Bounds on Weak Scattering

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Bounds on Weak Scattering"

Transcription

1 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 48, Number, 27 Bounds on Weak Scattering Gerald E. Sacks In Memory of Jon Barwise Abstract The notion of a weakly scattered theory T is defined. T need not be scattered. For each A a model of T, let sr(a) be the Scott rank of A. Assume sr(a) ω A for all A a model of T. Let σ 2 T be the least 2 admissible ordinal relative to T. If T admits effective k-splitting as defined in this paper, then θ < σ2 T such that sr(a) < θ for all A a model of T. Introduction This paper has two themes less disparate than they seem at first reading:. extending classical descriptive set theoretic results that impose bounds on suitably defined functions from ω ω into ω ; 2. extending and clarifying some early results on Scott ranks of countable structures sketched in [5]. Let F be a function, possibly partial, from ω ω into ω. A typical classical bounding theorem says the range of F is bounded by a countable ordinal if the graph of F has a suitable definition. For example, the graph of F is with real parameter p; in this formulation the graph of F is viewed as a subset of ω ω ω by requiring each value of F to be a well ordering of ω. Let F(X) ambiguously denote the well ordering and also the ordinal represented by the well ordering. For each X, F(X) is the unique solution of a formula with parameters p, X. Consequently F(X) (the well ordering) is hyperarithmetic in p, X, and so F(X) < ω p,x, (.) Received August 8, 25; accepted November 4, 25; printed February 26, 27 2 Mathematics Subect Classification: Primary, 3C7, 3D6 Keywords: weakly scattered theories, bounds on Scott rank c 27 University of Notre Dame 5

2 6 Gerald E. Sacks the least ordinal not recursive in p, X. The effective version of the theorem says that the bound on the range of F is an ordinal less than ω p. A recursion-theoretic approach to the effective bound originated by Kleene is as follows. (See Sacks [6] for details.) Suppose ( γ < ω p )( X)[F(X) > γ ]. (.2) Let R p e be the linear ordering of ω recursive in p via index e. Define W p to be the set of all e such that R p e is a well ordering. Then e W p X g[g is a - order-preserving map of R p e into F(X)]. (.3) But then W p is with parameter p. This last is false according to a Kleene hierarchy result that says W p is universal with parameter p, hence not with parameter p. A model theoretic approach to effective bounds is the path taken in this paper. A sketch may help to clarify later sections. Let A(p) be the least admissible set with p as a member. Let Z be a A(p) definable set of sentences of L ω,ω coded by elements of A(p) such that every model M of Z has the following properties:. The ordinals recursive in p form a proper initial segment of the ordinals in the sense of M. 2. There is an X M such that for all γ < ω p, F(X ) > γ. 3. p M and M is a admissible structure. Assume the range of F is not bounded by an ordinal below ω p. Then each A(p)- finite subset of Z (i.e., each subset of Z that is a member of A(p)) is consistent, and so Z has a model by Barwise Compactness. With the addition of effective type omitting, as in Grilliot [5] or Keisler [7], Z has a model M that omits ω p but has nonstandard ordinals greater than all standard ordinals less than ω p. Then ω p,x ω p ; (.4) otherwise, ω p is recursive in p, X and so ω p M. But then ω p,x = ω p and F(X ) ω p,x by property (2) of Z, which contradicts (.). The search for a bounding theorem that extends the classical result seems hopeless at first. An extension has to talk about an F that allows F(X) ω X,p, but ω X,p, as a function of X, is unbounded. Model theory comes to the rescue. Every countable structure A has a Scott rank [7], sr(a), an ordinal that can be as high as ω A + (see Section 2 for elaboration). Let T be a countable theory. A reasonable starting assumption on T is A[A T sr(a) ω A ]. (.5) An ingenious example (MA) devised by Makkai [] shows that (.5) is not enough. Examination of (MA) and its illuminative extensions in Knight and Young [8] leads to two further assumptions on T. The first, effective k-splitting, is technical and perhaps peripheral and is discussed further in Sections 9 and. The second, weakly scattered, is central. The theory T M associated with (MA) satisfies (.5) and has properties similar to effective k-splitting. In addition for every admissible countable α, T M has a model A such that ω A = α = sr(a). (.6)

3 Bounds on Weak Scattering 7 Corollary 9.5 says if T is weakly scattered, satisfies (.5), and has effective k- splitting, then there is a countable bound on the Scott ranks of the countable models of T ; the effective version provides a bound less than the first 2 admissible ordinal relative to T in contrast to the classical case above, where the effective bound on the range of F is less than ω p, the first admissible ordinal relative to p. The notion of weakly scattered is inspired by Morley s concept of scattered. Let L be a countable first-order language, L a countable fragment of L ω,ω, and T L a theory (i.e., a set of sentences) with a model. For (a) and (b) below, let L be any countable fragment of L ω,ω extending L, and T any finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory contained in L and extending T. (The notions of finitary consistency and ω-completeness for fragments are reviewed at the beginning of Section 4.) T is said to be scattered if and only if (a) and (b) hold. (a) For all n > and all T, S n T, the set of all n-types over T, is countable. (b) For all L, the set {T T L } is countable. The above definition of scattered is equivalent to the one in Morley s groundbreaking [3]. T is said to be weakly scattered if and only if (a) holds. By [3], a scattered theory can have at most ω many countable models. In contrast, a weakly scattered theory can have 2 ω many countable models. Knight [9] has announced a counterexample to Vaught s Conecture (VC), a scattered first-order theory with ω many countable models. VC has a precise formulation in Section 5. In [5] the following bounding result was established: if T is scattered and satisfies (.5), then T has only countably many countable models; furthermore, every countable model of T has a countable copy in L(β, T ) for some β < σ2 T, the least α such that L(α, T ) is 2 admissible. Hence Vaught s Conecture holds for T if T satisfies (.5). The proofs given in [5] were somewhat sketchy, so missing details needed in later sections of this paper are given in Sections 3 through 5. If Vaught s Conecture is false, then results for scattered theories yield information about models of counterexamples to VC. Theorem 4.9(vii) says if VC fails for T, then T has a model of cardinality ω not elementarily equivalent in the sense of L ω,ω to any countable model (Harnik and Makkai [6]). Theorem 5.3 describes an ω -sequence of atomic and saturated models that every counterexample must possess. Section 5 includes a related absoluteness result implicit in Morley [3]: VC(T ), Vaught s Conecture for T, is a L(ωL(T ),T ) predicate of T, hence, 2. Steel [8], as reported in [], used an assumption stronger than (.5) to prove VC(T ). In Section 2 an arbitrary countable structure A is associated with a theory T A contained in a countable fragment of L ω A ω,ω canonically generated from A. By an argument of Nadel [4], A is a homogeneous model of T A. Steel s assumption ω A is equivalent to for every A a model of T, T A is ω-categorical. Assumption (.5) ω A is equivalent to for every A a model of T, A is an atomic model of T A. Sacks and ω A Young [2] produced a structure A such that A is an atomic model of T A, but T A ω A ω A is not ω-categorical. (In addition, ω A = ωck and T A is a ω A subset of L(ω CK).) Sections 7 through 9 are devoted to bounding for weakly scattered theories.

4 8 Gerald E. Sacks 2 Scott Analysis and Rank This section revisits [5] as promised in Section. Scott [7] showed that an arbitrary countable structure A with underlying first-order language L can be characterized up to isomorphism by a single sentence of L ω,ω. In essence there is a countable fragment L A of L ω,ω such that A is the atomic model of T A, the complete theory of A in L A. Nadel [4] pointed the way to a canonical choice for L A. The admissible set L(ω A, A) is Gödel s L relativized to A as an element2 and chopped off at ω A, the least γ such that L(γ, A) is admissible. Let Nadel [4] showed that L A ω A,ω = L ω,ω L(ω A, A). (2.) A is a homogeneous model of its complete theory T A ω A,ω in LA ω A,ω. (2.2) It follows that A is the atomic model of its complete theory in L ω,ω L(ω A +, A), (2.3) since the types over T A ω A,ω realized in A are first-order definable over L(ωA, A) and so become atoms of the complete theory of A contained in (2.3). A recursion defines a canonical choice for L A and yields the definition of Scott rank for A.. L A = L. 2. L A λ = {LA δ δ < λ} for limit λ. 3. Tδ A = complete theory of A in L A δ. 4. L A δ+ = least fragment L+ of L ω,ω such that L + L A δ, and for each n >, if p( x ) is a nonprincipal n-type of Tδ A realized in A, then the conunction {F ( x ) F ( x ) p( x )} is a member of L +. Note that if A is isomorphic to B, then L A δ = L B δ and Tδ A = Tδ B for all δ. For some δ < ω, all the n-types of Tδ A realized in A are principal. To see this, fix γ and suppose some nonprincipal type p γ + of Tγ A + is realized in A. Let p γ be the restriction of p γ + to Tγ A. Since p γ + is nonprincipal, there is a formula G( x ) of such that both L A γ + x [p γ ( x ) G( x )] and x [p γ ( x ) G( x )] belong to T A γ +. Then there are n-tuples b and c of A such that A [p γ ( b ) G( b )], and A [p γ ( c ) G( c )]. Thus a distinction between b and c is made by a formula of L A γ + but not by any formula of L A γ. Since A is countable, only countably many distinctions can be made. Let d A be the the least δ < ω such that every distinction ever made is made by a formula of L A δ. Then A is the atomic model of T A d A +. (2.4)

5 The Scott Rank of A is defined by Bounds on Weak Scattering 9 sr(a) = least α [A is the atomic model of Tδ A ]. (2.5) If A is isomorphic to B, then sr(a) = sr(b). Nadel s proof of (2.2), p. 273 of [4], sketched below, also shows Hence d A ω A, and so sr(a) A is a homogeneous model of T A ω A. (2.6) ω A +. (2.7) Note that L A δ and Tδ A, as functions of δ < ωa, are L(ωA,A) ; that is, their graphs are definable subsets of L(ω A, A). Since the formulas of LA and T A are ω A ω A enumerated in increasing order of complexity, L A ω A and T A ω A are L(ωA,A). (2.8) To prove (2.6), let p ( x ) be an n-type, and q( x, y) an (n + )-type, of T A, and ω A a, b n-tuples of A. Suppose p( x ) q( x, y) and A [p( a ) p( b ) yq( a, y)]. (2.9) For homogeneity, a d A is required so that A q( b, d). Suppose no such d exists. Let q δ (x, y) be the restriction of q(x, y) to L A δ. Then {q δ (x, y) δ < ω A } is L(ωA,A). (2.) For each d A, there is a δ < ω A such that A q δ( b, d). Since δ can be defined as a L(ωA,A) function of d, the admissibility of L(ω A, A) implies there is a δ < ω A such that A y q δ ( b, y). But then A y q( a, y). (2.) A typical use of Scott rank in conunction with Barwise Compactness and Grilliot type omitting is as follows. Proposition 2. Suppose L(α, T ) is countable and admissible. If for each β < α, T has a model of Scott rank β, then T has a countable model such that sr(a) ω T,A = α. (2.2) Note that the A of (2.2) must have Scott rank either α or α + by (2.7). Forcing the outcome to be α + is a problem addressed in this paper but far from resolved. 3 Small ZF Sets The following is one of many variations (e.g., Makkai []) on a theme initiated by Barwise [2], an extension of a recursion theoretic fact needed for the enumeration of models of both scattered and weakly scattered theories. The variation below was mentioned and used in [5]. The recursion theoretic fact is as follows: if a set S of reals is and has cardinality less that 2ω, then there exists a hyperarithmetic real H such that every member of S is Turing reducible to H; in addition, an index for H can be computed uniformly from an index for S. The latter uniformity is

6 Gerald E. Sacks key to establishing the character of the enumeration of models in Sections 4 and 8. Recall that a ZF formula is a formula in the language of set theory with only bounded quantifiers ( xɛy) and ( uɛv). Let D(x, y) be a ZF lightface formula and A a countable admissible set. Suppose p, b A. Define S p,b = {x xɛv x b D(x, p)}. (3.) Theorem 3. If S p,b / A, then the cardinality of S p,b is 2 ω. Proof Let the language L consist of, bounded quantifiers x y and x y, an individual constant e for each e A, and a special individual constant c different from all the es. Let Z be the following A set of sentences of L.. The atomic diagram of A: d e d e; d / e d / e for d, e A. 2. c b, D(c, p), and c = e for all e A. Suppose Z is not consistent in the sense of L ω,ω. Then there is a z A such that z Z and z is not consistent. And z consists of some A A such that A is a subset of the atomic diagram of A, and c b, D(c, p), and {c = e e f } (3.2) for some f A. Since z is inconsistent, there is a deduction E A of [c b D(c, p)] c f (3.3) from A. But then S p,b f and so S p,b A. Suppose Z is consistent. Then a Henkin-style construction in ω many stages yields a model of Z, hence, an actual c (S p,b A). At stage, a sentence σ of L is considered, and σ is either σ or σ so long as Z {σ i i } is consistent. If σ is an infinite disunction (e.g., σ begins with x e ), then some component of σ is added immediately. The construction can be varied so 2 ω many cs are produced. Let t be a one-one map of ω onto {g g b}. After σ is chosen, and before σ + is chosen, create a split as follows. Choose an n so that (t(n) c) and (t(n) / c) are each consistent with Z {σ i i }. Then the construction takes 2 ω different paths, and different paths produce different cs. Such splits always exist. Otherwise there is a such that Z {σ i i } is consistent and for each n there is a deduction D n A from Z {σ i i } of either (t(n) c) or (t(n) / c). The admissibility of A puts all the D n s in some D A. D decides which elements of b belong to c. Hence there is an e A such that (c = e) is deducible from Z {σ i i }, a contradiction. Corollary 3.2 S p,b is countable S p,b A. Theorem 3.3 There exists a lightface ZF formula F (u, v, w) such that for any countable admissible set A and any p, b, s A, S p,b is countable A wf (p, b, w); (3.4) ( s A){[A F (p, b, s)] s = S p,b }. (3.5)

7 Bounds on Weak Scattering Proof The existence of F is implicit in the proof of Theorem 3.. Thus Z is inconsistent if and only if S p,b is countable if and only if S p,b A. The statement A F (p, b, s) (3.6) says (i) there exist A A and E such that A atomic diagram of A, and E is a deduction of (3.3) from A ; and (ii) s = {x x f x b D(x, p)}. (3.7) 4 Enumeration of Models for Scattered Theories Let L be a countable fragment of L ω,ω for some countable first-order language L and T L a theory with a model. Throughout this section T is scattered as defined in Section. For convenience assume T mentions all formulas of L ; thus L and L are recoverable from T. 4. Review of ω-completeness and finitary consistency for fragments Let L be a countable fragment of L ω,ω and T L a set of sentences. T is ω-complete in L if and only if () and (2) hold.. For every sentence F L, either F T or ( F ) T. 2. For any sentence ( i F i ) T, there is an i such that F i T. Say T is finitarily consistent if and only if no contradiction can be derived from T using only the finitary rules of L ω,ω. The infinitary step being avoided is deriving an infinite conunction by deriving each of its components. Say T is ω-consistent if and only if for any sentence ( i F i ) L, if T { i F i } is finitarily consistent, then there is an i such that T {F i } is finitarily consistent. Proposition 4. If T is finitarily consistent and ω-complete, then T has a model. Proof Note that T is ω-consistent. The model is constructed by extending T to a finitarily consistent and ω-complete set of sentences that includes Henkin axioms. At each stage of the construction, the set of sentences up to that point is ω-consistent. Proposition 4.2 Suppose for all β γ < λ, T β is finitarily consistent and ω- complete in the fragment L β, T β T γ, and L β L γ. Then {T β β < λ} is finitarily consistent and ω-complete in the fragment {L β β < λ}. Morley [3] showed that the scatteredness of T implies the countable models of T can be arranged in a hierarchy of height at most ω based on Scott rank with at most countably many models on each level. The current section revisits [5] and presents a enumeration of the countable models of T with a recursion-theoretic eye on some constructive details. The enumeration is a continuous tree TR(T ) with at most ω levels and at most countably many nodes on each level. Each node is a theory T finitarily consistent and ω-complete in a fragment L T with T T and L L T. Each T has an atomic model, and the class of all such models is the class of all countable models of T. The enumeration of TR(T ) is as follows.

8 2 Gerald E. Sacks Level Call T a node if and only if T is a finitarily consistent and ω-complete extension of T in the fragment L (= L T ). Level λ (limit) Call T a node if and only if there is a sequence T β (β < λ) such that T β is on level β, T β T γ (β < γ < λ), and T = {T β β < λ}. L T = {L Tβ β < λ}. Level δ + Suppose S is a node on level δ, that is, a finitarily consistent theory ω-complete in its fragment L S. If S is ω-categorical, then S has no successors on level δ +. Otherwise, S has a nonprincipal n-type p( x ). Let L S be the least fragment of L ω,ω extending L S and containing the conunction {F ( x ) F ( x ) p( x )} (4.) for every nonprincipal n-type p( x ) of S for all n >. Say T is a successor of S on level δ + if T is a finitarily consistent and ω-complete extension of S in the fragment L S (= L T ). Proposition 4.3 β. If β < ω, then TR(T ) has only countably many nodes on level Proof By induction on β. Level is countable by clause (b) of the definition of scattered. Suppose S is on level δ. Assume L S is countable. The set of all nonprincipal n-types of S is countable by clause (a) of the definition of scattered; hence, L S is countable. The set of all successors of S on level δ + is countable by clause (b) of the definition of scattered. Let T be any node on the countable limit level λ. Let L λ be the least fragment extending all the L S s for all theories S on all levels below λ. By induction, L λ is countable. Let T be any finitarily consistent and ω-complete extension of T in L λ. The set of all T s is countable, so the set of all T s is countable. Let TR(T ) β be the restriction of TR(T ) to the levels below β. Proposition 4.4 (i) If β < α < ω and L(α, T ) is admissible, then (TR(T ) β) L(α, T ). (ii) There exists a lightface ZF formula G(u, v, w) such that for all scattered T, all countable admissible L(α, T ), and all b L(α, T ), (TR(T ) β) = b L(α, T ) G(T, β, b). Proof By a L(α,T ) recursion that relies on Theorem 3.3. Suppose (TR(T ) (δ + )) L(α, T ), (4.2) and theory S is on level δ. The set of nonprincipal types of S is the unique s L(α, T ) that satisfies the F of Theorem 3.3 with p and b both equal to S. The statement q is a nonprincipal type of S is lightface ZF and corresponds to the formula D(x, y) of (3.). The fragment L S was defined ust before Equation (4.). The set of successors of S on level δ + is obtained from Theorem 3.3 with parameters p, b equal to S, L S.

9 Bounds on Weak Scattering 3 Let A be a countable model of T (a scattered theory as above). The Scott analysis of A differs little from its tree analysis: T (, A) = theory of A in L, and L T (,A) = L. T (λ, A) = {T (β, A) β < λ}. L T (λ,a) = {L T (β,a) β < λ}. L T (δ+,a) = L T (δ,a) (defined similarly to L S on level δ + of TR(T ) above). T (δ +, A) = theory of A in L T (δ+,a). Recall from Section 2 the definition of d A, the distinction rank of A, and the argument that the Scott rank of A is either d A or d A +. Clearly, there is a δ < ω such that for all n, any distinction made between n-tuples of A by a formula of L T (ω,a) is made by a formula of L T (δ,a). The tree rank of A is defined by Proposition 4.5 tr(a) = least δ [A is the atomic model of T (δ, A)]. (4.3) tr(a) sr(a). Proof Lδ A was defined ust after Equation 2.3. By induction on δ, LA δ L T (δ,a). Thus Tsr(A) A T (sr(a), A). But A is an atomic, hence homogeneous, model of, and so A is an atomic model of T (sr(a), A). T A sr(a) Proposition 4.6 Suppose A T and L(α, < T, A >) is admissible. Then tr(a) < α sr(a) < α. Proof Suppose not. Then D, the set of all distinctions between n-tuples (all n > ) of A made by formulas of L T (tr(a),a), belongs to L(α, T, A ) by Proposition 4.4. And there is an unbounded L(α, T,A ) map of D into α, a violation of the admissibility of L(α, T, A ). The map carries each distinction d D to the least δ such that d is made by some formula of L A δ. A theory T can be scattered up to a point. The tree TR(T ) is said to be scattered below β if the notion of scattered enumeration succeeds for T on all levels below β. To be more precise, TR(T ) has only countably many nodes (perhaps none) on each level below β. Proposition 4.7 Suppose α < ω, L(α, T ) is admissible, T is scattered below (α + ), and T has a model of Scott rank β for each β < α. Then there exists a theory T α on level α of TR(T ) such that T α is L(α,T ). Proof By Proposition 4.6, TR(T ) has nodes on all levels below α if an A can be found that satisfies the hypotheses of Proposition 4.6 and also sr(a) α. To find A through Barwise Compactness, consider the following set Z of sentences. (Z) Introduce a constant e to name each e L(α, T ). Add the atomic diagram (in the sense of L ω,ω) of L(α, T ) to Z. For each β < α, x[x β {x = γ γ < β}] (4.4) is a typical member of (Z). Any model of (Z) is an end extension of L(α, T ). (Z2) Introduce a new constant d and add sentences saying d is an ordinal greater than β for each β < α.

10 4 Gerald E. Sacks (Z3) Add A T and sr(a) > β for each β < α. (Z4) Add the axioms for admissibility. Let M be a model of Z that omits α but extends L(α, T ) as in [5] or [7]. L(α, T, A ) is admissible; otherwise α M. (Z3) insures sr(a) α. Let T denote an arbitrary node below level α. Call T unbounded if T has extensions to theories on arbitrarily high levels below α. Then T can be regarded as an unbounded node. Suppose T is an unbounded node below level β for some β < α; then T has an unbounded extension on level β. Otherwise, the admissibility of L(α, T ) implies T is bounded. There exists a β < α and an unbounded node T β on level β such that for all β (β, α), T β has a unique unbounded extension on level β. Otherwise, a tree U of unbounded nodes can be constructed such that U is isomorphic to the binary branching tree 2 <ω, and the branches of U define a continuum of nodes on some level α α of TR(T ) (α + ). The set S ub of unbounded nodes above T β form an expanding sequence whose union is the desired T α. To see S ub is L(α,T ), let N γ be the set of all nodes on level γ extending T β for each γ (β, α). Then N γ, as a function of γ, is L(α,T ) by Proposition 4.4, and (N γ S ub ) L(α, T ) since N γ S ub has ust one element. There is a L(α,T ) function that takes each node e (N γ S ub ) to a bound on the levels occupied by extensions of e. But then there is a strict upper bound b < α on the levels occupied by extensions of members of (N γ S ub ). Any such b singles out the unique member of N γ S ub. Proposition 4.8 Suppose α ω, L(α, T ) is 2 admissible, T is scattered below α, and T has models of arbitrarily high Scott rank less than α. Then there exists a theory T α on level α of TR(T ) such that T α is L(α,T ). Proof The proof is similar to that of Proposition 4.7. The only difference is in the handling of U. Then and now U can be defined by a L(α,T ) 2 recursion of length ω, since the set of unbounded nodes is L(α,T ). But now the 2 admissibility of L(α, T ) implies U L(α, T ), and so the branches of U define a continuum of nodes on some level α < α of TR(T ). Two L-structures are said to be L ω,ω-equivalent if they satisfy the same sentences of L ω,ω. (Recall that if A is countable and L ω,ω-equivalent to B, then A is L,ω - equivalent to B.) Theorem 4.9 Suppose Vaught s Conecture fails for T. Then there exist T β, A β, and L β (β ω ) such that (i) if β < ω, then T β is an ω-complete theory in the countable fragment L β ; (ii) if β γ ω, then T β T γ, A β A γ, and L β L γ ; (iii) if λ(limit) ω, then T λ = {T β β < λ} and A λ = {A β β < λ}; (iv) T ω is L(ω,T ) definable; (v) if β ω, then A β is an atomic model of T β ; (vi) if β < ω, then A β+ realizes a nonprincipal type of T β ; (vii) (Harnik and Makkai [6]) The cardinality of A ω is ω, and A ω is not L ω,ωequivalent to any countable model. 3

11 Bounds on Weak Scattering 5 Proof A uncountable model A ω of T is constructed so that it is not L ω,ωequivalent to any countable model. By Proposition 4.8, there is a theory T ω on level ω of TR(ω ) such that T ω is L(ω,T ). Thus T ω = {T γ γ < ω }, and (γ δ) (T γ T δ ). p, the parameter used in the L(α,T ) definition of T ω, belongs to L(α, T ) for some α < ω. Define K = {β α < β < ω L(β, T ) L(ω, T )}. (Recall that X Y means X is a ZF substructure of Y.) Let {γ δ δ < ω } be an increasing enumeration of K. Then L(γ δ, T ) is admissible, and so T γδ = T ω L(γ δ, T ) by Proposition 4.4(i). Also T γδ is L(γ δ,t ) definable via the same definition that works for T ω, since p L(γ δ, T ) L(ω, T ). Structures A δ (δ ω ) and inclusion maps i β,δ : A β A δ (β < δ) are defined by recursion on δ. The map i β,δ will be elementary with respect to the language L γβ ; that is, any sentence of L γβ with parameters in A β and true in A β will also be true in A δ. Stage Structure A is the countable atomic model of T γ. Stage δ + Assume A δ is the countable atomic model of T γδ. Extend A δ to A δ+, the countable atomic model of T γδ+, so that the inclusion map i δ,δ+ is L γδ - elementary. Stage λ (limit ω ) Let A λ = {A δ δ < λ}. For all δ < δ < λ, assume the inclusion map i δ,δ is L γδ -elementary. Then for each δ < λ, A λ is an L γδ -elementary extension of A δ and so is a model of T γδ. Thus A λ is a model of T γ λ. To see that A λ is an atomic model of T γ λ, let a be an n-tuple of A λ. For some δ < λ, a is an n-tuple of A δ and realizes some atom F ( x ) of T γδ. Then F ( x ) is an atom of T λ, because L(γ δ, T ) L(λ, T ). Hence, a realizes F ( x ) in A λ, since i δ,λ is L δ -elementary. If A ω were L ω,ω-equivalent to some countable model, then it would be an atomic model of T γδ for some δ < ω. But A δ+, hence A ω, realizes a nonprincipal type of T γδ. 5 Absoluteness of Vaught s Conecture Let VC(T ) be the predicate Vaught s conecture holds for T. Morley s work [3] implies that VC(T ) is absolute. The enumeration tree, TR(T ), of Section 4 is applied below to make the statement of VC(T ) more precise and to see in some detail how T can satisfy Vaught s Conecture. Suppose an attempt is made to develop TR(T ) and the attempt fails to produce a tree with only countably many nodes on each level and ω many nonempty levels. Then there must be a countable β such that one of the following holds: () β = and T has uncountably many finitarily consistent, ω-complete extensions in L ;

12 6 Gerald E. Sacks (2) β = δ +, some theory S is on level δ, and for some n, the set of n-types of S is uncountable; (3) β = δ +, some theory S is on level δ, for all n the set of n-types of S is countable, and the set of all finitarily consistent, ω-complete extensions of S in L S is uncountable. L S is defined ust before (4.). (4) β = λ and the set of nodes on level λ is uncountable. (5) level β is empty. Define the Vaught Rank of T, vr(t ) to be the least countable β that satisfies one of () (5) above. (If there is no such β, let vr(t ) be ω.) Define the predicate VC(T ) by vr(t ) < ω. Suppose vr(t ) = β < ω. If β =, then T has 2 ω finitarily consistent, ω-complete extensions in L by Theorem 3., hence, 2 ω many countable models. The same holds in cases (3) and (4). If (5) holds, then T has only countably many countable models, and each one is the atomic model of a theory on some level of TR(T ) below level β. Suppose case (2) holds. Then for some n, there are 2 ω n- types of S by Theorem 3., hence, 2 ω many countable models of T. Recall that Proposition 5. ω L(T ) = least γ [L(T ) (γ is uncountable )]. (5.) The predicate, Vaught s Conecture holds for T, is L(ωL(T ),T ), hence 2. Proof By Proposition 4.4, TR(T ) L(ω, T ) and is L(ω,T ). The statement VC(T ) says at some level γ < ω, either (a) TR(T ) ends or (b) blows up; that is, a perfect kernel of theories or types is manifest. Let α be the least α > γ such that L(α, T ) is admissible. Suppose (a) holds. Then Levy-Shoenfield Absoluteness implies α < ω L(T ), and there is an L ω,ω sentence K L(α, T ) that expresses the fact that every model of T is an atomic model of some theory on some level at or below γ of TR(T ). Suppose (b) holds. Theorem 3. implies the existence of a perfect kernel of theories or types. A coding of some such perfect kernel by a real is constructible from any counting of α. The proof of Theorem 3. relies on the consistency of a certain set Z of axioms. Z is L(α,T ), and the consistency of Z is L(α,T ). Hence Levy- Shoenfield Absoluteness implies α < ω L(T ), and so a code for the perfect kernel belongs to L(ω L(T ), T ). Proposition 5.2 Suppose T is a counterexample to Vaught s Conecture. Then there is a theory T ω on level ω of TR(T ) such that T ω is L(ω,T ). For all countable β, T β, the restriction of T ω to level β, has an atomic model whose Scott rank is β. Proof By Proposition 4.8. Suppose L(α, T ) is admissible, A is a countable model of T, and ω A = α. According to (2.6), A is a homogenous model of Tα A ; A is said to be α-saturated if every n-type (n ) of Tα A is realized in A. Theorem 5.3 Suppose T is a counterexample to Vaught s Conecture. Then there is a L(ω,T ) theory T ω on level ω of TR(T ) and a closed unbounded set C ω such that α C: T α, the restriction of T ω to level α, has an atomic model A α of

13 Bounds on Weak Scattering 7 Scott rank α and an α-saturated model B α of Scott rank α +. The atomic models form an expanding chain and each inclusion A β A γ (β < γ ) is elementary with respect to the language of T β. Proof Proposition 4.8 provides T ω. Let p L(ω, T ) be the parameter needed for the L(ω,T ) definition of T ω. For any α, let α + be the least β > α such that L(β, T ) is admissible. For x L(T ), let H (x) be the hull of x in L(T ). Recall that x H (x) L(T ) and that x and H (x) have the same cardinality in L(T ). An expanding sequence of countable hulls, H δ (δ < ω ), is defined by recursion on δ. H is H ({tc(p), ω, tc(t )}). (tc is transitive closure.) Note that ω +, ω H ; if d < e < ω and e H, then d H. Let c be the lub of the countable ordinals in H. Let L(β, T ) be the transitive collapse of H. Then c = ω L(β,T ) and L(c +, T ) L(β, T ). (5.2) Stage δ + Assume H δ is countable in V. Then H δ ω is a proper initial segment of ω. Let c δ be the least countable ordinal not in H δ. H δ+ is H (H δ {c δ }). Stage λ (limit) Let H λ be {H δ δ < λ}. Then C = {c δ δ < ω } is a closed unbounded set. Let L(β δ, T ) be the transitive collapse of H δ. Then c δ = ω L(β δ,t ) and L(c + δ, T ) L(β δ, T ). (5.3) Let T cδ be the restriction of T ω to level c δ of TR(T ). Then T cδ is L(c δ,t ) via parameter p, and N, the set of nonprincipal types of T cδ, is nonempty and countable in V. Then T cδ L(c δ +, T ), and so N L(c+ δ, T ) by Theorem 3.. Hence the structure L[c δ, T ; T cδ, N] (i.e., L(c δ, T ) with x T cδ and x N as additional atomic predicates) is admissible because no subset of c δ in L(β δ, T ) can define a counting of ω L(β δ,t ). Now the construction of M in the proof of Theorem 6. can be imitated to produce a model B of T cδ such that B realizes all the types in N and ω B = c δ. The atomic A β s are supplied by Theorem Bounds on Scattered Theories Once again L is a countable first-order language, L is a countable fragment of L ω,ω, and T L has a model. L and L are effectively recoverable from T. T is scattered below β as was defined ust before Proposition 4.7. Theorem 6. Suppose α < ω, L(α, T ) is 2 admissible, T is scattered below α, and for each β < α, T has a model of Scott rank β. Then T has a model A such that ω A = α and sr(a) = α +. Proof By Proposition 4.8, TR(A) has a theory T α on level α such that T α is α and T α is {T β β < α}, where T β is a node on level β. Let Z be the following set of sentences. (Z) (Z2) The atomic diagram of L(α, T ) in the sense of L ω,ω. Add (d > β) for all β < α. d is a constant not occurring in (Z).

14 8 Gerald E. Sacks (Z3) Let T d be a theory on level d of TR(T ). Add A is the countable atomic model of T d and F T d for each sentence F T α. (Z4) Add (b( x ) is an atom of T d ) for each b( x ) that is an atom of T α ; that is, b( x ) generates a principal type of T α. (Z5) Add the axioms of admissibility. The set Z is L(α,T ) 2, since the set of atoms of T α is L(α,T ). Suppose β < α, L(β, T ) is admissible, and Z β is Z L(β, T ). A fundamental fact of forcing in the setting of set theory is the Levy collapse of a cardinal to V preserves replacement; furthermore, the preservation of n replacement needs only n replacement in V. To check the consistency of Z β, augment L(α, T ) by adding a generic counting of L(β, T ) to L(α, T ) that preserves the 2 admissibility of L(α, T ). The set Z β can be modeled by the augmented L(α, T ). By Proposition 4.4, T β L(β, T ). Interpret d as β. Interpret A as the atomic model of T β. Such an A belongs to the augmented L(α, T ) because there T β is countable. If b( x ) is an atom of T α and belongs to L(β, T ), then b( x ) is an atom of T β. The set Z has a model M that is a proper end extension of L(α, T ) but omits α. ω A α; otherwise, α is recursive in A, and then α M. By design A T β for all β < α; hence, sr(a) α by Proposition 4.5, and so ω A = α by (2.6). Suppose sr(a) = α. Then α M as follows. By supposition A is the atomic model of T α. The rank of an atom b( x ) of T α is the least β < α such that b( x ) is an atom of T β. Let f be the function that carries each a A to the rank of an atom of T α that generates the principal type realized by a in A. Thanks to (Z4) f is definable from T d, and so f M. Then lub(range f ) = α M. Corollary 6.2 ([5]) Suppose for every countable model A of T, the Scott rank of A is less than or equal to ω A. Then Vaught s Conecture holds for T. Proof Suppose VC(T ) fails. Then T is scattered below ω, and TR(T ) has nodes on every countable level. Choose an α < ω such that L(α, T ) is 2 admissible. Then T has a countable model A such that ω A = α and sr(a) = α +. A more effective version of Corollary 6.2 is as follows. Define σ T 2 = least α [L(α, T ) is 2 admissible]. (6.) vr(t ), the Vaught rank of T, was defined at the beginning of Section 6. Corollary 6.3 Then vr(t ) < σ T 2. Suppose T does not have a countable model A such that ω A = σ T 2 and sr(a) = σ T 2 +. (6.2) Proof If vr(t ) σ2 T, then T is scattered below σ 2 T level below σ2 T. and TR(T ) has nodes on every As a warmup to the main bounding results of the paper (Section 8), the above is recast as an effective bounding theorem. Corollary 6.4 Suppose T is scattered and sr(a) ω A for every countable A T. (6.3)

15 Then β < σ T 2 such that sr(a) < β for every A T. (6.4) Bounds on Weak Scattering 9 Let SA(T ) say for every countable model A of T, the theory T A is ω-categorical. ω A Steel [8], as reported in Makkai [], showed that VC(T ) follows from SA(T ). Theorem 6.5 is an effective version of Steel s result. The set L(α, T ) is said to be recursively Mahlo if L(α, T ) is admissible and every L(α,T ) closed unbounded subset of α has a member β such that L(β, T ) is admissible. Define Note that rm(t ) < σ T 2. Theorem 6.5 rm(t ) = least γ [L(γ, T ) is recursively Mahlo]. (6.5) Suppose T is scattered and T A ω A Then β < rm(t ) such that is ω-categorical for every countable A T. (6.6) sr(a) < β for every countable A T. (6.7) Proof Suppose there is no such β. Let α be rm(t ). Then Proposition 4.7 supplies a L(α,T ) theory T α on level α of TR(T ). Then T α = {T β β < α}, and T β, as a function of β, is L(α,T ). There is a L(α,T ) function f such that T β L( f (β), T ) for all β < α. Iteration of f leads to a L(α,T ) closed unbounded set C = {γ T γ L(γ, T )}. (6.8) A similar argument produces a L(α,T ) closed unbounded set C such that [ γ C (Tα L(γ, T )) is L(γ,T ) ]. (6.9) Then there is a L(α,T ) closed unbounded set K such that γ K [ T γ L(γ, T ) and T γ is L(γ,T ) ]. (6.) Hence, for some γ K, L(γ, T ) is admissible. Consequently T γ has a model B such that ω B = γ. But then T B, hence T ω B γ, is ω-categorical and so has no extension to a node on level α. 7 Iterated Classical Bounding In this section classical bounding (reviewed in Section ) is translated into the language of admissible sets and revised to allow for iterated use in recursive definitions in Section 8. Let B(x) be a ZF formula with parameter p. The formula B(x) is β-bounded if and only if c[b(c) L[β, p ; c] B(c)]. (7.) The set L[β, p ; c] is the result of iterating first-order definability with y c as an additional atomic predicate through the ordinals less than β starting with the transitive closure (tc) of {p }. Assume B(x) is β-bounded. Define c β = c L[β, p ; c]. (7.2)

16 2 Gerald E. Sacks Then B(c) B(c β ). For all z let A z be the least admissible set with z as a member; thus A z = L(ω z, tc({z})). (7.3) Let F (u, v) be a ZF formula with parameter p, and let p be {p, p }. Suppose for all c, if B(c), then there exists a unique δ A {p,β,cβ } such that designate δ by δ p,β,c. Theorem 7. (i) There exists a δ p,β A {p,β} such that for all c, A {p,β,cβ } F (c β, δ); (7.4) B(c) δ p,β,c δ p,β. (7.5) (ii) δ p,β can be construed as a partial function of p and β whose restriction to any admissible A has a A definition uniformly in A; that is, one formula works for all A. Proof Let Z be the following A {p,β} set of sentences. Let α = ω {p,β}. (Z) Introduce constants c and c β, and put c β = c L[β, p ; c] and B(c β ) in Z. (Z2) Add constants that name the elements of L(α, tc({p, β, c β })) (7.6) and sentences of L ω,ω that define each element in terms of elements of lower definability rank. (Z3) Let F (u, v) be wg(u, v, w) for some ZF formula G(u, v, w). Add G(c β, δ, r) for all δ < α and every r that names an element of (7.6). (Z4) Add axioms for admissibility. Suppose Z is consistent. Assume for a moment that Z is countable. (7.7) As in the proof of Proposition 4.7, Z has a model M that is a proper end extension of (7.6) but omits α. Then (7.6) is admissible, and so A {p,β,cβ } = L(α, tc({p, β, c β })). (7.8) But then A {p,β,cβ } F (c β, δ) for all δ < α, a contradiction since δ p,β,cβ A {p,β,cβ }. Thus Z is inconsistent. To remove assumption (7.7), generically extend the universe V to V so that Z is countable in V. Then Z is inconsistent in V, hence in V, by the absoluteness of provability in the sense of L,ω. Since Z is A {p,β}, there must be an inconsistent W Z such that W A {p,β}. The set W consists of (W ), (W 2), and (W 3): (W) (W2) (Z) and (Z4) above. Some A A {p,β} such that A set of sentences of (Z2).

17 Bounds on Weak Scattering 2 (W3) For some δ < α, the sentence G(c β, δ, r) for all δ < δ and every r of (Z2) that names an element of L(δ, tc({p, β, c β })). Then there is a deduction D A {p,β} from (W ) and (W 2) of {F (c β, δ) δ < δ }. (7.9) Let ρ be the least ρ such that there is such a D L(ρ, tc({p, β})); let δ {p,β} be the least δ associated with any such D L(ρ, tc({p, β})). Then δ p,β,c δ p,β (7.) for any c such that B(c) holds. The ZF formula H that defines δ p,β as a partial function of p, β uniformly owes its existence to the effective nature of deducibility in L ω,ω. The formula H singles out a deduction in A {p,β} that establishes the value of δ p,β and can be formulated to succeed in every admissible A, because p, β A implies A {p,β} is a A definable (uniformly) subclass of A. 8 Enumeration of Models under Weak Scattering Let L be a countable fragment of L ω,ω for some countable first-order language L and T L a theory with a model. Assume T is weakly scattered as defined in Section. For convenience assume T mentions all formulas of L ; thus L and L are recoverable from T. Since T need not be scattered, there is no hope of enumerating theories in L(ω, T ) whose atomic models are exactly the countable models of T. But some useful vestiges of the constructive features of scattering carry over to weak scattering, and L(ω, T ) manages to say a great deal about the countable models of T. First consider RH(T ), the raw hierarchy for the countable models of T. On level of RH(T ), put every T such that T T and T is a finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory of L. (If needed, see the beginning of Section 4 for a review.) Suppose T δ is on level δ of RH(T ). Define δ if δ is a successor, δ = (8.) δ if δ is not a successor. Let L (T ) be L. Assume T δ extends a unique T δ on level δ and L δ (T δ ) is countable. If all n-types (n ) of T δ are principal, then L δ+ (T δ ) is undefined and T δ has no extensions on level δ +. Otherwise, let L δ+ (T δ ) be the least fragment of L ω,ω extending L δ (T δ ) and having as a member the conunction {F ( x ) F ( x ) p( x )} (8.2) for every nonprincipal n-type p( x ) of T δ (n ). Since T is weakly scattered, the set L δ+ (T δ ) is countable. On level δ + of RH(T ) put every T δ+ that extends T δ and is a finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory of L δ+ (T δ ). Put T λ on level λ if there is a sequence T δ (δ < λ) such that (a) T δ is on level δ; (b) T β T γ if β γ ; and (c) T λ = {T δ δ < λ}.

18 22 Gerald E. Sacks Define L λ (T λ ) to be {L δ (T δ ) δ < λ}. It is straightforward to verify that A is a countable model of T if and only if A is the atomic model of T δ for some countable δ. Define the raw tree rank of A by rtr(a) = (least δ)[a is the atomic model of some T δ ]. (8.3) Propositions 4.5 and 4.6 hold when tr is rtr. Thus and if L(α, T, A ) is admissible, then rtr(a) sr(a), (8.4) rtr(a) < α sr(a) < α. (8.5) What matters more is what can be expressed inside L(α, T ) when α ω and L(α, T ) is admissible. Let A δ be the set of all T δ s on level δ of RH(T ). The set A δ will be defined by a β-bounded ZF formula (7.), and its definition as such, denoted by A δ, will belong to L(α, T ) when δ < α. The fragment L δ (T δ ) will be constructible from T δ via an ordinal ρ δ < α for all T δ A δ. The pair A δ and ρ δ will be defined by a simultaneous L(α,T ) recursion uniformly in α, that is, the same formula will work for all α ω such that L(α, T ) is admissible. Consider an arbitrary T δ on level δ of RH(T ). There exists a natural recovery process that can be applied to T δ to recover the unique sequence T γ (γ < δ) such that T γ is on level γ, γ γ 2 T γ T γ2, and (8.6) T λ = {T γ γ < λ} for all limit λ δ. The recovery proceeds as follows. It begins with T is T δ L. If γ is a successor, then T γ = T δ L γ (T γ ). (8.7) If γ is a limit, then T γ = {T β β < λ}. The recovery process can be used to decide whether or not an arbitrary set c is a theory on level δ of RH(T ). The answer is yes if and only if c passes the following tests at all levels γ δ. Level Let c be c L ; c is an extension of T and a finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory of L. Level γ + δ Let L γ + (c γ ) be the least fragment extending L γ (c γ ) and having as a member the conunction {F ( x ) F ( x ) p( x )} (8.8) for every nonprincipal n-type p( x ) of c γ. Let c γ + be c L γ + (c γ ). c γ + extends c γ and is a finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory of L γ + (c γ ). Level λ (limit) δ Let c λ be {c γ γ < λ}; let L λ (c λ ) be {L γ (c γ ) γ < λ}. In short, c is a theory on level δ of RH(T ) if and only if c satisfies the recovery process on all levels γ δ and c = c δ. It will follow below that A δ is β-bounded ZF definable (7.), where β is large enough to define the recovery process. An effective version of the recovery process is woven into the L(α,T ) recursive definitions of ρ δ and A δ for < δ < α. The set L δ (T δ ) is constructible from

19 Bounds on Weak Scattering 23 T δ via the ordinal ρ δ for all T δ A δ, and A δ is a β-bounded ZF definition of A δ. The definition A δ specifies the value of β and the ZF formula. Stage L (T ) is L ; A is the set of all finitarily consistent, ω-complete theories of L extending T. Since L is recoverable from T, the set A is β-bounded ZF definable with β = and parameter T. Stage δ + Assume the recursion has produced sequences {ρ γ γ δ}, { A γ γ δ} L(α, T ) (8.9) such that A γ is a β-bounded ZF definition of A γ, and L γ (T γ )(γ δ) is firstorder definable over L[ρ γ, L ; T γ ]. (8.) (The definition of (8.) follows (7.).) Consider an arbitrary T δ A δ (δ > ). Use the recovery process to construct the unique T δ A δ such that T δ T δ L δ (T δ ). (8.) The recovery is effective thanks to the sequence ρ γ (γ δ). Now L δ+ (T δ ) can be defined as above (8.2) but with an effective twist. Let ST δ be the set of all n-types (n ) of T δ. Since T is weakly scattered, Corollary 3.2 implies the least admissible set with T δ as a member. Let ST δ L(ω T δ, T δ), (8.2) γ Tδ = (least γ)[st δ L(γ, T δ )]. (8.3) By Theorem 3.3, the ordinal γ Tδ, as a function of T δ, is uniformly ; the same ZF formula singles out γ Tδ in L(ω T δ, T δ) for every T δ A δ and for all δ. By Theorem 7.(i), there is a γ δ such that ( T δ A δ )[γ Tδ γ δ < α]. (8.4) Hence ST δ L(γ δ, T δ ) for all T δ A δ. Theorem 7.(ii) implies that γ δ, as a function of δ, has a uniform definition utilizing the parameters occurring in A δ and the uniform definition of γ Tδ. Any n-type p( x ) ST δ for any T δ A δ is constructible from T δ via some ordinal less than γ δ. A set P δ of first-order definitions can be assembled at level γ δ of L(α, T ) as follows. Let {p T δ J δ } (8.5) be the set of all first-order definitions over L(γ, T ) for all γ < γ δ with parameter T δ. For each T δ A δ, the obect p (T δ ) is the set defined by p (T δ ) when the parameter T δ is assigned the value T δ. The set (8.5) has a natural well-ordering W δ definable at level γ δ, since each p T δ is specified by its level γ < γ δ and its Gödel number e < ω as a formula of ZF. The type d δ (T δ ), the default type for T δ, is defined by its action on T δ A δ : (T δ ) = (least in sense of W δ )[p (T δ ) is an n-type of T δ ]; (8.6) d δ (T δ ) = p (Tδ )(T δ ). (8.7)

20 24 Gerald E. Sacks The formula p T δ is a slight variant of p (T δ ) and is defined by its action on T δ A δ. p (T δ ) if p (T δ ) is an n-type of T δ, p T δ = (8.8) d δ (T δ ) the default type, otherwise. Let P δ = {p T δ J δ }. Then. for all T δ A δ and p( x ) ST δ, there is a J δ such that p T δ p( x ) at level γ δ of L(α, T ), and 2. p T δ ST δ for all T δ A δ and all J δ. defines It can happen for some T δ A δ and, k J δ that = k but p T δ = p T δ k. Such repetitions are the price paid to have P δ L(γ δ +, T ). The ordinal ρ δ+ < α is chosen ust large enough to develop the sequence ρ γ (γ δ) needed for the recovery of T δ from T δ (δ > ) and the ordinal γ δ needed to assemble P δ. The set L δ+ (T δ ) is first-order definable over L[ρ δ+, L ; T δ ]; its definition begins with L δ (T δ ), adds the conunction of all formulas in p T δ for each p T δ P δ, and closes under the finitary operations that generate a fragment of L ω,ω. To complete stage δ +, construe A δ+ to be the set of all x such that the effective version of the recovery process applied to x reports that x is a theory on level δ + of RH(T ). The effective version uses the sequence ρ γ ( < γ δ + ) to define L γ (T γ ) from T γ for all T γ A γ. Thus A δ+ is β-bounded ZF definable with β equal to ρ δ+, and A δ+ L(α, T ). The parameter specified by A δ+ is T. Stage λ (limit) Assume for < γ < λ that L γ (T γ ) is constructible from T γ via ρ γ for all T γ A γ. Use the effective version of the recovery process to define A λ as a β-bounded ZF class. For T γ A λ, effectively recover the unique sequence T γ (γ < λ) such that T λ is {T γ γ < λ}, and then define L λ (T λ ) to be {L γ (T γ ) < γ < λ}. Makkai [] showed that if T is a counterexample to Vaught s Conecture, then T has a model of cardinality ω that is L,ω equivalent to a countable model. The following are variants of his results. Suppose A is a countable admissible set and T A. Assume T L, L is a countable fragment of L ω,ω, and L is a countable first-order language. Also assume every symbol of L is mentioned in T so that L is recoverable from T. Let L denote an arbitrary fragment of L ω,ω that extends L, and T an arbitrary finitarily consistent, ω-complete theory contained in L and extending T. Call T weakly scattered in A if and only if ST A for all T A. According to Theorem 3.3, we have the following. Theorem 8. Suppose A is a countable model of T. Assume T is weakly scattered in L(ω T,A, T, A ), and sr(a) ω T,A. Then A is L,ω equivalent to a model of T of cardinality ω. Proof Let α =ω T,A. Thus ω A = α, since ωa + sr(a). Let T β A (β sr(a)) be the Scott analysis of A as defined in Section 2. By Theorem 3.3, STβ A L(α, T, A )

21 Bounds on Weak Scattering 25 (and so Tβ A has a countable atomic model) for all β such that β + < sr(a). The set Z is L(α, T,A ) and consists of the following sentences: (Z) the atomic diagram (in the sense of L ω,ω) of L(α, T, A ); (Z2) d is a countable ordinal and d δ (all δ < ω T,A ); (Z3) y[y < d T A y has a countable atomic model]; (Z4) axioms of admissibility. The set Z is consistent since it can be modeled by V (the real world). Every model of Z is an end extension of L(α, T, A ). Let M be a model of Z that omits α. Thus M has nonstandard ordinals greater than every ordinal less than α. Hence sr(a) α in V and α / M, so sr(a) γ for some nonstandard γ M. Now work inside M. Let Tδ A (δ γ ) be the Scott analysis of A up to level γ. Choose a nonstandard β < γ. Then Tβ A has a countable atomic model A β. There is a map i βγ : A β A (8.9) that is elementary with respect to all formulas of L A β (defined in Section 2). Note that i bγ is not onto, since A β is not isomorphic to A in M. But A β is isomorphic to A in V. Now ω A β α since α / M; also sr(a β ) δ for all δ < α. Hence sr(a β ) α, and so ω A β α. Thus both A β and A are homogeneous models of Tα A by (2.6). To see they realize the same types of T α A, choose p α STα A and first suppose A β p α (b). In M, note that A β p β (b) for some type p β of Tβ A and that A p γ (i βγ (b)) for some type p γ of Tγ A. Then p α p β p γ, (8.2) since i βγ is L A β elementary. Hence A p α(i βγ (b)). It follows that i βγ is L ω,ω elementary, (8.2) since the types of Tα A realized in A β are atoms of L ω,ω. Now suppose A p α (a). In M, the tuple a realizes p γ in A, a type of Tγ A. Choose a nonstandard δ < β. Let p β be the restriction of p γ to Lβ A, and let p δ be the restriction to L A δ. Then p α p δ p β p γ. So A x p δ (x). (8.22) But then x p δ (x) T δ+ T β, so p δ, hence p α, is realized in A β. Thanks to the above there exist structures B and B, both isomorphic to A, such that B B and the inclusion map i is L ω,ω elementary. A strictly expanding L ω,ω elementary chain B δ (δ ω ) is defined by iterating i. For δ < ω, assume B δ is isomorphic to A. Then enlarge B δ to B δ+, another copy of A. For limit λ ω, let B λ be the union of the B δ s (δ < λ). B ω is an L ω,ω elementary extension of B, hence L ω,ω-equivalent to A, consequently L,ω -equivalent to A. Corollary 8.2 Suppose T is weakly scattered. For each β < ω T, assume T has a model of Scott rank β. Then T has a countable model A such that sr(a) ω T,A = ω T,

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago May 22, 2005 1 Is the Vaught Conjecture model

More information

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order. October 12, 2010 Sacks Dicta... the central notions of model theory are absolute absoluteness, unlike cardinality, is a logical concept. That is why model theory does not founder on that rock of undecidability,

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures Rose-Hulman Undergraduate Mathematics Journal Volume 18 Issue 1 Article 14 Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures Brian Tyrrell Trinity College Dublin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.rose-hulman.edu/rhumj

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago February 8, 2006 Abstract We give a model

More information

The rise and fall of uncountable models

The rise and fall of uncountable models Chris Laskowski University of Maryland 2 nd Vaught s conjecture conference UC-Berkeley 2 June, 2015 Recall: Every counterexample Φ to Vaught s Conjecture is scattered. Recall: Every counterexample Φ to

More information

In Memoriam Professor Joseph R. Shoenfield

In Memoriam Professor Joseph R. Shoenfield E-RECURSIVE INTUITIONS GERALD E. SACKS In Memoriam Professor Joseph R. Shoenfield A. An informal sketch (with intermittent details) of parts of E-Recursion theory, mostly old, some new, that stresses intuition.

More information

Disjoint n-amalgamation

Disjoint n-amalgamation October 13, 2015 Varieties of background theme: the role of infinitary logic Goals 1 study n- toward 1 existence/ of atomic models in uncountable cardinals. 2 0-1-laws 2 History, aec, and Neo-stability

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Computability theory and uncountable structures

Computability theory and uncountable structures Sets and Computations, April 17 2015 Joint with Greg Igusa, Julia Knight and Antonio Montalbán Table of Contents 1 Generically presentable structures 2 3 1 Generically presentable structures 2 3 What phenomena

More information

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Joint work with: W. Boney, S. Friedman, C. Laskowski, M. Koerwien, S. Shelah, I. Souldatos University of Illinois at Chicago AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Cantor s Middle Attic Uncountable

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin large and large and March 3, 2015 Characterizing cardinals by L ω1,ω large and L ω1,ω satisfies downward Lowenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward Lowenheim Skolem. Definition sentence

More information

Almost Galois ω-stable classes

Almost Galois ω-stable classes Almost Galois ω-stable classes John T. Baldwin Paul B. Larson Saharon Shelah March 11, 2015 Abstract Theorem. Suppose that k = (K, k ) is an ℵ 0-presentable abstract elementary class with Löwenheim-Skolem

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. This paper attempts to serve as an introduction to abstract model theory. We introduce the notion of abstract logics, explore first-order logic as an instance

More information

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Sy D. Friedman KGRC Michael C. Laskowski University of Maryland Martin Koerwien KGRC September 17, 2014 Abstract

More information

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler ATHEATCS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATONS Vol. - odel Theory - H. Jerome Keisler ODEL THEORY H. Jerome Keisler Department of athematics, University of Wisconsin, adison Wisconsin U.S.A. Keywords: adapted probability

More information

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture

Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture Three Red Herrings around Vaught s Conjecture John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Sy D. Friedman KGRC Michael C. Laskowski University of Maryland Martin Koerwien KGRC November 21, 2013 Abstract

More information

A Vaught s conjecture toolbox

A Vaught s conjecture toolbox Chris Laskowski University of Maryland 2 nd Vaught s conjecture conference UC-Berkeley 1 June, 2015 Everything begins with the work of Robert Vaught. Everything begins with the work of Robert Vaught. Fix

More information

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago July 12, 2006 Abstract We give a model theoretic

More information

The Absoluteness of Constructibility

The Absoluteness of Constructibility Lecture: The Absoluteness of Constructibility We would like to show that L is a model of V = L, or, more precisely, that L is an interpretation of ZF + V = L in ZF. We have already verified that σ L holds

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Part II Logic and Set Theory Part II Logic and Set Theory Theorems Based on lectures by I. B. Leader Notes taken by Dexter Chua Lent 2015 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory Metainduction in Operational Set Theory Luis E. Sanchis Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Syracuse University Syracuse, NY 13244-4100 Sanchis@top.cis.syr.edu http://www.cis.syr.edu/

More information

The complexity of recursive constraint satisfaction problems.

The complexity of recursive constraint satisfaction problems. The complexity of recursive constraint satisfaction problems. Victor W. Marek Department of Computer Science University of Kentucky Lexington, KY 40506, USA marek@cs.uky.edu Jeffrey B. Remmel Department

More information

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. We prove several equivalences and relative consistency results involving notions of generic absoluteness beyond Woodin s ) (Σ

More information

Informal Statement Calculus

Informal Statement Calculus FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS Branches of Logic 1. Theory of Computations (i.e. Recursion Theory). 2. Proof Theory. 3. Model Theory. 4. Set Theory. Informal Statement Calculus STATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES Example

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Jouko Väänänen 1,2 1 Department of Mathematics and Statistics, University of Helsinki 2 Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam Beijing, June

More information

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic 1. Background and Motivation Why use proof theory to study theories of arithmetic? 2. Conservation Results Showing that if a theory T 1 proves ϕ,

More information

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness

Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook and T. Pitassi) Fall, 2014 Herbrand Theorem, Equality, and Compactness The Herbrand Theorem We now consider a complete method for proving the unsatisfiability of sets of first-order

More information

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007 Modern Model Theory Begins Theorem (Morley 1965) If a countable first order theory is categorical in one uncountable cardinal it is categorical in all uncountable cardinals. Outline 1 2 3 SELF-CONSCIOUS

More information

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Alf Dolich Kingsborough Community College Julia F. Knight University of Notre Dame Karen Lange Wellesley College David Marker University of Illinois at Chicago

More information

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, we construct a model in which there exists an ω 2 -Aronszajn tree, the ω 1 -approachability

More information

Scott processes. Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014

Scott processes. Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014 Scott processes Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014 Abstract The Scott process of a relational structure M is the sequence of sets of formulas given by the Scott analysis of M. We present axioms for the class

More information

DEGREES OF CATEGORICITY AND THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY

DEGREES OF CATEGORICITY AND THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY DEGREES OF CATEGORICITY AND THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY BARBARA F. CSIMA, JOHANNA N. Y. FRANKLIN, AND RICHARD A. SHORE Abstract. We study arithmetic and hyperarithmetic degrees of categoricity. We extend

More information

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Wellesley College Wellesley College Digital Scholarship and Archive Faculty Research and Scholarship 8-2015 Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Alf Dolich Julia F. Knight Karen Lange klange2@wellesley.edu

More information

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game Noah Schoem September 11, 2014 1 Abstract An argument involving the Hydra game shows why ACA 0 is insufficient for a theory of ordinals in which

More information

The Scott Isomorphism Theorem

The Scott Isomorphism Theorem The Scott Isomorphism Theorem Julia F. Knight University of Notre Dame Outline 1. L ω1 ω formulas 2. Computable infinitary formulas 3. Scott sentences 4. Scott rank, result of Montalbán 5. Scott ranks

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

Lecture 7: Recursive saturation

Lecture 7: Recursive saturation MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 7: Recursive saturation Tin Lok Wong 19 November, 2014 One of the most significant by-products of the study of admissible sets with urelements is the emphasis it has

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism

Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism Vassilis Gregoriades TU Darmstadt October 203, Vienna The motivation It is essential for the development of effective descriptive set theory to

More information

Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory

Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory Rachael Alvir November 2016 1 Axioms of KP and Admissible Sets An admissible set is a transitive set A satisfying the axioms of Kripke-Platek Set Theory

More information

Set Theory and Models of Arithmetic ALI ENAYAT. First European Set Theory Meeting

Set Theory and Models of Arithmetic ALI ENAYAT. First European Set Theory Meeting Set Theory and Models of Arithmetic ALI ENAYAT First European Set Theory Meeting Bedlewo, July 12, 2007 PA is finite set theory! There is an arithmetical formula E(x, y) that expresses the x-th digit of

More information

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER Abstract. We show that any countable model of a model complete theory has an elementary extension with a pseudofinite-like

More information

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Lecture 11: Minimal types MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 11: Minimal types Tin Lok Wong 17 December, 2014 Uniform extension operators are used to construct models with nice structural properties Thus, one has a very simple

More information

ON EXISTENCE IN SET THEORY

ON EXISTENCE IN SET THEORY ON EXISTENCE IN SET THEORY RODRIGO A. FREIRE Abstract. The aim of the present paper is to provide a robust classification of valid sentences in set theory by means of existence and related notions and,

More information

ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS PETER A. CHOLAK, CARL G. JOCKUSCH, JR., AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We study the proof theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of

More information

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 s to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 In the problems below L is a signature and X is a set of variables. Problem 0. Define a function λ from the set of finite nonempty sequences of elements

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ Model Theory MARIA MANZANO University of Salamanca, Spain Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ CLARENDON PRESS OXFORD 1999 Contents Glossary of symbols and abbreviations General introduction 1 xix 1 1.0

More information

Classical Propositional Logic

Classical Propositional Logic The Language of A Henkin-style Proof for Natural Deduction January 16, 2013 The Language of A Henkin-style Proof for Natural Deduction Logic Logic is the science of inference. Given a body of information,

More information

On Recognizable Languages of Infinite Pictures

On Recognizable Languages of Infinite Pictures On Recognizable Languages of Infinite Pictures Equipe de Logique Mathématique CNRS and Université Paris 7 JAF 28, Fontainebleau, Juin 2009 Pictures Pictures are two-dimensional words. Let Σ be a finite

More information

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real Generic Absoluteness Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman Abstract We explore the consistency strength of 3 and 4 absoluteness, for a variety of forcing notions. Introduction Shoeneld's absoluteness theorem

More information

SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES

SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES URI ANDREWS AND JULIA F. KNIGHT Abstract. For a countable structure B, the spectrum is the set of Turing degrees of isomorphic copies of B. For complete elementary first order

More information

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin Mathematical Logic 1 First-Order Languages. Symbols. All first-order languages we consider will have the following symbols: (i) variables v 1, v 2, v 3,... ; (ii)

More information

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018 Lecture 2: Syntax January 24, 2018 We now review the basic definitions of first-order logic in more detail. Recall that a language consists of a collection of symbols {P i }, each of which has some specified

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

Realizable Extensions of Intuitionistic Analysis: Brouwer, Kleene, Kripke and the End of Time

Realizable Extensions of Intuitionistic Analysis: Brouwer, Kleene, Kripke and the End of Time Realizable Extensions of Intuitionistic Analysis: Brouwer, Kleene, Kripke and the End of Time Joan Rand Moschovakis Occidental College, Emerita ASL Special Session on Intuitionism and Intuitionistic Logic

More information

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. There is a set of reals U such that for every analytic set A there is a continuous function f which maps U bijectively to A. 1. Introduction A set

More information

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. 20 Definition 20.1. A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. (a) Each natural number n is an ordinal. (b) ω is an ordinal. (a) ω {ω} is an ordinal.

More information

Atomic models higher up

Atomic models higher up Atomic models higher up J. Millar and G. E. Sacks Brown University and Harvard University December 24, 2007 Abstract There exists a countable structure M of Scott rank ω1 CK where ω1 M = ω1 CK and where

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory University of Helsinki

The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory University of Helsinki The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory University of Helsinki John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago June 3, 2016 John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at ChicagoThe Rocky Romance

More information

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems Vol. 10, No. 3, (2013) pp. 103-113 103 PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY S. M. BAGHERI AND M. MONIRI Abstract. We present some model theoretic results for

More information

Limit computable integer parts

Limit computable integer parts Limit computable integer parts Paola D Aquino, Julia Knight, and Karen Lange July 12, 2010 Abstract Let R be a real closed field. An integer part I for R is a discretely ordered subring such that for every

More information

Semantic methods in proof theory. Jeremy Avigad. Department of Philosophy. Carnegie Mellon University.

Semantic methods in proof theory. Jeremy Avigad. Department of Philosophy. Carnegie Mellon University. Semantic methods in proof theory Jeremy Avigad Department of Philosophy Carnegie Mellon University avigad@cmu.edu http://macduff.andrew.cmu.edu 1 Proof theory Hilbert s goal: Justify classical mathematics.

More information

CONTENTS. Appendix C: Gothic Alphabet 109

CONTENTS. Appendix C: Gothic Alphabet 109 Contents 1 Sentential Logic 1 1.1 Introduction............................ 1 1.2 Sentences of Sentential Logic................... 2 1.3 Truth Assignments........................ 7 1.4 Logical Consequence.......................

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 14, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be stably embedded. Let P be P with

More information

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory? Chapter 1 Axiomatic set theory 1.1 Why axiomatic set theory? Essentially all mathematical theories deal with sets in one way or another. In most cases, however, the use of set theory is limited to its

More information

Main Goals. The Computably Enumerable Sets. The Computably Enumerable Sets, Creative Sets

Main Goals. The Computably Enumerable Sets. The Computably Enumerable Sets, Creative Sets Main Goals The Computably Enumerable Sets A Tutorial Peter Cholak University of Notre Dame Department of Mathematics Peter.Cholak.1@nd.edu http://www.nd.edu/~cholak/papers/ http://www.nd.edu/~cholak/papers/cholakkobe.pdf

More information

USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE

USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE MIKAYLA KELLEY Abstract. This paper will establish that ultrapowers can be used to determine whether or not two models have the same theory. More

More information

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background. Model Theory II. 80824 22.10.2006-22.01-2007 (not: 17.12) Time: The first meeting will be on SUNDAY, OCT. 22, 10-12, room 209. We will try to make this time change permanent. Please write ehud@math.huji.ac.il

More information

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS ARTEM CHERNIKOV 1. Intro Motivated by connections with computational complexity (mostly a part of computer scientice today).

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 7 Dec 2017

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 7 Dec 2017 CANONICAL TRUTH MERLIN CARL AND PHILIPP SCHLICHT arxiv:1712.02566v1 [math.lo] 7 Dec 2017 Abstract. We introduce and study a notion of canonical set theoretical truth, which means truth in a transitive

More information

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe: Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe: Ultimate L W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University IMS Graduate Summer School in Logic June 2018 Ordinals: the transfinite numbers is the smallest ordinal: this is

More information

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated Denis R. Hirschfeldt Department of Mathematics University of Chicago, USA Bakhadyr Khoussainov Department of Computer

More information

SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8

SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8 SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8 We are now ready to start work on the proof of the Completeness Theorem for first order logic. Before we start a couple of remarks are in order (1) When we studied propositional

More information

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece Is the amalgamation property for L ω1,ω-sentences absolute for transitive models of ZFC? Logic Seminar - UIC 2018 02 01 Ioannis (Yiannis)

More information

A Sharp for the Chang Model

A Sharp for the Chang Model A Sharp for the Chang Model William Mitchell wjm@ufl.edu University of Florida February 19, 2011 Inner Model Theory & Large Cardinals A 50 Year Celebration Mitchell (University of Florida) A Sharp for

More information

REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction

REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction RELIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERRITHMETIC HIERRCHY S DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE bstract. We construct a class of relations on computable structures

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Well Ordered Sets (continued)

Well Ordered Sets (continued) Well Ordered Sets (continued) Theorem 8 Given any two well-ordered sets, either they are isomorphic, or one is isomorphic to an initial segment of the other. Proof Let a,< and b, be well-ordered sets.

More information

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. Every complete first order theory has a corresponding complete theory in continuous logic, called the randomization theory.

More information

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness.

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness. Goals The fundamental notion of a Stone space is delicate for infinitary logic. I will describe several possibilities. There will be a quiz. Infinitary Logic and Omitting Types Key Insight (Chang, Lopez-Escobar)

More information

Elementary Equivalence, Partial Isomorphisms, and. Scott-Karp analysis

Elementary Equivalence, Partial Isomorphisms, and. Scott-Karp analysis Elementary Equivalence, Partial Isomorphisms, and Scott-Karp analysis 1 These are self-study notes I prepared when I was trying to understand the subject. 1 Elementary equivalence and Finite back and forth

More information

17.1 Correctness of First-Order Tableaux

17.1 Correctness of First-Order Tableaux Applied Logic Lecture 17: Correctness and Completeness of First-Order Tableaux CS 4860 Spring 2009 Tuesday, March 24, 2009 Now that we have introduced a proof calculus for first-order logic we have to

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

Classification and Measure for Algebraic Fields

Classification and Measure for Algebraic Fields Classification and Measure for Algebraic Fields Russell Miller Queens College & CUNY Graduate Center Logic Seminar Cornell University 23 August 2017 Russell Miller (CUNY) Classification of Algebraic Fields

More information

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS ASHER M. KACH AND ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We study the connection between the number of ascending and descending cuts of a linear order, its classical size, and its effective

More information

Basics of Model Theory

Basics of Model Theory Chapter udf Basics of Model Theory bas.1 Reducts and Expansions mod:bas:red: defn:reduct mod:bas:red: prop:reduct Often it is useful or necessary to compare languages which have symbols in common, as well

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

Incompleteness Theorems, Large Cardinals, and Automata ov

Incompleteness Theorems, Large Cardinals, and Automata ov Incompleteness Theorems, Large Cardinals, and Automata over Finite Words Equipe de Logique Mathématique Institut de Mathématiques de Jussieu - Paris Rive Gauche CNRS and Université Paris 7 TAMC 2017, Berne

More information

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos armandobcm@yahoo.com February 5, 2014 Abstract This note is for personal use. It

More information

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6 MAGIC Set theory lecture 6 David Asperó Delivered by Jonathan Kirby University of East Anglia 19 November 2014 Recall: We defined (V : 2 Ord) by recursion on Ord: V 0 = ; V +1 = P(V ) V = S {V : < } if

More information

A Sharp for the Chang Model

A Sharp for the Chang Model A Sharp for the Chang Model William Mitchell wjm@ufl.edu University of Florida February 19, 2011 Inner Model Theory & Large Cardinals A 50 Year Celebration Mitchell (University of Florida) A Sharp for

More information

Overview of Topics. Finite Model Theory. Finite Model Theory. Connections to Database Theory. Qing Wang

Overview of Topics. Finite Model Theory. Finite Model Theory. Connections to Database Theory. Qing Wang Overview of Topics Finite Model Theory Part 1: Introduction 1 What is finite model theory? 2 Connections to some areas in CS Qing Wang qing.wang@anu.edu.au Database theory Complexity theory 3 Basic definitions

More information