Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information"

Transcription

1 Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz x September 203 Abstract We show that under standard assumptions a Tullock contest with asymmetric information has a pure strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Next we study common-value Tullock contests. We show that in equilibrium the expected payo of a player is greater or equal to that of any other player with less information, i.e., an information advantage is rewarded. Moreover, if there are only two players and one of then has an information advantage, then in the unique equilibrium both players exert the same expected e ort, although the less informed player wins the prize more frequently. These latter properties do not extend to contests with more than two players. Interestingly, players may exert more e ort in a Tullock contest than in an all-pay auction. JEL Classi cation: C72, D44, D82. Moreno gratefully acknowledges nancial support from the Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación, grant ECO y Department of Economics, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev. z Departamento de Economía, Universidad Carlos III de Madrid. x Department of Economics, University of Haifa.

2 Introduction In a Tullock contest see Tullock (980) each player s probability of winning the prize is the ratio of the e ort he exerts and the total e ort exerted by all players. Baye and Hoppe (2003) have identi ed a variety of economic settings (rent-seeking, innovation tournaments, patent races) which are strategically equivalent to a Tullock contest. Tullock contests also arise by design, e.g., in sport competition, internal labor markets. A number of studies have provided an axiomatic justi cation to such contests, see, e.g., Skaperdas (996) and Clark and Riis (998)). There is an extensive literature studying Tullock contests, and its variations, with complete information. Perez-Castrillo and Verdier (992), Baye Kovenock and de Vries (994), Szidarovszky and Okuguchi (997), Cornes and Hartley (2005), Yamazaki (2008) and Chowdhury and Sheremeta (2009) study existence and uniqueness of equilibrium. Skaperdas and Gan (995), Glazer and Konrad (999), Konrad (2002), Cohen and Sela (2005) and Franke et al. (20) look into the e ects of changes in the payo structure on the behavior of players, and Schweinzer and Segev (202) and Fu and Lu (203) study optimal prize structures. See Konrad (2008) for a general survey. Tullock contests with asymmetric information, the topic of the present paper, have been seldom investigated in the literature see Fey (2008) and Wasser (203) for a recent analysis of rent-seeking games under incomplete information. In our setting, each player s value for the prize as well as his cost of e ort depend on the state of nature. The set of states of nature is nite. Players have a common prior belief, but upon the realization of the state of nature, and prior to taking action, each player observes some event that contains the realized state of nature. The information of each player at the moment of taking action is described by a partition of the set of states of nature. A contest is therefore formally described by a set of players, a probability space describing players uncertainty and their prior belief, a collection of partitions of the state space describing the players information, a collection of state-dependent functions describing the players values and costs, and a success function specifying the probability distribution that is used to allocate the prize for each pro le of e orts. This representation is equivalent to Harsanyi s model of Bayesian games that uses players types see Jackson (993) and Vohra (999). (In a similar framework, Einy et al. (200, 2002), Forges and Orzach (20), and Malueg

3 and Orzach (2009, 202) study common-value rst- and second-price auctions.) We show that if players cost functions are continuously di erentiable, strictly increasing and convex with respect to e ort, then a Tullock contest has a pure strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Our existence result applies regardless of whether players have private or common values, or whether their costs of e ort is the same or di erent, and makes no assumptions about the players private information. Moreover, our result extends to a general class of Tullock-like contests in which success function is given by the ratio between the score given to a player s e ort and the total scores given to all players, provided each player s score function is strictly increasing and concave. Our proof of existence of equilibrium involves constructing a sequence of equilibria of contests obtained from the original Tullock contest by truncating the action space so that it is a closed and bounded interval, whose lower bound approaches zero from above. We show that any limit point of a sequence of equilibria of these contests, which have an equilibrium by Nash s (existence) theorem, is an equilibrium of the original Tullock contest. A key step in the proof is to show that in any such limit point the total e ort exerted by players is positive in every state of nature. To our knowledge, there are no previous results in the literature on Tullock contests establishing existence of equilibrium by appealing to Nash s theorem. Next we study Tullock contests in which players have a common value for the prize and a common state independent linear cost function, to which we refer simply as common-value Tullock contests. We show that in any equilibrium of a commonvalue Tullock contests, the payo of a player is greater or equal to that of any other player with less information. Thus, a common-value Tullock contests rewards any information advantage. This result, which is a direct implication of a theorem of Einy, Moreno and Shitovitz (2002) showing that in any Bayesian Cournot equilibrium of an oligopolistic industry a rm s information advantage is rewarded, is established by observing the formal equivalence between a common-value Tullock contest and an oligopoly with asymmetric information. We then proceed to study other properties of the equilibria of common-value The payo functions in the truncated contests are continuous and concave in players own strategies, which allows the use of the Nash s theorem. However, it cannot be applied to the original, untruncated, contest, in which payo s have a discontinuity when all e orts are equal to zero. 2

4 Tullock contests. We show that a two-player contest in which one of the players has an information advantage over his opponent (i.e., the partition of one player is ner than that of his opponent) has a unique (pure strategy) Bayesian Nash equilibrium, which we characterize. 2 In equilibrium both players exert the same expected e ort, although the player with less information wins the prize more frequently. We also examine how players information a ects the e ort they exert and their payo s. Assuming that the distribution of the players value for the prize is not too disperse, we show that when one player is better informed than the other the total e ort exerted by the players is smaller, and thus the share of the total surplus they capture is larger, than when both players have the same information. However, these properties of equilibrium of two-player contests do not extend to contests with more than two players. Speci cally, we construct a three-player contest in which two of the players have symmetric information, which is superior to that of the third player, in which the expected e orts exerted by players di er. We also provide an example of a contest in which a player that has an information advantage over all other players, who have symmetric information, wins the prize with a greater ex-ante probability than that of any other player. Our results for two-player common-value Tullock contests are akin to those established by Warneryd (2003) in a setting where players common value is a continuous random variable, assuming that one player observes the value precisely while the other player does not observe anything. In our framework, our results apply whenever one player s information partition is ner than that of his opponent, i.e., whenever the players information endowments can be ranked. It is unclear whether this is also the case when players common value is a continuous random variable. Finally, we study the relative e ectiveness of Tullock contests and all-pay auctions in inducing the players to exert e ort. Einy et al. (203) characterize the unique equilibrium of a two-player common-value all-pay auction, which is in mixed strategies, and provide an explicit formula that allows to compute the players total e ort. Using the results in Einy et al. (203) and our results we show that the sign of the di erence in the total e ort exerted by players in a Tullock contest and an all-pay 2 Warneryd (202) establishes existence of equilibrium when there are two types of players, and investigates which players are active, i.e., make a positive e ort, in equilibrium. 3

5 auction is undetermined, and may be either positive or negative depending on the distribution of the players value for the prize. (Fang (2002) and Epstein, Mealem and Nitzan (20) study the outcomes of Tullock contests and all-pay auction under complete information.) The rest of the paper is organized as follows: in Section 2 we describe the general setting. In Section 3 we establish that every Tullock contest has a pure strategy Bayesian Nash equilibrium. In Section 4 we study common-value Tullock contests. Section 5 studies the relative e ectiveness of common-values Tullock contests and all pay auction in inducing players to exert e ort. Long proofs are given in the Appendix. 2 Tullock Contests A group of players N = f; :::; ng; with n 2; compete for a prize by choosing a level of e ort in R +. Players uncertainty about the state of nature is described by a probability space (; p); where is a nite set and p is a probability distribution over describing the players common prior belief about the realized state of nature. W.l.o.g. we assume that p(!) > 0 for every! 2. The private information about the state of nature of player i 2 N is described by a partition i of : The value for the prize of each player i is given by a random variable V i :! R ++, i.e., if! 2 is realized then player i s ( private ) value for the prize is V i (!). The cost of e ort of each player i 2 N is described by a function c i : R +! R +, which is continuously di erentiable, strictly increasing and convex in e ort x i, and such that c i (; 0) = 0 on : A contest starts by a move of nature that selects a state! from according to the distribution p: Every player i 2 N observes the element i (!) of i which contains! the set of states of nature between which i cannot distinguish given!. Then players simultaneously choose their e ort levels (x ; :::; x n ) 2 R n +. The prize is awarded in a probabilistic fashion, according to a success function ; which attributes to each pro le of e ort levels x 2 R n + a probability distribution (x) in the n-simplex according to which the prize recipient is chosen. Hence, the payo of player i 2 N; u i : R n +! R, is given for every! 2 and x 2 R n + by u i (!; x) = i (x) V i (!) c i (!; x i ) : () 4

6 Thus, a contest is described by a collection (N; (; p); f i g i2n ; fv i g i2n ; fc i g i2n ; ): In a contest, a pure strategy of player i 2 N is a i -measurable function X i :! R + (i.e., X i is constant on every element of i ); that represents i s choice of e ort in each state of nature following the observation of his private information. We denote by S i the set of strategies of player i, and by S = n i=s i the set of strategy pro les. For any strategy X i 2 S i and i 2 i ; X i ( i ) stands for the constant value that X i () takes on i. Also, given a strategy pro le X = (X ; :::; X n ) 2 S; we denote by X i the pro le obtained from X by suppressing the strategy of player i 2 N: Throughout the paper we restrict attention to pure strategies. Let X = (X ; :::; X n ) be a strategy pro le. We denote by U i (X) the expected payo of player i, which is given by U i (X) E[u i (; (X () ; :::; X n ())]: For i 2 i ; we denote by U i (X j i ) the expected payo of player i conditional on i ; i.e., U i (X j i ) E[u i (; (X () ; :::; X n ()) j i ]: An N-tuple of strategies X = (X; :::; XN ) is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium if for every player i 2 N, and every strategy X i 2 S i U i (X ) U i (X i; X i ); (2) or equivalently, for every i 2 i : U i (X j i ) U i (X i; X i j i ) (3) 3 Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests Tullock contests are identi ed by a class of success functions T such that for x 2 R n +nf0g the probability that player i 2 N wins the prize is T i (x) = x i x ; (4) where x P N k= x k is the total e ort exerted by the players. Theorem establishes existence of equilibrium in Tullock contests. 5

7 Theorem. Every Tullock contest has a (pure strategy) Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Theorem makes no assumptions about players private information, and applies regardless of whether players have private or common values, or whether their costs of e ort are the same or di erent. Theorem also implies existence of a Bayesian Nash equilibrium in a Tullock contest in the Harsanyi types model, where each player s uncertain type represents his private information, and players have a common prior distribution over all possible realizations of types. (In the discrete case, these two models of incomplete information games are equivalent see Jackson (993) and Vohra (999).) The proof of Theorem, given in the Appendix, relies on Nash s theorem. Nash s theorem, however, cannot be applied directly to a Tullock contest because the expected payo functions have a discontinuity when all e orts are equal to zero in some state of nature. Truncated contests, where players are forced to choose e orts from a compact interval with a positive lower bound, need to be considered instead then the expected payo functions are continuous and concave in players own strategies, which allows the use of the Nash s theorem to deduce the existence of equilibrium. However, in order for a limit point of the sequence of equilibria of truncated contests with a lower bound on players e orts approaching zero to be an equilibrium in the original contest the upper hemi-continuity property the expected payo functions must be continuous at the limit strategy pro le, and this holds provided the total e ort in the limit pro le is positive in all states of nature. Establishing the latter property is the crux of the proof of Theorem. A direct implication of Theorem is Corollary below, which establishes existence of equilibrium for a general class of success functions. The proof of Corollary proceeds by rst showing the existence of equilibrium in scores, and then in e orts, which is an argument familiar in the literature studying equilibrium under complete information see Corchon (2007). Existence of equilibrium in contests with success functions belonging to this class was established for the complete information case by Szidarovszky and Okuguchi (997). Theorem and Corollary extend their result into the incomplete information setting, employing a noticeably di erent method of proof. 6

8 Corollary. Every contest in which the success function is given for x 2 R n +nf0g and i 2 N by i (x) = g i (x i ) P n j= g j (x j ) ; where, for every j 2 N; his score function g j : R +! R + is a strictly increasing and concave bijection 3, has a Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Proof. Let C = (N; (; p); f i g i2n ; fv i g i2n ; fc i g i2n ; ) be a contest satisfying the assumptions of Corollary for (g ; :::; g n ). The Tullock contest (N; (; p); f i g i2n ; fv i g i2n ; fc i g i2n ; T ) where c i (; ) = c i ; g i () for every i 2 N and T (0) = (0) has an equilibrium X = (X ; :::; X n) by Theorem. It is easy to see that Y = (g X; :::; gn Xn) is an equilibrium of C: 4 Common-Value Tullock Contests Henceforth we study contests in which players have a common value for the prize and a common state-independent linear cost function, i.e., for all i 2 N; V i = V; and c i (; x) x on. We refer to these contests as common-value contests, and they are described by a collection (N; (; p); ( i ) i2n ; V; ). We say that player i 2 N has an information advantage over player j 2 N if partition i is ner than partition j : Thus, if i has an information advantage over j; then i (!) j (!) for every! 2 ; i.e., player i knows the realized state of nature with at least the same precision as player j. We begin by establishing in Theorem 2 a general property of common-value Tullock contests: these contests reward information advantage. This is a direct implication of the theorem of Einy, Moreno and Shitovitz (2002), that shows that information advantage is rewarded in any Bayesian Cournot equilibrium of a symmetric oligopolistic industry in which the rms cost function is linear. 3 Functions g j do not, in fact, need to be bijections, for our claim to hold. This can be shown using the same argument as in the proof below, provided Theorem is extended to hold for contests where the levels of e ort are restricted to be in a set [a; b) for 0 a b and b 2 R + [ fg (under the additional assumption that lim x!b c i (; x) = ). This extension of Theorem can be obtained by essentially the same proof as the one given in the Appendix. 7

9 Theorem 2. Let X = (X ; :::; X n) be any equilibrium of an n-player commonvalue Tullock contest. If player i has an information advantage over player j, then U i (X ) U j (X ). Proof. An n-player common-value Tullock contest (N; (; p); ( i ) i2n ; V ) is formally identical to an oligopolist industry (N; (; p); P; c; ( i ) i2n ); where the market demand P and the cost function c are de ned for (!; x) 2 R ++ as and P (!; x) = V (!) x ; c(!; x) = x; respectively. With this convention, the state-dependent pro t of rm i 2 N in the industry coincides with the payo of player i 2 N in the contest, i.e., for! 2 and X 2 S; u i (!; X) = V (!) P n s= X s X i (!) X i (!) = P (!; nx X s (!))X i (!) c(!; X i (!)): s= Theorem 2 then follows from the theorem of Einy, Moreno and Shitovitz (2002). 4 Next we study other properties of common-value Tullock contests. Let us index the set of states of nature as = f! ; :::;! m g: For k = ; :::; m, write and w.l.o.g. assume that p(! k ) = p k and V (! k ) = v k ; 0 < v v 2 ::: v m : We begin by studying two-player contests in which player 2 has an information advantage over player. Thus, we may assume w.l.o.g. that the only information player 4 The demand function P (!; x) is not di erentiable at x = 0 it is not even de ned and therefore does not formally satisfy the assumptions of Einy, Moreno and Shitovitz (2002). However, it is easy to see that in any equilibrium X of a common-value Tullock contest the total e ort is positive in all states of nature, i.e., X() > 0: Thus the non-di erentiability at 0 is irrelevant, and the proof of the theorem in Einy, Moreno and Shitovitz (2002) applies in this case with no change. 8

10 has about the state is the common prior belief, i.e., = fg, whereas player 2 has perfect information about the state of nature, i.e., 2 = ff! g; :::; f! m gg. In such contests a strategy pro le is a pair (X; Y ); where X can be identi ed with a number x 2 R + specifying player s unconditional e ort, and Y can be identi ed with a vector (y ; :::; y m ) 2 R m + specifying the e ort of player 2 in each of the m states of nature. Thus, abusing notation, we shall write X = x and Y = (y ; :::; y m ) whenever appropriate. The following notation will be useful in characterizing the pure strategy Bayesian Nash equilibria of a contest. For k 2 f; :::; mg write Note that A k =! p vs s=k + A = E(p V ) : 2 Lemma establishes a key property of the sequence fa k g m k= :! : (5) s=k Lemma. If k > k: p vk > A k for some k < m; then p v k > A k and A k > A k for all Proposition shows that a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage has a unique pure strategy equilibrium, which is calculated explicitly. Let k 2 f; :::; mg be the smallest index such that p v k > A k : Since k is well de ned. p vm > p m p vm = A m ; ( + p m ) Proposition. A two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage has a unique Bayesian Nash equilibrium (X ; Y ) given by x = A 2 k ; and 8 < 0 if k < k yk = : p A k vk A k otherwise. 9

11 Proposition in particular implies uniqueness and symmetry of equilibrium in the complete information case, i.e., when m =. (Note that in this case k = ; and therefore y = A ( p v A ) = v =2 v =4 = A 2 = x. This result is well known in the literature.) When m >, we have p v > A = E( p V )=2 (and hence k = ) whenever the distribution of values is not too disperse; e.g., this inequality holds when v m < 4v : When this is the case, the unique equilibrium is interior. For future references we state this observation in Remark 2. Remark 2. Consider a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage. The unique Bayesian Nash equilibrium is interior if and only if p v > E( p V )=2, i.e., the distribution of values is not too disperse. Interestingly, when one player has superior information the expected e ort exerted by players in the equilibrium of the contest is the same. Proposition 2. In a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage both players exert the same (expected) e ort, i.e., E(Y ) = A 2 k = x = X : (6) Hence the expected total e ort is T E = X + E(Y ) = 2A 2 k : Proof. By Proposition, E(Y ) = ys s= = A k ( p v k s=k A k ) = p A k vk A 2 k s=k = A 2 k + m X = A 2 k : s=k! s=k X m A 2 k p s s=k 0

12 In a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage the equilibrium probability that player wins the prize when the state is! k is k := T (x ; y k) = A 2 k + A k A 2 k p vk = A k p A k vk when k k ; whereas the probability that player 2 wins the prize is 2k = k : Thus, the larger is the realized value of the prize, the smaller (larger) is the probability that player (player 2) wins the prize, i.e., k 0 k and 2k 0 2k for k0 > k k ; with a strict inequality if v k 0 prize, the larger is the e ort of player 2, i.e., > v k : Of course, the larger is the realized value of the y k 0 = A k (p v k 0 A k ) A k ( p v k A k ) = y k: for k 0 > k k (with a strict inequality if v k 0 > v k ). Additionally, for k 0 > k k ; k 0v k 0 = A k p vk 0 A k p vk = kv k (with a strict inequality if v k 0 > v k ), i.e., the larger is the realized value of the prize, the larger is the conditional expected payo of player ; also, 2k 0v k 0 2kv k 0 2kv k (with a strict inequality if v k 0 > v k ), i.e., the larger is the realized value of the prize, the larger is the conditional expected payo of player 2. Write i = E( i ) for the ex-ante probability that player i wins the prize. Proposition 3 establishes another interesting property of equilibrium. Proposition 3. Consider a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage. If v < v 2 < ::: < v m, then the ex-ante probability that player wins the prize is greater than that of player 2, i.e., > 2: The next Remark 3 is a corollary of propositions and 2, and its straightforward proof if omitted. Remark 3. A two-player common-value Tullock contest in which players have symmetric information has a unique pure strategy equilibrium, in which each player exerts the same expected e ort, equal to E(V )=4:

13 The surplus captured by the players in a contest is the di erence between the expected (total) surplus E(V ) and the expected total e ort they exert. In Proposition 4 below we show that asymmetry of information leads, in an interior equilibrium, to exertion of less e ort, and therefore to the capture a greater share of surplus, compared to the symmetric information case. Proposition 4. Consider a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage. If v < v m and the distribution of values is not too disperse, i.e., p v > E( p V )=2, then the players exert less e ort and hence capture a greater share of the surplus than when both players have symmetric information. Proof. When player 2 has an information advantage, then p v > E( p V )=2 implies that the equilibrium is interior by Remark 2, and therefore the expected total e ort is T E = 2A 2 = E( p 2 V ) =2 by Proposition 2. When players have symmetric information the expected total e ort T E is T E = E(V )=2 by Remark 3. v < v m together with Jensen s inequality imply T E T E = E(V ) 2 E( p V ) 2 2 > 0: The following example illustrates our ndings for two-player contests. Then Example. Let m = 2, p = p; v = ; and v 2 = v; where p 2 (0; ) and v 2 (; ): Then E(V ) = p( v), E( p p V ) = p( v); A = E( p V )=2, and A 2 = p p v=( + p): If v < ( + p) 2 =p 2 ; then p v = > A and k = ; otherwise k = 2: In a Tullock contest in which player 2 observes the value but player does not, the unique equilibrium is X = A 2 ; Y = (A ( A ) ; A p v A ); and the total e ort is T E = 2A 2 = [ p( Otherwise, the unique equilibrium is p v)] 2 =2 when v < ( + p) 2 =p 2. X = A 2 2; Y = (0; A 2 p v A2 ); and the total e ort is T E = 2A 2 2 = 2p 2 v=(+p) 2 : If v < ( + p) 2 =p 2 ; then the ex-ante probability that player wins the prize is = ( p) A + p A p v = 2 p + ( p)p v p + p p v p v + p > 2 : 2

14 Otherwise, this probability is = ( p) + p A 2 p v = ( p) + p2 + p = + p > 2 : Hence, consistent with Proposition 3 the uninformed player wins the prize more frequently than the informed player. Further, if v < ( + p) 2 =p 2, then 2 [U 2 (X ; Y ) U (X ; Y )] = ( p) A ( A ) A 2 A 2 + A ( A ) + pv A p ( v A ) A 2 A 2 + A ( p v A ) p 2 = ( p) p v And if v ( + p) 2 =p 2, then > 0: 2 [U 2 (X ; Y ) U (X ; Y )] = ( p) + pv A 2 ( p v A 2 ) A 2 2 A A 2 ( p v A 2 ) = p (p(v p + ) ) > p p > 0: That is, consistent with Theorem 2, the payo of the informed player is greater or equal to that of the uninformed player. Under symmetric information the equilibrium total e ort in a Tullock contest is E(V )=2 > maxf2a 2 ; 2A 2 2g; i.e., the total e ort when player 2 has an information advantage is less than when both players have the same information. Warneryd (2003) establishes counterparts to propositions to 4 when the players common-value V is a continuous random variable, and also shows that the fully informed player obtains a greater payo than the uninformed player. This latter result also holds when V is a discrete random variable, according to Theorem 2, and in fact extends to contests with three or more players in a very general way when a player has an information advantage (not necessarily an extreme one) over some other player, then in any equilibrium the expected payo of the former is greater or equal to that of the latter. The following examples show that the properties established in propositions 2 and 3 do not extend to common-value Tullock contests with more than two players. 3

15 In Example 2 player has only the prior information whereas players 2 and 3 have complete information. In equilibrium the expected e ort of the uninformed player is below that of each of the informed players. Example 2. Consider a 3-player common-value Tullock contest in which m = 2; p = p 2 = =2, v = and v 2 = 2: Player has no information, i.e., his information partition is = f! ;! 2 g; and players 2 and 3 have complete information, i.e., their information partitions are 2 = 3 = ff! g; f! 2 gg: In the interior equilibrium of this contest, which is readily calculated by solving the system of equations formed by the players reaction functions, the e ort of player is X = 0:30899 while the e orts of players 2 and 3 are X 2 = X 3 = (0:20342; 0:46933). Note that X = 0:30899 < 2 (0: :46933) = E(X 2) = E(X 3); i.e., the e ort of player is less than the expected e ort of players 2 and 3. In Example 3 there is an informed player and a number of uninformed players. In equilibrium, the ex-ante probability that the informed player wins the prize is above that of the uninformed players. Thus, the natural extension of Proposition 3 to contests with more than two players does not hold. Example 3. Consider an eight player common-value Tullock contest in which m = 2; p = p 2 = =2, v = and v 2 = 2: Players to 7 have no information, i.e., their information partition is i = f! ;! 2 g for i 2 f; :::; 7g; and player 8 is completely informed, i.e., his information partitions is 8 = ff! g; f! 2 gg: This contest has a (corner) equilibrium given by X = ::: = X 7 = 0:555; X 8 = (0; 0:38694) : In equilibrium, the ex-ante probability that player i 2 f; 2; :::; 7g wins the prize is i = 2 ( 7 + 0:55 5 7(0:55 5) + 0: ) = 0:243; whereas the ex-ante probability that player 8 win the prize is 8 = 7(0:243) = 0:309: Thus, the informed player wins the prize more frequently than an uninformed player. 4

16 5 Common-Value Tullock and All-Pay Auction Contests Contests that arise in many economic and political applications are e ectively all-pay auctions either by design (e.g., sports or political competition) or by the nature of the problem (e.g., patent races). Here we study whether the players expected total e ort in all pay auctions and Tullock contests can be ranked. A common-value all-pay auction is a common-value contest in which the success function is given for x 2 R n + by AP A (x) = =m(x) if x i = maxfx j g j2n ; and AP A (x) = 0 otherwise, where m(x) = jk 2 N : x k = maxfx j g j2n j. Einy et. al. (203) show that in the unique equilibrium of a two-player common-value all-pay auction in which v < ::: < v m and player 2 observes the value while player does not, the players total expected e ort is! Xs T E AP A = 2 p k v k + 2 v s = 2 s= k= s= X p k v k + s k= p 2 sv s : Hence the di erence between total e orts in an all-pay auction and a Tullock contest is := T E AP A T E = 2 s= X p k v k + s k= s= p 2 sv s 2A 2 k : For simplicity, consider the case where there are only two states of nature, i.e., m = 2: If the equilibrium of the Tullock contest is interior, then = 2p p 2 v + p 2 v + p 2 2v 2 2A 2 = 2p p 2 v + p 2 v + p 2 2v 2 2 p p p 2 v + p 2 v2 4 = 2p p 2 v + 2 (p p p v p 2 v2 ) 2 > 0: Hence an all-pay auction generates more e ort that a Tullock contest. However, if the Tullock contest has a corner equilibrium, then = 2p p 2 v + p 2 v + p 2 2v 2 2A 2 2 = 2p p 2 v + p 2 v + p 2 2v 2 2 p p 2 2 v2 ( + p 2 ) 2 = p v ( + p 2 ) p 2 2 2v 2 ( + p 2 ) 2 : 5 s=

17 We show that may be either positive or negative depending on the distribution of the players common value. Consider the environment described in Example. In an all pay auction in which player 2 observes the value but player does not, the equilibrium total e ort is T E AP A = 2 ( p) p + ( p) 2 + p 2 v = ( p) ( + p) + p 2 v: As we have shown above, if v < ( + p) 2 =p 2 ; then the expected total e ort in the unique equilibrium of the Tullock contest, which is interior, is T E = 2A 2 2 = [ p( p v)] 2 =2: Hence T E AP A T E = ( p) ( + p) + p 2 v ( p( 2 p v)) 2 > 2p > 0: However, if v ( + p) 2 =p 2 ; then the expected total e ort in the unique equilibrium of the Tullock contest, which is a corner equilibrium, is T E = 2p 2 v= ( + p) 2 : Assume that p = =4. Then T E AP A T E = v: Hence T E AP A < T E for v > 375=7. Therefore the level of e ort generated by these two contests cannot be ranked in general. 6 Appendix Proof of Theorem. Let C = (N; (; p); f i g i2n ; fv i g i2n ; fc i g i2n ; T ) be a Tullock contest. Since the cost function of each player is strictly increasing and convex in the player s e ort, it follows from () that there exists Q > 0 such that u i (; x) < 0 for every i 2 N and every x 2 R n +; provided x i Q: For any 0 < " < Q consider a variant of the contest, denoted by C " ; in which the e ort set of each player i is restricted to be the bounded interval ["; Q] : In C " ; the set of strategies of player i, S i;", is identi able with the compact set ["; Q] i via the the bijection x i! (x i ( i )) i 2 i. Player i s expected payo function U i is continuous on S " = n i=s i;" (since the success function in (4) is continuous if e orts are restricted to ["; Q]), and it is concave in i s own strategy (as the state-dependent payo function u i (; x) is concave in the variable x i if e orts are restricted to ["; Q]). Nash s theorem thus guarantees 6

18 existence of a Bayesian Nash equilibrium in C " ; pick one such equilibrium and denote it by X " = (X ;"; :::; X n;"). We show that lim inf "!0+ X " () > 0: Indeed, suppose to the contrary that there is a vanishing positive sequence f" k g k= such that and x! 2 such that lim min k!!2 X " k (! ) = min!2 X " k (!) = 0; (7) X " k (!) (8) for in nitely many k (and thus, w.l.o.g., for every k). Since the expected payo of player i is negative in every state of nature when x i = Q; for any su ciently small " k the equilibrium strategy X i;" k satis es X i;" k () < Q: Thus, for a given i 2 i ; X i ( i ) 2 [" k ; Q): Additionally, X i and X i ( i ) can both be viewed as the argument of the function U i (X i;" k ; X i j i ); since X i ( i ) is the only numerical input needed to determine the conditional expected payo of player i given i ; when the equilibrium strategies of players other than i are X i;" k. Since the equilibrium strategy X i;" k (local) maximizer of U i (X i;" k ; X i j i ) by (3), du i (X i;" k ; X i ; j i ) dx i ( i ) 0: Xi ( i )=Xi;"k ( i) is a That is, de[u i (; X i;" k () ; X i ( i ) j i ] dx i ( i ) 0; Xi ( i )=Xi;"k ( i) or, equivalently, dui (; X i;" E k () ; Xi;" k ( i )) j i 0: dx i Using (4) and () we calculate the derivative explicitly, " V i () Xi;" E k ( i ) V i () d X " k () X " k () 2 c i ; Xi;" dx k ( i ) # j i 0: i Thus E Vi () X " k () d dx i c i ; X i;" k ( i ) j i X i;" k ( i ) E " # V i () X " k () 2 j i 0; 7

19 which leads to X i;" k ( i ) Vi () d E c X " i ; Xi;" k () dx k ( i ) j i i " # : (9) V i () E X " k () 2 j i Inequality (9) holds, in particular, for i = i (! ) : Since X i;" k (! ) = X i;" k ( i (! )) (as, by de nition,! 2 i (! )); (9) yields Vi () d E c X Xi;" k (! " i ; Xi;" ) k () dx k (! ) j i (! ) i " # : (0) V i () E X " k () 2 j i (! ) Summing over i 2 N we obtain Vi () d E c nx X X " k (! i ; Xi;" " ) k () dx k (! ) j i (! ) i " # ; i= V i () E X " k () 2 j i (! ) or (since X " k (! ) n" > 0) X "k (! ) E nx X " k () V i() X "k (! ) d dx i c i ; Xi;" k (! ) j i (! ) " # : () X "k (! ) 2 E X " k () 2 V i() j i (! ) i= By the de nition of X " k (! ) (see (8)), 0 X " k (! ) X " k (!) for every! 2 : Hence we assume w.l.o.g. (by moving to a subsequence if necessary) that the limit a (!) = lim k! X "k (! ) X " k (!) exists for every! 2 : Note also that a (!) = for! =!, which occurs with positive probability by our assumption on p; and thus " # X lim E "k (! ) 2 k! X " k () 2 V i() j i (! ) = E a () 2 V i () j i (! ) > 0: (2) 8

20 Also, (7) and (8) imply lim E k! " X " k (! ) dc i ; Xi;" k (! ) # j i (! ) = 0: (3) dx i Taking limit of the right-hand side of (), which exists by (2) and (3), we get nx i= E[a () V i () j i (! )] E[a () 2 V i () j i (! )] : Furthermore, as 0 a () 2 a () ; we obtain nx i= E[a () V i () j i (! )] E[a () 2 V i () j i (! )] n: Since by assumption n 2; we have reached a contradiction. indeed, lim inf "!0+ This proves that, X " () > 0: (4) Now let f" k g k= be a vanishing positive sequence such that the limit X i (!) lim k! X i;" k (!) exists for every i 2 N and! 2 : (Such a sequence exists since all X i;" (!) belong to the compact interval [0; Q]:) Obviously, X = (X ; :::; X n) constitutes a strategy pro le in the contest C; and it follows from (4) that X () > 0: (5) We show that X is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of C. Since the state-dependent payo function u i (; x) is continuous at any point x with x > 0, for every i 2 N, every i 2 i ; and every sequence fy k g k=0 of strategy pro les such that Y 0 () > 0 and Y i;0 (!) = lim k! Y i;k (!) for every i and!; we have lim U i(y ;k ; :::; Y n;k j i ) = U i (Y ;0 ; :::; Y n;0 j i ): (6) k! Since every X " is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium in C " ; for every su ciently large k and every strategy X i of player i satisfying 0 < X i () Q we have U i (X " k j i) U i (X i;" k ; X i j i ): (7) 9

21 Applying the limit as k! to both sides of inequality (7), it follows from (6) (and the fact (5)) that U i (X j i ) U i (X i; X i j i ) (8) for every strategy X i of player i satisfying 0 < X i () Q and every i 2 i : It is easy to see that lim inf x i!0+ U i(x i; x i j i ) U i (X i; 0 j i ); where x i > 0 (respectively, x i = 0) is identi ed with a strategy of i for which X i ( i ) = x i (respectively, X i ( i ) = 0): Thus (8) in fact holds for every strategy X i satisfying 0 X i () Q (i.e., the deviations of i may be zero at some states of nature). Finally, note that player i can improve upon any strategy X i for which X i (!) > Q at some! by lowering the e ort on i (!) to zero and thus receiving non-negative expected payo conditional on i (!): Thus, in contemplating a unilateral deviation from X i ; player i is never worse o by limiting himself to strategies X i satisfying 0 X i () Q: But this implies that (8) holds for every strategy X i 2 S i : Since this is the case for every i 2 N, we have shown that X is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of C. Proof of Lemma. Assume that p v k > A k for some k < m: We show that p v k > A k for all k > k: Suppose not; let ^k > k be the rst index k > k such that for p v k A k : Note that v^k v^k and p v^k > A^k imply + s=^k A p v^k > = = + + s=^k + s=^k s=^k A p v^k p^k p v^k A A^k p^k p v^k p vs p^k p v^k s=^k which contradicts the assumption that p v^k A^k: 20 A A^k;

22 Now we show that A k > A k for all k > k: Suppose not; let ~ k > k be the rst index k > k such that A k A k : Since p v ~k > A ~k (as we have just shown), + Hence + s= ~ k s= ~ k i.e., 0 Thus, A k A + Proof of Proposition. A A ~k = s= ~ k p vs = p ~k p v~k + 0 p vs s= ~ k > p ~k A ~k + 0 A A ~k p ~k A ~k + s= ~ k 0 A A ~k + s= ~ k s= ~ k s= ~ k A A ~k : > A ~k ; which contradicts the choice of ~ k. A A ~k : A A ~k ; Let (X; Y ); where X = x and Y = (y ; :::; y m ), be a Bayesian Nash equilibrium, whose existence is guaranteed by Theorem. We show that x > 0: If x = 0; then T 2 (0) = ; since otherwise player 2 does not have a best response against x = 0: But then y = y 2 = ::: = y m = 0; and therefore player can pro tably deviate by exerting an arbitrarily small e ort " > 0: Hence x > 0: Moreover, y k > 0 for some k 2 f; :::; mg since otherwise x > 0 is not a best response of player : Since x > 0 maximizes player s payo s= v s x x + y s! x = y s v s (x + y s ) 2 = 0: (9) And since y s maximizes player 2 s payo in state! s given y s x v s y s = v s x + y s (x + y s ) 2 0; (20) (with equality if y s > 0) for each s = ; :::; m. s= 2

23 Notice next that if y k > 0 for some k < m; then y k 0 > 0 for all k 0 > k: Since x > 0; if y k > 0 then y k = p x p p v k x by (20), and since vk 0 v k for all k 0 > k; p p p x vk 0 x > 0, i.e., x v k 0 > 0; x 2 for all k 0 > k: Then y k 0 = 0 would violate inequality (20) for s = k 0 : Hence y k 0 > 0: Let k be the smallest index such that y k > 0: Thus, (9) implies y s v s (x + y s= s ) 2 = y s v s (x + y s=k s ) 2 = ; and (20) implies y k 0 = p x p p v k 0 x > 0 for all k 0 k : Hence x = A 2 k ; y k = p A k vk A k for all k k ; and y k = 0 for all k < k : We now show that k = k, which establishes that the pro le (x ; y ; :::; y m) identi ed in Proposition is the unique equilibrium. Assume rst that k < k : Then p v k A k since k is the smallest index such that p v k > A k ; and hence y k = p x p p p v k x = Ak vk A k 0; a contradiction as yk > 0 by the de nition of k : Assume next that k > k : In this case, y k = 0: Since p v k > A k ; by Lemma and therefore x v k x 2 This stands in contradiction to (20), as y k conclude that indeed k = k. A 2 k > A2 k = x; (2) = A2 k A 4 k v k A 2 k > 0: = 0 by the de nition of k (> k ): We Proof of Proposition 3. Let us be given a two-player common-value Tullock contest in which player 2 has an information advantage over player. Given (y k ; ::::; y m ) 2 R m k + + de ne the function p 2 (y k ; :::; y m ) := k=k p k y k y k + P m s=k y s : Hence, recalling (6), 2 = p 2 (y k ; :::; y m). We show that a maximum point y of p 2 on K = f(y k ; ::::; y m ) 2 R m k + + j y k y k+ ::: y m g must satisfy y k = ::: = y m : Hence max K p 2 = P m s=k + P m s=k 2 : (22) 22

24 Since yk < ::: < y m (the inequalities are strict, which follows from our assumption that v < v 2 < ::: < v m and the expressions for (y k )m k=k given in Proposition ), (22) implies which establishes Proposition 3. 2 = p 2 (y k ; :::; y m) < max K p 2 =2; Di erentiating p 2 with respect to y k for k 2 fk ; :::; mg we p k = p k t=k ;t6=k p t y t (y k + P m s=k y s ) 2 t=k ;t6=k p t y t (y t + P m s=k y s ) 2! : (23) For every (y k ; :::; y m ) 2 K such that y k < y k + ::: y m p 2 =@y k (y) > 0; and therefore necessarily y k = y k +. Suppose now that it has already been shown that y k = y k + = ::: = y k ; m k > : We show that y k+ = y k as well. Indeed, if y k = y k + = ::: = y k < y k+ ::: y m, then by (23) we obtain p 2 =@y k (y) > 0; a contradiction. Thus y k = ::: = y m : 23

25 References [] Baye, M., Hoppe, H.: The strategic equivalence of rent-seeking, innovation, and patent-race games. Game and Economic Behavior 44(2), (2003). [2] Baye, M., Kovenock, D., de Vries, C.: The solution to the Tullock rent-seeking game when r > 2: mixed-strategy equilibrium and mean dissipation rates. Public Choice 8, (994). [3] Chowdhury, S., Sheremeta, R.: Multiple equilibria in Tullock contests. Economics Letters, 2, (20). [4] Clark, D., Riis, C.: Contest success functions: an extension. Economic Theory, (998). [5] Cohen, C., Sela, A.: Manipulations in contests. Economics Letters 86, (2005). [6] Corchon, L.: The Theory of Contests: A Survey. Review of Economic Design, (2007). [7] Cornes, R., Hartley, R.: Asymmetric contests with general technologies. Economic Theory 26, (2005). [8] Einy, E., Haimanko, O., Orzach, R., Sela, A.: Dominant strategies, superior information and winner s curse in second-price auctions. International Journal of Game Theory 30, (200). [9] Einy, E., Haimanko, O., Orzach, R., Sela, A.: Dominance solvability of secondprice auctions with di erential information. Journal of Mathematical Economics 37, (2002). [0] Einy, E., Haimanko, O., Orzach, R., Sela, A.: Common-value all-pay auctions with asymmetric information. Working paper, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev (203). [] Einy, E., Moreno, D., Shitovitz, B.: Information advantage in Cournot oligopoly, Journal of Economic Theory 06, 5-60 (2002). 24

26 [2] Epstein, G., Mealem Y., Nitzan S.: Political culture and discrimination in contests. Journal of Public Economics 95(-2), (20) [3] Fang, H.: Lottery versus all-pay auction models of lobbying. Public Choice 2, (2002). [4] Fey, M.: Rent-seeking contests with incomplete information. Public Choice 35(3), (2008). [5] Forges, F., Orzach, R.: Core-stable rings in second price auctions with common values. Journal of Mathematical Economics 47, (20). [6] Franke, J., Kanzow, C., Leininger, W., Schwartz, A.: E ort maximization in asymmetric contest games with heterogeneous contestants. Economic Theory, forthcoming (20). [7] Fu, Q., Lu, J.: The optimal multi-stage contest. Economic Theory 5(2), (202). [8] Glazer, A., Konrad, K.: Taxation of rent-seeking activities. Journal of Public Economics 72, 6-72 (999). [9] Jackson, M.: Bayesian implementation. Econometrica 59, (993) [20] Konrad, K.: Investment in the absence of property rights: the role of incumbency advantages. European Economic Review 46(8), (2002). [2] Konrad, K.: Strategy and dynamics in contests. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008). [22] Malueg, D., Orzach, R.: Revenue comparison in common-value auctions: two examples. Economics Letters 05, (2009). [23] Malueg, D., Orzach, R.: Equilibrium and revenue in a family of common-value rst-price auctions with di erential information. International Journal of Game Theory 4(2), (202). [24] Nitzan, S.: Modelling rent-seeking contests. European Journal of Political Economy 0(), 4-60 (994). 25

27 [25] Perez-Castrillo, D., Verdier, T.: A general analysis of rent-seeking games. Public Choice 73, (992). [26] Schweinzer, P., Segev, E.: The optimal prize structure of symmetric Tullock contests. Public Choice 53(), (202). [27] Skaperdas, S.: Contest success functions. Economic Theory 7, (996). [28] Skaperdas, S., Gan, L.: Risk aversion in contests. Economic Journal 05, (995). [29] Szidarovszky, F., Okuguchi, K.: On the existence and uniqueness of pure Nash equilibrium in rent-seeking games. Games and Economic Behavior 8, (997). [30] Tullock, G.: E cient rent-seeking, in J.M. Buchanan, R.D. Tollison and G. Tullock (Eds.), Toward a theory of rent-seeking society. College Station: Texas A.&M. University Press (980). [3] Vohra, R.: Incomplete information, incentive compatibility and the core. Journal of Economic Theory 54, (999). [32] Yamazaki, T.: On the existence and uniqueness of pure-strategy Nash equilibrium in asymmetric rent seeking contests. Journal of Public Economic Theory 0, (2008). [33] Warneryd, K.: Information in con icts, Journal of Economic Theory 0, 2 36 (2003). [34] Warneryd, K.: Multi-player contests with asymmetric information, Economic Theory 5: (202). [35] Wasser, C.: Incomplete information in rent-seeking contests. Economic Theory, 53: (203). 26

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126

Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126 UC3M Working papers Departamento de Economía Economics Universidad Carlos III de Madrid 13-14 Calle Madrid, 126 July, 2013 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34) 916249875 TULLOCK CONTESTS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION

More information

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y

On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y On the Existence of a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information y E. Einy z, O. Haimanko z, D. Moreno x, A. Sela z, and B. Shitovitz { December 2014 Abstract We show that

More information

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y

Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y Tullock Contests with Asymmetric Information y E. Einy z, O. Haimanko z, D. Moreno x, A. Sela z, and B. Shitovitz { July 2014 Abstract We show that under standard assumptions every member of a broad class

More information

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information

Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information Existence of Equilibrium in Tullock Contests with Incomplete Information E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz x December 2014 Abstract We show that under general assumptions

More information

Information Advantage in Tullock Contests

Information Advantage in Tullock Contests Information Advantage in Tullock Contests A. Aiche, E. Einy y, O. Haimanko y, D. Moreno z, A. Sela y, and B. Shitovitz March 2017 Abstract We study the impact of an information advantage on the equilibrium

More information

Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information

Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information Common-Value All-Pay Auctions with Asymmetric Information Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach, Aner Sela July 14, 014 Abstract We study two-player common-value all-pay auctions in which the players have

More information

COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS. Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No.

COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS. Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No. COMMON-VALUE ALL-PAY AUCTIONS WITH ASYMMETRIC INFORMATION AND BID CAPS Ezra Einy, Ori Haimanko, Ram Orzach and Aner Sela Discussion Paper No. 4-0 September 04 Monaster Center for Economic Research Ben-Gurion

More information

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Volume 35, Issue 4 Group contests and technologies Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University Abstract We study the role of returns of scale of the technology on the characterization of

More information

Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information

Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information 1 2 Unique Equilibrium in Contests with Incomplete Information 3 4 Christian Ewerhart y Federico Quartieri z 5 July 2013 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 Abstract. For a large class of contests with incomplete

More information

Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer.

Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer. Information Advantage in Cournot Ol Title Separable Information, or Nondiffer Author(s) Haimanko, Ori Citation Issue 2009-09 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/17650

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Modelling incomplete information So far, we have studied games in which information was complete,

More information

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests

Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Multiple Equilibria in Tullock Contests Subhasish Chowdhury and Roman Sheremeta 20 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/5204/ MPRA Paper No. 5204, posted 0. December

More information

Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest

Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest Information Sharing in Private Value Lottery Contest Zenan Wu Jie Zheng May 4, 207 Abstract We investigate players incentives to disclose information on their private valuations of the prize ahead of a

More information

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd March 25, 2008 Abstract We consider imperfectly discriminating, common-value,

More information

Working Paper Series. Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes. Jun Xiao. June Research Paper Number 1151

Working Paper Series. Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes. Jun Xiao. June Research Paper Number 1151 Department of Economics Working Paper Series Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Jun iao June 212 Research Paper Number 1151 ISSN: 819 2642 ISBN: 978 734 451 Department of Economics The

More information

Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes

Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Asymmetric All-Pay Contests with Heterogeneous Prizes Jun iao y May 212 Abstract This paper studies complete-information, all-pay contests with asymmetric players competing for multiple heterogeneous prizes.

More information

SIGNALING IN CONTESTS. Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No November 2017

SIGNALING IN CONTESTS. Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela. Discussion Paper No November 2017 SIGNALING IN CONTESTS Tomer Ifergane and Aner Sela Discussion Paer No. 17-08 November 017 Monaster Center for Economic Research Ben-Gurion University of the Negev P.O. Box 653 Beer Sheva, Israel Fax: 97-8-647941

More information

SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER

SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER scottish institute for research in economics SIRE DISCUSSION PAPER SIRE-DP-00-83 Affirmative Action Policy and Effort Levels. Sequential-Move Contest Game Argument Andrzej Kwiatkowski University of Dundee

More information

Relative Di erence Contest Success Function

Relative Di erence Contest Success Function Relative Di erence Contest Success Function Carmen Beviá Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona and Barcelona GSE Luis C. Corchón Universidad Carlos III de Madrid First version January 20 th, 2012. This version

More information

Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests

Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests University of Zurich Department of Economics Working Paper Series ISSN 1664-7041 (print) ISSN 1664-705X (online) Working Paper No. 143 Mixed equilibria in Tullock contests Christian Ewerhart March 2014

More information

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich

Volume 30, Issue 3. Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions. Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Volume 30, Issue 3 Monotone comparative statics with separable objective functions Christian Ewerhart University of Zurich Abstract The Milgrom-Shannon single crossing property is essential for monotone

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen 1 Bayesian Games So far we have assumed that all players had perfect information regarding the elements of a game. These are called games with complete information.

More information

Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules

Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules Linking Individual and Collective Contests through Noise Level and Sharing Rules Pau Balart Subhasish M. Chowdhury Orestis Troumpounis November 6, 2015 Abstract We provide a theoretical link between the

More information

On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation. Volker Schlepütz

On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation. Volker Schlepütz On Overdissipation of Rents in Contests with Endogenous Intrinsic Motivation Volker Schlepütz Diskussionsbeitrag Nr. 421 Februar 2008 Diskussionsbeiträge der Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaft der FernUniversität

More information

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma

Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma Sending Information to Interactive Receivers Playing a Generalized Prisoners Dilemma K r Eliaz and Roberto Serrano y October 10, 2010 Abstract Consider the problem of information disclosure for a planner

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016 games Article Payoff Shares in Two-Player Contests Samuel Häfner and Georg Nöldeke * Faculty of Business and Economics, University of Basel, Peter Merian-Weg 6, Basel 400, Switzerland; samuel.haefner@unibas.ch

More information

The Geometry of Aggregative Games

The Geometry of Aggregative Games The Geometry of Aggregative Games Richard Cornes School of Economics University of Nottingham Nottingham NG2 7RD UK Roger Hartley Economic Studies School of Social Sciences University of Manchester Oxford

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: Signalling Games In general, a dynamic game of incomplete information is any extensive form game in which at least one player is uninformed about some

More information

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter Forthcoming in Public Choice A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter J. Atsu Amegashie Department of Economics University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario Canada NG W E-mail: jamegash@uoguelph.ca

More information

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form) A Game in Normal (strategic) Form consists of three components. A set of players. For each player, a set of strategies (called actions in textbook). The interpretation

More information

Optimal Favoritism in All-Pay Auctions and Lottery Contests

Optimal Favoritism in All-Pay Auctions and Lottery Contests Optimal Favoritism in All-Pay Auctions and Lottery Contests Jörg Franke 1, Wolfgang Leininger 1, and Cédric Wasser 2 1 University of Dortmund (TU) Department of Economics Vogelpothsweg 87 44227 Dortmund

More information

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games John Morgan University of California at Berkeley Preliminaries Our running example is that of a decision maker (DM) consulting a knowledgeable expert for advice about

More information

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Limit pricing models and PBE 1 EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Limit pricing models and PBE 1 1 Model Consider an entry game with an incumbent monopolist (Firm 1) and an entrant (Firm ) who analyzes whether or not to join the

More information

Cartel Stability in a Dynamic Oligopoly with Sticky Prices

Cartel Stability in a Dynamic Oligopoly with Sticky Prices Cartel Stability in a Dynamic Oligopoly with Sticky Prices Hassan Benchekroun and Licun Xue y McGill University and CIREQ, Montreal This version: September 2005 Abstract We study the stability of cartels

More information

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter

A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter Public Choice (2006) 126: 135 144 DOI: 10.1007/s11127-006-2461-z C Springer 2006 A contest success function with a tractable noise parameter J. ATSU AMEGASHIE Department of Economics, University of Guelph,

More information

COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN ZERO-SUM GAMES. 1. Introduction

COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN ZERO-SUM GAMES. 1. Introduction COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN ZERO-SUM GAMES MARCIN PESKI* Abstract. This note provides simple necessary and su cient conditions for the comparison of information structures in zero-sum games.

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs

Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Equilibria in Second Price Auctions with Participation Costs Guofu Tan and Okan Yilankaya January 2005 Abstract We investigate equilibria of sealed-bid second price auctions with bidder participation costs

More information

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis

Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Simultaneous Choice Models: The Sandwich Approach to Nonparametric Analysis Natalia Lazzati y November 09, 2013 Abstract We study collective choice models from a revealed preference approach given limited

More information

Incentives versus Competitive Balance

Incentives versus Competitive Balance Incentives versus Competitive Balance Marc Möller Department of Economics Universität Bern Abstract When players compete repeatedly, prizes won in earlier contests may improve the players abilities in

More information

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University Topics in Mathematical Economics Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University 25 November 2018 2 Contents 1 Preliminary Mathematics 5 1.1 Topology.................................. 5 1.2 Linear Algebra..............................

More information

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 Cycles of length two in monotonic models José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 October 20122 JEL:

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game

The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game University of Zurich Department of Economics Working Paper Series ISSN 1664-7041 (print) ISSN 1664-705X (online) Working Paper No. 242 The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game Christian Ewerhart

More information

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4

Game Theory. Solutions to Problem Set 4 1 Hotelling s model 1.1 Two vendors Game Theory Solutions to Problem Set 4 Consider a strategy pro le (s 1 s ) with s 1 6= s Suppose s 1 < s In this case, it is pro table to for player 1 to deviate and

More information

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly

Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly Endogenous timing in a mixed duopoly Rabah Amir Department of Economics, University of Arizona Giuseppe De Feo y CORE, Université Catholique de Louvain February 2007 Abstract This paper addresses the issue

More information

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Walter Trockel University of California, Los Angeles and Bielefeld University Mai 1999 Abstract The paper presents a method of supporting

More information

Internet Appendix for The Labor Market for Directors and Externalities in Corporate Governance

Internet Appendix for The Labor Market for Directors and Externalities in Corporate Governance Internet Appendix for The Labor Market for Directors and Externalities in Corporate Governance DORON LEVIT and NADYA MALENKO The Internet Appendix has three sections. Section I contains supplemental materials

More information

Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation

Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation Experimentation, Patents, and Innovation Daron Acemoglu y Kostas Bimpikis z Asuman Ozdaglar x October 2008. Abstract This paper studies a simple model of experimentation and innovation. Our analysis suggests

More information

Upstream capacity constraint and the preservation of monopoly power in private bilateral contracting

Upstream capacity constraint and the preservation of monopoly power in private bilateral contracting Upstream capacity constraint and the preservation of monopoly power in private bilateral contracting Eric Avenel Université de Rennes I et CREM (UMR CNRS 6) March, 00 Abstract This article presents a model

More information

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE)

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE) EconS 3 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium (SPNE). Based on MWG 9.B.3 Consider the three-player nite game of perfect information depicted in gure. L R Player 3 l r a b

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

A Note on Sabotage in Collective Tournaments

A Note on Sabotage in Collective Tournaments Discussion Paper No. 61 A Note on Sabotage in Collective Tournaments Oliver Gürtler* October 2005 *Oliver Gürtler, Department of Economics, BWL II, University of Bonn, Adenauerallee 24-42, D-53113 Bonn,

More information

Volume 35, Issue 2. Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof

Volume 35, Issue 2. Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof Volume 35, Issue 2 Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof Pierre von Mouche Wageningen Universiteit Federico Quartieri Universita degli studi di Napoli Federico

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit

Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Welfare Maximizing Contest Success Functions when the Planner Cannot Commit Luis Corchon Carlos III 2. November 2009 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/876/ MPRA

More information

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1846 EFFICIENT AUCTIONS AND INTERDEPENDENT TYPES Dirk Bergemann, Stephen Morris, and Satoru Takahashi

More information

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Matthias Kräkel y Anja Schöttner z Abstract It is well-known that, in static models, minimum wages generate positive worker rents and, consequently, ine ciently

More information

A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms

A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms A Note on Multi-winner Contest Mechanisms Subhasish M. Chowdhury and Sang-Hyun Kim February 11, 2014 Abstract In this note we consider a realistic multi-winner nested elimination contest in which losers

More information

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics Topics Volume 7, Issue 1 2007 Article 29 Asymmetric Nash Bargaining with Surprised Players Eran Hanany Rotem Gal Tel Aviv University, hananye@post.tau.ac.il Tel

More information

Carrot and stick games

Carrot and stick games Bond University epublications@bond Bond Business School Publications Bond Business School 6-14-2001 Carrot and stick games Jeffrey J. Kline Bond University, jeffrey_kline@bond.edu.au Follow this and additional

More information

An E cient Auction. (First version: October 1998) April 2001

An E cient Auction. (First version: October 1998) April 2001 An E cient Auction Motty Perry The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Penn State University and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago (First version: October 1998) April 2001 Abstract

More information

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University

Topics in Mathematical Economics. Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University Topics in Mathematical Economics Atsushi Kajii Kyoto University 26 June 2018 2 Contents 1 Preliminary Mathematics 5 1.1 Topology.................................. 5 1.2 Linear Algebra..............................

More information

Ability Grouping in All-Pay Contests

Ability Grouping in All-Pay Contests Ability Grouping in All-Pay Contests Jun Xiao October 11, 2017 Abstract This paper considers a situation in which participants with heterogeneous ability types are grouped into different competitions for

More information

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS # 2010 085 Negative and Positive Effects of Competition in a Preemption Game by Toru Suzuki www.jenecon.de ISSN 1864-7057 The JENA ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS is a joint publication

More information

Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry

Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry Endogenous network formation in patent contests and its role as a barrier to entry Marco Marinucci y Wouter Vergote z October 23, 2009 Abstract In a setting of R&D co-opetition we study, by using an all-pay

More information

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective Alex Possajennikov University of Nottingham January 2012 Abstract Suppose that in aggregative games, in which a player s payoff

More information

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Soc Choice Welfare (1999) 16: 557±567 Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Lars-Gunnar Svensson Department of Economics, Lund University, P.O. Box 7082, SE-220 07 of Lund, Sweden (e-mail: lars-gunnar.svensson@nek.lu.se)

More information

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES IN ECONOMICS AND MANAGEMENT Strategic Incentives for Managers in Contests Matthias Kräkel Discussion Paper No. 01-08 GERMAN ECONOMIC ASSOCIATION OF BUSINESS ADMINISTRATION - GEABA

More information

Northwestern University

Northwestern University Northwestern University 2001 Sheridan Road 580 Leverone Hall Evanston, IL 60208-2014 USA Discussion Paper #1487 March 2010 Common Knowledge of Rationality and Market Clearing in Economies with Asymmetric

More information

Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill Premium

Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill Premium Addendum to: International Trade, Technology, and the Skill remium Ariel Burstein UCLA and NBER Jonathan Vogel Columbia and NBER April 22 Abstract In this Addendum we set up a perfectly competitive version

More information

Contests with Endogenous and Stochastic Entry

Contests with Endogenous and Stochastic Entry Contests with Endogenous and Stochastic Entry Qiang Fu y Qian Jiao z Jingfeng Lu x December 2011 Abstract This paper studies imperfectly discriminatory contest with endogenous and stochastic entry, and

More information

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person.

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person. Chapter 9 Welfare Exercise 9. In a two-commodity exchange economy there are two large equalsized groups of traders. Each trader in group a has an endowment of 300 units of commodity ; each person in group

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static nformation Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris European Summer Symposium in Economic Theory, Gerzensee, July 2016 Mechanism Design and nformation Design Mechanism Design: Fix an economic environment

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Pei-yu Lo 1 Introduction Recap: BoS. Look for all Nash equilibria. show how to nd pure strategy Nash equilibria. Show how to nd mixed strategy Nash equilibria.

More information

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics ECON2285: Mathematical Economics Yulei Luo Economics, HKU September 17, 2018 Luo, Y. (Economics, HKU) ME September 17, 2018 1 / 46 Static Optimization and Extreme Values In this topic, we will study goal

More information

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation

Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation Contest Functions: Theoretical Foundations and Issues in Estimation Hao Jia, Stergios Skaperdas, and Samarth Vaidya May 14, 2011 Abstract Contest functions (alternatively, contest success functions) determine

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

Incentives and Machine Learning

Incentives and Machine Learning Incentives and Machine Learning John Hegeman December 12, 2008 In 2007, US paid search ad spend was $8.9 billion - most of which used a pay per click (PPC) billing model. In PPC, advertisers only pay the

More information

The Identi cation Power of Equilibrium in Games: The. Supermodular Case

The Identi cation Power of Equilibrium in Games: The. Supermodular Case The Identi cation Power of Equilibrium in Games: The Supermodular Case Francesca Molinari y Cornell University Adam M. Rosen z UCL, CEMMAP, and IFS September 2007 Abstract This paper discusses how the

More information

Mean-Variance Utility

Mean-Variance Utility Mean-Variance Utility Yutaka Nakamura University of Tsukuba Graduate School of Systems and Information Engineering Division of Social Systems and Management -- Tennnoudai, Tsukuba, Ibaraki 305-8573, Japan

More information

Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom

Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom Characterization of the Shapley-Shubik Power Index Without the E ciency Axiom Ezra Einy y and Ori Haimanko z Abstract We show that the Shapley-Shubik power index on the domain of simple (voting) games

More information

A Simple Model of Competition Between Teams

A Simple Model of Competition Between Teams A Simple Model of Competition Between Teams Kfir Eliaz and Qinggong Wu April 27, 216 Abstract We model a competition between two teams as an all-pay auction with incomplete information. The teams may differ

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series The Knob of the Discord Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Discussion Paper No.: 0405-14 Department of Economics Columbia University

More information

Ranking Bertrand, Cournot and Supply Function Equilibria in Oligopoly

Ranking Bertrand, Cournot and Supply Function Equilibria in Oligopoly ISSN 2282-6483 Ranking Bertrand, Cournot and Supply Function Equilibria in Oligopoly Flavio Delbono Luca Lambertini Quaderni - Working Paper DSE N 1000 Ranking Bertrand, Cournot and Supply Function Equilibria

More information

FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS FUNCTIONS

FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS FUNCTIONS Working Paper 07-04 Departamento de Economía Economic Series 01 Universidad Carlos III de Madrid January 2007 Calle Madrid, 126 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34-91) 6249875 FOUNDATIONS FOR CONTEST SUCCESS

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Cooperative game theory Harald Wiese University of Leipzig Harald Wiese (University of Leipzig) Advanced Microeconomics 1 / 45 Part D. Bargaining theory and Pareto optimality 1

More information

game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les Illes Balears June 1, 2012 Abstract

game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les Illes Balears June 1, 2012 Abstract On the optimality of bargaining outcomes in the Collective-Particularistic multilateral bargaining game. Daniel Cardona Universitat de les Illes Balears and CREB Antoni Rubí-Barceló Universitat de les

More information

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search

Labor Economics, Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 11: Partial Equilibrium Sequential Search Daron Acemoglu MIT December 6, 2011. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Sequential Search December 6, 2011. 1 / 43 Introduction Introduction

More information

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: Interpretation and Step-by-Step Examples Ana Espínola-Arredondo School of Economic Sciences Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164 Félix Muñoz-García y School

More information

Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks

Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks Spatial Competition and Collaboration Networks Yasunori Okumura y Kanagawa University May, 009 Abstract In this paper, we discuss the formation of collaboration networks among rms that are located in a

More information

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES

OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES OPTIMISM AND PESSIMISM IN GAMES Jürgen Eichberger Department of Economics, Universität Heidelberg, Germany David Kelsey Department of Economics University of Exeter, England University of Exeter October

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key EconS 503 - Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key 1. WEAs with market power. Consider an exchange economy with two consumers, A and B, whose utility functions are u A (x A 1 ; x A 2 ) = x A

More information

Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests

Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests RUHR ECONOMIC PAPERS Jörg Franke Christian Kanzow Wolfgang Leininger Alexandra Schwartz Lottery versus All-Pay Auction Contests A Revenue Dominance Theorem #35 Imprint Ruhr Economic Papers Published by

More information

A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games

A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games Towson University Department of Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper No. 2017-04 A Necessary and Sufficient Condition for a Unique Maximum with an Application to Potential Games by Finn Christensen

More information

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring 2012 EC941: Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Final Exam Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours. 1. Consider

More information

An E cient Auction. (First version: October 1998) October 2000

An E cient Auction. (First version: October 1998) October 2000 An E cient Auction Motty Perry The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Penn State University and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago (First version: October 1998) October 2000 Abstract

More information