that a subset of a uniformly convex normed space is nearly

More information

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts Review of Economics & Finance Submitted on 28/Nov./2011 Article ID: 1923-7529-2012-02-65-11 Yutaka Matsushita Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure

More information

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Egregious Errata Positive Political Theory II (University of Michigan Press, 2005) regrettably contains a variety of obscurities and errors,

More information

1 of 8 7/15/2009 3:43 PM Virtual Laboratories > 1. Foundations > 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 6. Cardinality Definitions and Preliminary Examples Suppose that S is a non-empty collection of sets. We define a relation

More information

2 Interval-valued Probability Measures

2 Interval-valued Probability Measures Interval-Valued Probability Measures K. David Jamison 1, Weldon A. Lodwick 2 1. Watson Wyatt & Company, 950 17th Street,Suite 1400, Denver, CO 80202, U.S.A 2. Department of Mathematics, Campus Box 170,

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

TitleList-based decision problems Author(s) Dimitrov, Dinko; Mukherjee, Saptars Citation Issue 2013-03 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/25504 Right Hitotsubashi

More information

Quantum Decision Theory

Quantum Decision Theory Quantum Decision Theory V.I. Yukalov and D. Sornette Department of Management, Technology and Economics\ ETH Zürich Plan 1. Classical Decision Theory 1.1. Notations and definitions 1.2. Typical paradoxes

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

Learning and Risk Aversion

Learning and Risk Aversion Learning and Risk Aversion Carlos Oyarzun Texas A&M University Rajiv Sarin Texas A&M University January 2007 Abstract Learning describes how behavior changes in response to experience. We consider how

More information

A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games

A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games Towson University Department of Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper No. 2017-04 A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games by Finn Christensen

More information

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

1 Uncertainty and Insurance Uncertainty and Insurance Reading: Some fundamental basics are in Varians intermediate micro textbook (Chapter 2). A good (advanced, but still rather accessible) treatment is in Kreps A Course in Microeconomic

More information

Appendix II Testing for consistency

Appendix II Testing for consistency Appendix II Testing for consistency I. Afriat s (1967) Theorem Let (p i ; x i ) 25 i=1 be the data generated by some individual s choices, where pi denotes the i-th observation of the price vector and

More information

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP Prof. Olivier Bochet Room A.34 Phone 3 63 476 E-mail olivier.bochet@vwi.unibe.ch Webpage http//sta.vwi.unibe.ch/bochet Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2 Lecture Note Choice-Based Approach Price e ects, Wealth

More information

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu April 1993 Abstract

More information

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility

Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences. in Expected Utility Notes on Supermodularity and Increasing Differences in Expected Utility Alejandro Francetich Department of Decision Sciences and IGIER Bocconi University, Italy March 7, 204 Abstract Many choice-theoretic

More information

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System 21-355 Principles of Real Analysis I Fall 2004 I. The Real Number System The main goal of this course is to develop the theory of real-valued functions of one real variable in a systematic and rigorous

More information

Choosing the Two Finalists

Choosing the Two Finalists Choosing the Two Finalists K r Eliaz Department of Economics, Brown University Michael Richter Department of Economics, New York University Ariel Rubinstein University of Tel Aviv Cafés and Department

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity

Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity Uniform Expected Utility Criteria for Decision Making under Ignorance or Objective Ambiguity Nicolas Gravel y, Thierry Marchant z and Arunava Sen x April 4th 2009 Keywords: Ignorance, Ambiguity, Uniform

More information

Chapter 1. GMM: Basic Concepts

Chapter 1. GMM: Basic Concepts Chapter 1. GMM: Basic Concepts Contents 1 Motivating Examples 1 1.1 Instrumental variable estimator....................... 1 1.2 Estimating parameters in monetary policy rules.............. 2 1.3 Estimating

More information

Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component

Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component Christophe Gonzales LIP6 Université Paris 6 tour 46-0, ème étage 4, place Jussieu 755 Paris Cedex 05, France e-mail: ChristopheGonzales@lip6fr

More information

What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing?

What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing? What Are Asset Demand Tests of Expected Utility Really Testing? Felix Kubler, Larry Selden and Xiao Wei August 25, 2016 Abstract Assuming the classic contingent claim setting, a number of nancial asset

More information

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Berardi Stefano Valentini Silvio Dip. Informatica Dip. Mat. Pura ed Applicata Univ. Torino Univ. Padova c.so Svizzera

More information

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg

Inequality and Envy. Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert. London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg Inequality and Envy Frank Cowell and Udo Ebert London School of Economics and Universität Oldenburg DARP 88 December 2006 The Toyota Centre Suntory and Toyota International Centres for Economics and Related

More information

LECTURE 12 UNIT ROOT, WEAK CONVERGENCE, FUNCTIONAL CLT

LECTURE 12 UNIT ROOT, WEAK CONVERGENCE, FUNCTIONAL CLT MARCH 29, 26 LECTURE 2 UNIT ROOT, WEAK CONVERGENCE, FUNCTIONAL CLT (Davidson (2), Chapter 4; Phillips Lectures on Unit Roots, Cointegration and Nonstationarity; White (999), Chapter 7) Unit root processes

More information

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions Department Discussion Paper DDP0702 ISSN 1914-2838 Department of Economics Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

More information

A New Look at Local Expected Utility

A New Look at Local Expected Utility A New Look at Local Expected Utility S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci Department of Decision Sciences and GER, Università Bocconi February 22, 2014 Abstract We revisit the classical local

More information

Ergodic Theory (Lecture Notes) Joan Andreu Lázaro Camí

Ergodic Theory (Lecture Notes) Joan Andreu Lázaro Camí Ergodic Theory (Lecture Notes) Joan Andreu Lázaro Camí Department of Mathematics Imperial College London January 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Measure Theory 5 2.1 Motivation: Positive measures and

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Ordinal preference theory Harald Wiese University of Leipzig Harald Wiese (University of Leipzig) Advanced Microeconomics 1 / 68 Part A. Basic decision and preference theory 1 Decisions

More information

Econ Spring Review Set 1 - Answers ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE-

Econ Spring Review Set 1 - Answers ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE- Econ 4808 - Spring 2008 Review Set 1 - Answers ORY ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT. SET THE- 1. De ne a thing or action in words. Refer to this thing or action as A. Then de ne a condition

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Ordered Value Restriction

Ordered Value Restriction Ordered Value Restriction Salvador Barberà Bernardo Moreno Univ. Autònoma de Barcelona and Univ. de Málaga and centra March 1, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we restrict the pro les of preferences to be

More information

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games John Morgan University of California at Berkeley Preliminaries Our running example is that of a decision maker (DM) consulting a knowledgeable expert for advice about

More information

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable

4.1 Real-valued functions of a real variable Chapter 4 Functions When introducing relations from a set A to a set B we drew an analogy with co-ordinates in the x-y plane. Instead of coming from R, the first component of an ordered pair comes from

More information

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University and Warwick Business School Quitzé Valenzuela-Stookey Northwestern University Marie-Louise Vierø Queen s University December 10,

More information

Subjective Recursive Expected Utility?

Subjective Recursive Expected Utility? Economic Theory manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Subjective Recursive Expected Utility? Peter Klibano 1 and Emre Ozdenoren 2 1 MEDS Department, Kellogg School of Management, Northwestern

More information

A prospect proof of the Goldbach s conjecture

A prospect proof of the Goldbach s conjecture A prospect proof of the Goldbach s conjecture Douadi MIHOUBI LMPA, the University of M sila, 28000 M sila, Algeria mihoubi_douadi@yahoofr March 21, 2015 Abstract Based on, the well-ordering (N;

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

Abstract Measure Theory

Abstract Measure Theory 2 Abstract Measure Theory Lebesgue measure is one of the premier examples of a measure on R d, but it is not the only measure and certainly not the only important measure on R d. Further, R d is not the

More information

CAE Working Paper # Equivalence of Utilitarian Maximal and Weakly Maximal Programs. Kuntal Banerjee and Tapan Mitra.

CAE Working Paper # Equivalence of Utilitarian Maximal and Weakly Maximal Programs. Kuntal Banerjee and Tapan Mitra. ISSN 1936-5098 CAE Working Paper #09-03 Equivalence of Utilitarian Maximal and Weakly Maximal Programs by Kuntal Banerjee and Tapan Mitra February 2009 Equivalence of Utilitarian Maximal and Weakly Maximal

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis 1 Convex sets Both convex sets and functions have general importance in economic theory, not only in optimization. Given two points x; y 2 R n and 2 [0; 1]; the weighted

More information

The Algebra of Fuzzy Truth Values

The Algebra of Fuzzy Truth Values The Algebra of Fuzzy Truth Values Carol L. Walker and Elbert A. Walker New Mexico State University Department of Mathematical Sciences Las Cruces, NM 88003, USA Abstract The purpose of this paper is to

More information

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun Faculty of Business and Law School of Accounting, Economics and Finance ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16 Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun The

More information

Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory

Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory Chapter 12: Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University 1 1 Introduction In this chapter, we consider a society with I 2 individuals, each of them endowed

More information

Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering

Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering Mathematical Methods for Physics and Engineering Lecture notes for PDEs Sergei V. Shabanov Department of Mathematics, University of Florida, Gainesville, FL 32611 USA CHAPTER 1 The integration theory

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE) EconS 3 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE). Based on MWG 9.B.3 Consider the three-player nite game of perfect information depicted in gure. L R Player 3 l r a b

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory Metainduction in Operational Set Theory Luis E. Sanchis Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Syracuse University Syracuse, NY 13244-4100 Sanchis@top.cis.syr.edu http://www.cis.syr.edu/

More information

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES NATHANIEL GALLUP 1. Introduction Number theory begins as the study of the natural numbers the integers N = {1, 2, 3,...}, Z = { 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3,...}, and sometimes

More information

Introduction to Real Analysis

Introduction to Real Analysis Christopher Heil Introduction to Real Analysis Chapter 0 Online Expanded Chapter on Notation and Preliminaries Last Updated: January 9, 2018 c 2018 by Christopher Heil Chapter 0 Notation and Preliminaries:

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Ranking completely uncertain decisions by the uniform expected utility criterion

Ranking completely uncertain decisions by the uniform expected utility criterion Ranking completely uncertain decisions by the uniform expected utility criterion Nicolas Gravel y, Thierry Marchant z and Arunava Sen x February 28th 2008 Keywords: Complete Ignorance, uncertainy, uniform

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

Products, Relations and Functions

Products, Relations and Functions Products, Relations and Functions For a variety of reasons, in this course it will be useful to modify a few of the settheoretic preliminaries in the first chapter of Munkres. The discussion below explains

More information

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2

Solutions for Homework Assignment 2 Solutions for Homework Assignment 2 Problem 1. If a,b R, then a+b a + b. This fact is called the Triangle Inequality. By using the Triangle Inequality, prove that a b a b for all a,b R. Solution. To prove

More information

Cartesian Products and Relations

Cartesian Products and Relations Cartesian Products and Relations Definition (Cartesian product) If A and B are sets, the Cartesian product of A and B is the set A B = {(a, b) : (a A) and (b B)}. The following points are worth special

More information

The Expected Utility Model

The Expected Utility Model 1 The Expected Utility Model Before addressing any decision problem under uncertainty, it is necessary to build a preference functional that evaluates the level of satisfaction of the decision maker who

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

A division algorithm

A division algorithm A division algorithm Fred Richman Florida Atlantic University Boca Raton, FL 33431 richman@fau.edu Abstract A divisibility test of Arend Heyting, for polynomials over a eld in an intuitionistic setting,

More information

Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom

Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom Ezra Einy y and Ori Haimanko z Abstract We show that the Shapley-Shubik power index on the domain of simple (voting) games

More information

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries

Chapter 2. Decision Making under Risk. 2.1 Consequences and Lotteries Chapter 2 Decision Making under Risk In the previous lecture I considered abstract choice problems. In this section, I will focus on a special class of choice problems and impose more structure on the

More information

2 Garrett: `A Good Spectral Theorem' 1. von Neumann algebras, density theorem The commutant of a subring S of a ring R is S 0 = fr 2 R : rs = sr; 8s 2

2 Garrett: `A Good Spectral Theorem' 1. von Neumann algebras, density theorem The commutant of a subring S of a ring R is S 0 = fr 2 R : rs = sr; 8s 2 1 A Good Spectral Theorem c1996, Paul Garrett, garrett@math.umn.edu version February 12, 1996 1 Measurable Hilbert bundles Measurable Banach bundles Direct integrals of Hilbert spaces Trivializing Hilbert

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Piero Gottardi EUI Sept. 26, 2016 Piero Gottardi (EUI) Microeconomics, Block I Part 1 Sept. 26, 2016 1 / 53 Choice Theory Set of alternatives: X, with generic elements x,

More information