Increases in Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice in a Complete Market

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Increases in Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice in a Complete Market"

Transcription

1 Increases in Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice in a Complete Market Philip H. Dybvig Yajun Wang August 2, 2009 Abstract We examine the effect of changes in risk aversion on optimal portfolio choice in a complete market. We show that an agent who is less risk averse than another chooses a portfolio whose payoff is distributed as the other s payoff plus a nonnegative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise. Conversely, an agent who chooses a portfolio whose payoff in all complete markets, is distributed as another s payoff plus a nonnegative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise is less risk averse than the other. In this sense, the two portfolio choices represent a trade-off between risk and return, and not only in a mean-variance world. In addition, if either agent has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, then the non-negative random variable can be chosen to be a constant. We are grateful for useful discussions with Hong Liu, Georg Pflug, Steve Ross, and Walter Schachermayer. We also thank An Chen, Jianfeng Zhang for their comments. Dybvig is grateful for the support from the Sloan Research Fellowship program. All remain errors are our own responsibility. Olin Business School, Washington University in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO, Olin Business School, Washington University in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO, 6330.

2 I. Introduction The trade-off between risk and return arises in many portfolio problems in finance. This trade-off is more-or-less assumed in mean-variance optimization, and is also present in the comparative statics for two-asset portfolio problems explored by Arrow (965) and Pratt (964) (for a model with a riskless asset) and Kihlström, Romer, and Williams (98) and Ross (98) (for a model without a riskless asset). However, the trade-off is less clear in portfolio problems with many risky assets, as pointed out by Hart (975). Assuming a complete market with many states (and therefore many assets), we show that a less risk-averse (in the sense of Arrow and Pratt) agent s portfolio payoff is distributed as the payoff for the more risk-averse agent, plus a non-negative random variable (extra return), plus conditional-mean-zero noise (risk). Therefore, the general complete-markets portfolio problem, which may not be a mean-variance problem, still trades off risk and return. We also provide several related results. One is a converse theorem. Suppose there are two agents, such that in all complete markets, the first agent chooses a payoff that is distributed as the second s payoff, plus a non-negative random variable, plus conditional-mean-zero noise. Then the first agent is less risk averse than the other agent. We also prove a multiple-period result. Consumption at each date may not be ordered when risk aversion changes, due to shifts in the timing of consumption. However, for agents with the same pure rate of time preference, there is a weighting of probabilities across periods that preserves the single-period result. We also show that, if either agent has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, then the non-negative random variable can be chosen to be a constant. We also give a counter-example that shows that in general, the non-negative random variable cannot be chosen to be a constant. In this case, the less risk averse agent s payoff can have a higher mean and a lower variance than the more risk averse agent s payoff. 2 This can happen because In a mean-variance world with multivariate normality asset payoffs and increasing concave von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions, a less risk averse agent will choose a higher mean and higher variance. Given joint normality, this implies that the less risk averse agent s payoff is distributed as the other payoff, plus a non-negative constant plus conditional-mean zero noise. 2 As it is already known in the literature, variance is not a good risk measure for von Neumann- Morgenstern utility functions. 2

3 although adding condition-mean-zero noise always increases variance, adding the nonnegative random variable decreases variance if it is sufficiently negatively correlated with rest. The proofs in the paper use results from stochastic dominance, complete-markets portfolio choice, and Arrow-Pratt risk aversion. One contribution of the paper is to show how these concepts relate to each other. We use general versions of the stochastic dominance results for L random variables and monotone concave preferences, following Strassen (965) and Ross (97). To see why our results are related to stochastic dominance, note that if the first agent s payoff equals the second agent s payoff plus a non-negative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise, this is equivalent to saying negative the first agent s payoff is monotone-concave dominated by negative the second agent s payoff. Section II introduces the model setup and gives examples, Section III develops the basic framework and derives the main results. Section IV extends the main results in a multiple-period model. Section V illustrates the main results using some examples and Section VI concludes. II. Model Setup and Examples We want to work in a fairly general setting with complete markets and strictly concave increasing von Neumann-Morgenstern preferences. There are two agents A and B with von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions U A (c) and U B (c), respectively. We assume that U A (c) and U B (c) are of class C 2, U A (c) > 0, U B U B (c) < 0. Each agent s problem has the form: Problem Choose random consumption c to (c) > 0, U A (c) < 0 and maxe[u i ( c)], s.t. E[ ρ c] = w 0. () In Problem, i = A or B indexes the agent, w 0 is initial wealth (which is the same for both agents), and ρ > 0 is the state price density. We will assume that agents 3

4 have optimal random consumptions, called c A and c B. The first order condition is U ( c) = λ ρ, i.e., the marginal utility is proportional to the state price density ρ. Therefore, the first order conditions for the two agents optima are given by U A( c A ) = λ A ρ, U B( c B ) = λ B ρ, (2) i.e., c A = I A (λ A ρ), c B = I B (λ B ρ), (3) where I A and I B are the inverse function of U A ( ) and U B ( ) respectively, by negativity of the second derivatives, c A and c B are decreasing functions of ρ. Our main result will be that c A d c B + z + ε, where d denotes is distributed as, Prob( z 0) =, and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. Before presenting our main results, we consider two examples to illustrate this result. Example II. B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows U A (c) = 2 ( ) 2 c, U B (c) = ( ) 2 c, a 2 a 2 a i c > 0, i =, 2. a < a 2. We assume that the state price density ρ is uniformly distributed in [0, ]. The first order conditions give us c A = a λ A ρ, c B = a 2 λ B ρ. (4) From the budget constraint E[ ρc] = w 0, (assuming a < 2w 0 and a 2 < 2w 0 ), we ( ) ( ) get that λ A = 3 2a w 0 and λ B = 3 2a 2 w 0. Therefore, c A is uniformly distributed in 2a [ ] [ ] + 3w 0, a and c B is uniformly distributed in 2a 2 + 3w 0, a 2. ( ) E[ c A ] E[ c B ] = 4 a a 2 > 0, and the support of c A is wider than that of c B, let a 2 = 6a 3+6a w 0, i.e., the range of c A is twice of that of c B, and ε has a Bernoulli distribution drawn independently of c B with two equally possible outcomes 3 ( ) 2 2a 2 w 0 ( ) and 3 2 2a 2 w 0. It is not difficult to see that c A is distributed as c B + z + ε, where z = E[ c A ] E[ c B ] and E[ ε c B ] = 0. 4

5 From this example, we can see that an agent who is less risk averse than another chooses a portfolio whose payoff is distributed as the other s payoff plus a nonnegative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise. In this example, this nonnegative random variable z can be chosen to be a constant, and therefore the variance of the less risk averse agent s payoff is higher. In addition, in this example, the random noise ε can be chosen to be independent of c B + z. It is interesting to see whether the results hold for more general utility functions. Can the nonnegative random variable always be chosen to be a constant? Is the variance of the less risk averse agent s payoff always higher? Can the random noise always be chosen to be independent of c B + z? As we can see from the following example, the answers to these questions are negative. Example II.2 B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows ( ) na ( ) nb U A (c) = a c, U B (c) = a c, where a c > 0, n A < n B. The first order conditions give us U A( c A ) = n A ( a c A ) na = λ A ρ, U B( c B ) = n B ( a c B ) nb = λ B ρ. (5) We will prove later in the main results and in Section V that c A c B + z + ε and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. However, we can see that z may not be chosen to be a constant E[ c A ] E[ c B ] > 0 (pick ρ, such that E[ c A ] E[ c B ]). From previous discussion, we know that c A and c B are decreasing functions of ρ, from (5), it is not difficult to see that c A and c a B when ρ 0. Letting c a A = c A (E[ c A ] E[ c B ]), then it is easy to see that there exists c, such that for c > c, we have c A < c B. If c A c B + ε and E[ε c B ] = 0, then Prob(ε > 0) > 0 for any given c B (we will see in Section 3 that ε 0), therefore, esssup c A = inf{a R : µ ({ c B + ε > a}) = 0} > inf{a R : µ ({ c B > a}) = 0} = esssup c B. Contradiction! We conclude that we cannot write c A c B +ε, where E[ε c B ] = 0, this implies that in this example, z cannot be chosen to be a constant. 5

6 We now show that ε cannot be chosen to be independent of c B + z. If ε is independent with c B + z, then we have esssup c A esssup { c B + z} > esssup { c B + z+ ε}. The left inequality is because z is a nonnegative random variable and the right inequality is because Prob( ε > 0) > 0 for any given c B + z and ε 0. Contradiction! To find an example that the variance of the less risk averse agent s payoff can be smaller, we assume that ρ has a discrete distribution, i.e., ρ = 0 with probability 2,3 ρ = with probability and ρ = with probability. From (5), we have c A = ( ) λ n A a n A ρ A. From the budget constraint, E[ ρ c A ] = w 0, (assuming a < 3 6w 0 ). It is not hard to get that V ar( c A ) = 0.42 ( 3 4w ) 2 4a 0 < V ar( c B ) = ( 3 4w 2 4a 0) for n A = 3 and n B = 5, i.e., the variance of the more risk averse agent s payoff is higher. From these examples, we know that the less risk averse agent A s payoff is distributed as the more risk averse agent B s payoff plus a non-negative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise. In general, this non-negative random variable z may not be chosen to be a constant and the random noise ε may not be chosen to be independent of c B + z. Interestingly, the variance of the more risk averse agent s payoff can be higher though the mean of the payoff is always lower. Next example shows that if the utility functions are not strictly concave, then our main results do not hold. Example II.3 B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 = 2 and the utility functions are as follows 3 e 2 c c < 2 c 2 c 4 U A (c) = (c 6 2) < c < 8 2 c c 2 0 e (c 2)/2 c > 2, 3 Having ρ = 0 with positive probability implies there is arbitrage, which is okay because the preferences are satiated, this is not an essential feature of the example. In Corollary, we provide a general condition under which a less risk averse agent s payoff has a higher expected return and a smaller variance. 6

7 U B (c) = e4 2c c < 2 c 2 c 4 6 2) < c < c e (c 2) c > 2. We assume that ρ = with probability and ρ = with probability. Then, it is not difficult to see that c A = (4, 8) and c B = (2, 2) is the optimal consumption for agent A and B for λ A = λ B = 2. However, we cannot order c A and c B. We next present and prove our main results. III. Main Results We now prove our main results. We compare agents risk aversion in the sense of Arrow and Pratt. Recall that we assume that agent B is more risk averse than agent A, and that both utility functions are strictly increasing and strictly concave C 2 functions. By Pratt (964), we have the concave transform characterization U B (c) = G(U A (c)), (6) where G ( ) 0 and G ( ) 0. Therefore, we have: Lemma If B is more risk averse than A, ( c, U B (c) U B ) A U (c) (c) U A (c), then. for any solution to (2) (which may not satisfy the budget constraint ()), there exists some critical consumption level c (can be ± ) such that c A c B when c B c, and such that c A c B when c B c ; 2. assuming c A and c B have finite means, and A and B have equal initial wealths, then E[ c A ] E[ c B ]. Proof: Using the concave transform characterization of more risk averse in (6), the first order condition (2) becomes U A( c A ) = λ A ρ = λ A λ B λ B ρ = λ A λ B G (U A ( c B ))U A( c B ). (7) 7

8 (7) can be written as [ ] λa c A = I A G (U A ( c B )) U A λ ( c B). (8) B Because marginal utility is strictly decreasing, we have c A > c B, if G < λ B λa c A = c B, if G = λ B λa c A < c B, if G > λ B λa. Choose c so that G (U A (c )) = λ B λa if possible, or pick c = if G < λ B λa everywhere or c = + if G > λ B λa everywhere. If c B c, then G (U A ( c B )) G (U A (c )) = λ B λa, i.e., G λ B λa, therefore, c A c B. If c B c, then G (U A ( c B )) G (U A (c )) = λ B λa, i.e., G λ B λa, therefore, c A c B. This proves statement. Now suppose that A and B have equal initial wealths, then the budget constraints for the agents are that E[ ρ c A ] = E[ ρ c B ] = w 0, (9) therefore, we have E[ ρ( c A c B )] = 0, because ρ is inversely related to both c A and c B, ρ is smaller in the states with c B c, in which c A c B and ρ is bigger in the states with c B c, in which c A c B. Let ρ be the critical value corresponding to c, i.e., E[ρ c ] = w 0, then, 0 = E[ ρ( c A c B )] = E[ρ ( c A c B )] + E[( ρ ρ )( c A c B )] ρ E[ c A c B ]. Therefore, E[ c A ] E[ c B ]. Q.E.D. Lemma gives us a sense in which decreasing the agent s risk aversion takes us further from the riskless asset. In fact, we can obtain a more explicit description of how decreasing the agent s risk aversion changes the optimal portfolio choice. The description and proof are both related to monotone concave stochastic dominance. 4 4 We avoid using the concept of second order stochastic dominance in this paper because there are two different definitions in the literature. In this paper, we follow Ross (97): () if E[V (X)] E[V (Y )] for all nondecreasing utility functions, then X monotone stochastically dominates Y ; (2) if E[V (X)] E[V (Y )] for all concave utility functions, then X concave stochastically dominates Y ; 8

9 The following theorem gives a distributional characterization of stochastic dominance for all monotone and concave utility functions of one random variable over another. The form of this result is from Ross (97) and is a special case of a result of Strassen (965) which generalizes a traditional result for bounded random variables to possibly unbounded random variables with finite means. Rothschild and Stiglitz (972) popularized a similar characterization of stochastic dominance for all concave utility functions (which implies equal means) that is a special case of another result of Strassen s. Theorem Let X and Y be two random variables defined in R with finite mean; then E[V (X)] E[V (Y )], for all concave nondecreasing utility function, V ( ), iff Y X Z + ε, where Z 0, and E[ε X Z] = 0. Proof: (Sufficiency) The monotonicity of the utility function and Jensen s inequality yield E[V (Y )] = E[V (X Z + ε)] = E[E[V (X Z + ε) X, Z]] E[V (X Z)] = E[E[V (X Z) X]] E[V (X)]. (Necessity) Let µ be the distribution of X, and let µ 2 be the distribution of Y. From Theorem 9 in Strassen (965), the following two statements are equivalent. (i) For any concave nondecreasing function V (s), V ( s)dµ (s) V ( s)dµ 2 (s), (ii) There exists a submartingale ξ n, n =, 2, such that the distribution of ξ n is µ n, i.e., E[ξ 2 ξ ] ξ. From (ii), we have (iii) ξ 2 = ξ + (E[ξ 2 ξ ] ξ ) + (ξ 2 E[ξ 2 ξ ]), letting Z = (3) if E[V (X)] E[V (Y )] for all concave nondecreasing utility functions, then X monotone concave stochastically dominates Y. 9

10 E[ξ 2 ξ ] ξ 0, and ε = ξ 2 + E[ξ 2 ξ ], we have E[ε ξ + Z] = E[( ξ 2 + E[ξ 2 ξ ]) E[ξ 2 ξ ]] = 0. Then, from (i), we have E[V (X)] E[V (Y )], from (iii), we have Y X+Z ε, where Z E[ Y X] +X and ε Y + E[ Y X], we get Y X Z +ε, where Z 0 and E[ε X Z] = 0. Q.E.D. Now we prove our main results. Theorem 2. If B is weakly more risk averse than A in the sense of Arrow and Pratt, then c A is distributed as c B + z + ε, where z 0 and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. Furthermore, whenever c A c B, neither z nor ε is identically zero. 2. Conversely, if for all distributions of ρ, c A is distributed as c B + z + ε, where z 0 and E[ ε c B + z] = 0, then B is weakly more risk averse than A. Proof: Firstly, we prove result. The first step of the proof is to show that c B monotone concave stochastically dominates c A. By Lemma, c A and c B are monotonely related and there is a critical value c above which c A is weakly larger and below which c B is weakly larger. We have { c A q} { c B q} when q c. This is because if c B q and q c, then c B q c, from Lemma, we have c A c B q, i.e., c A q. Similarly, we have { c A q} { c B q} when q c. By the definition of the distribution functions for c A and c B, this means precisely that F ca (q) F cb (q) for q c, and F ca (q) F cb (q) for q c. (0) Define I(c) = c q= [F ca (q) F cb (q)]dq. () I(+ ) = E[ c A c B ] 0 by integration by parts and Lemma. It is not hard to see E[V ( c B ) V ( c A )] = + 0 V (q)[df cb (q) df ca (q)]

11 + = lim q + V (q)[f c B (q) F ca (q)] lim q V (q)[f c B (q) F ca (q)] V (q)[f cb (q) F ca (q)]dq = + V (q)[f cb (q) F ca (q)]dq, (2) where the limits are zero because c A and c B have finite mean and V ( ) is concave nondecreasing. Now, (2) is equal to + V ( c )[F cb (q) F ca (q)]dq c (V (q) V ( c ))[F cb (q) F ca (q)]dq + (V (q) V ( c ))[F cb (q) F ca (q)]dq. (3) c From the concavity of V ( ) and (0), it is easy to see that the second and third terms in (3) are nonnegative. From monotonicity of V ( ) and I(+ ) 0, we also get that the first term of (3) is nonnegative. Therefore, we get E[V ( c B )] E[V ( c A )]. (4) By Theorem, this says that c A is distributed as c B z + ε, where z 0 and E[ ε c B z] = 0. This is exactly the same as saying that c A is distributed as c B + z + ( ε), where z 0 and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. Relabel ε as ε, and we have proven the first sentence of part of the theorem. To prove the second sentence of part, note that because c A and c B are monotonely related, c A is distributed the same as c B only if c A = c B. Therefore, if c A c B, one or the other of z or ε is not identically zero. Now, if z is identically zero, then ε must not be identically zero, and c A is distributed as c B + ε, by Jensen s inequality, we have E[U A ( c A )] = E[U A ( c B + ε)] = E[E[U A ( c B + ε) c B ]] < E[U A (E[ c B c B ]+E[ ε c B ])] = E[U A ( c B )], which contradicts the optimality of c A for agent A. If ε is identically zero, then z must not be, and c A is distributed as c B + z, where z 0 and is not identically zero, therefore, c A strictly monotone stochastically dominates c B, contradicting optimality

12 of c B for agent B. We prove part 2 by contradiction. If B is not weakly more risk averse than A, then there exists a constant ĉ, such that U B (ĉ) < U B A U (ĉ) (ĉ) U A (ĉ). Since U A and U B are of the class of C 2, from the continuity of U i (c), where i = A, B, we get that there exists an U i (c) interval RA containing ĉ, s.t., c RA, U B (c) < U B A U (c) (c) U A (c). We pick c, c 2 RA with c < c 2. Now we construct agents A and B, so that A agrees with A and B agrees with B on [c, c 2 ], but A is everywhere more risk averse than B (and not just on RA). Specifically, let and let a k exp( U A (c ) c) c < c U A (c ) U A (c) = U A (c) c c c 2 a 2 k 2 exp( U A (c 2) c) c > c U A (c 2) 2, a 3 k 3 exp( U B (c ) c) c < c U B (c ) U B (c) = U B (c) c c c 2 a 4 k 4 exp( U B (c 2) c) c > c U B (c 2) 2, where k j and a j (j=, 2, 3, 4) are determined by the continuity and smoothness of U i (c), for i = A, B. For example, a and k are determined by: ( U A a k exp (c ) ( ) U U A (c ) c A = U A (c ), and k exp (c ) ) U U A (c ) c A (c ) U A (c ) = U A (c ). (5) It is easy to see that U A is in the class of C 2 since from (5), we get: k = (U A (c )) 2 U A (c ) exp ( U A (c ) ( ) U U A (c ) c A = k exp (c ) ( ) U U A (c ) c A (c ) U A (c ) ) 2 = U A(c ). Similarly, we can show that U B (c) is also in the class of C 2. U A (c) < 0, U B (c) < 0, and U B (c) A (c) < U B U, for c, i.e., agent A (c) U A (c) is more risk averse than B. Fix any λ B > 0 and choose any random ρ that takes on all the values on [ U B (c 2) ], then λ B, U B (c ) λ B the corresponding c B solving the F.O.C. U B ( ρ) = λ B c B takes on all the values on [c, c 2 ]. Because U B < 0, the F.O.C solution is also sufficient, c B solves the portfolio 2

13 problem for utility function U B, state price density ρ and initial wealth w 0 = E[ ρ c B ]. Since U B = U B on the support of c B, letting c B = c B, c B solves the corresponding optimization for U B for λ B = λ B. We now show that there exists λ A such that c A I A (λ A ρ) satisfies the budget constraint E[ ρ c A ] = w 0. Due to the choice of U A, I A (λ A ρ) exists and is a bounded random variable for all λ A. Let ρ = U B (c 2) λ B and ρ = U B (c ), then ρ [ρ, ρ], we define λ = U A (c ) ρ and λ 2 = U A (c 2 ) ρ, i.e., c = I A (λ ρ) > I A (λ ρ) and c 2 = I A (λ 2 ρ) < I A (λ 2 ρ). Then, we have E[ ρi A (λ ρ)] < E[ ρc ] < E[ ρ c B ] = w 0, and E[ ρi A (λ 2 ρ)] > E[ ρc 2 ] > E[ ρ c B ] = w 0. Since I A (λ ρ) is continuous from the assumption that U A is in the class of C 2 and U A < 0. By the intermediate value theorem, there exists λ A, such that E[ ρi A (λ A ρ)] = w 0, i.e., c A satisfies the budget constraint for ρ and w 0. Now, let us show that c B has a wider range of support than that of c A when c B c A. Since A is more risk averse than B, from Lemma, we know that there exists c, such that c B c A when c A c, and c B c A when c A c. And we can choose c [c, c 2 ], or else either c B < c A or c B > c A and both could not satisfy the budget constraint. Therefore, c B has a wider range of support than that of c A. Let the support of A s optimal consumption be [c 3, c 4 ] [c, c 2 ]. From the construction of U A, since U A = U A on the support of c A, letting c A = c A, c A solves the corresponding optimization for U A for λ A = λ A. From the first result of this theorem, we get c B c A + z + ε, where z 0 and E[ ε c A + z ] = 0. Furthermore, if c A c B, then neither z nor ε is identically zero. We now show that c A c B. If c A = c B, then we pick any two points, for example, c 3, c 4 (c 3 < c 4 [c, c 2 ]) at which both c A and c B can attain. From the U A first order conditions, we get: (c 3 ) = U B (c 3 ), i.e., U A (c 3 ) = U A (c 4 ) U A (c 4 ) U B (c 4 ) U B (c 3 ) U B (c 4. However, from ) U B (c) ( ) A (c) < U B U, we have: d log U A (c) < 0, i.e., U A (c) decreases in c. We have: (c) U A (c) dc U B (c) U B (c) U A (c 3 ) U B (c 3 ) > U A (c 4 ) U B (c 4 ). Contradiction! So, c A c B, we get that neither z nor ε is identically zero. Therefore, E[ c B ] > E[ c A ], i.e. E[ c B ] > E[ c A ], this contradicts the assumption that c A is distributed as c B + z + ε, where z 0 and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. Q.E.D. λ B 3

14 Theorem 2 shows that if B is weakly more risk averse than A, then c A is distributed as c B plus a risk premium plus random noise. Except that the risk premium has mean equal to the difference of the mean consumptions, the distributions of the risk premium and the noise term are typically not uniquely determined. Also, it is possible that the less risk averse agent s payoff can have a higher mean and a lower variance than the more risk averse agent s payoff as we have seen in example II.2. This can happen because although adding condition-mean-zero noise always increases variance, adding the non-negative random variable decreases variance if it is sufficiently negatively correlated with the rest. More specifically, we have: Corollary If B is weakly more risk averse than A, then V ar( c A ) < V ar( c B ) when Cov( c B, z) < (V ar( z) + V ar( ε)). 2 Proof: We first recall that if E[ ε c B + z] = 0, then Cov( ε, c B + z) = 0. Therefore, V ar( c A ) = V ar( c B )+V ar( ε)+v ar( z)+2cov( c B, z). If Cov( c B, z) < (V ar( z) + V ar( ε)), 2 then V ar( c A ) < V ar( c B ). As it is already known in the literature, Corollary implies that variance may not be a good measure of risk for von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions, and for general distributions in a complete market, mean-variance preferences are hard to justify. If von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions are mean-variance preferences, then they have to be quadratic utility functions, but quadratic preferences are not increasing everywhere and they have increasing risk aversion. Our second main result says that when either of the two agents has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, we can choose z to be non-stochastic. Theorem 3 If B is weakly more risk averse than A and either of the two agents has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, then c A is distributed as c B + z + ε, where z = E[ c A c B ] 0 and E[ ε c B ] = 0. Proof: We first consider the case when A has non-increasing absolute risk aversion. Define the utility function U A ( c) = U A ( c + E[ c A c B ]). Agent A s problem with this utility function and wealth w 0 E[ ρ]e[ c A c B ] is max E[U A ( c + E[ c A c B ])], c 4

15 s.t. E[ ρ( c + E[ c A c B ])] = w 0. (6) The first order conditions are the same as for optimality of c A for agent A. To satisfy the budget constraints, agent A will optimally hold c A E[ c A c B ]. Also, A is less risk averse than B because A is less risk averse than B and non-increasing risk aversion of A implies that A is less risk averse than A. Therefore, by similar arguments as in the proofs of the first result in Lemma and Theorem 2, 5 we can conclude that c A E[ c A c B ] c B + z + ε, (7) where z 0, and E[ ε c B + z] = 0. From (7), we have E[ c A ] = E[E[ c A c B + z]] = E[E[ c B + E[ c A c B ] + z + ε] c B + z] = E[ c A ] + E[ z], so E[ z] = 0. However, z 0, so we must have z = 0. It follows that c A E[ c A c B ] c B + ε, i.e., c A c B + E[ c A c B ] + ε, where E[ ε c B ] = 0. In the case that B has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, the proof is similar except that we define a utility function UB ( c) = U B( c E[ c A c B ]), then agent B with this utility function will optimally hold c B +E[ c A c B ] when given initial wealth w 0 +E[ ρ]e[ c A c B ]. Agent B is weakly more risk averse than B and is therefore more risk averse than A. Q.E.D. The non-increasing absolute risk aversion condition is sufficient but not necessary. A quadratic utility function has increasing absolute risk aversion. But, as we illustrate in example V.2, the non-negative random variable can still be chosen to be a constant for quadratic utility functions. If the non-negative random variable can be chosen to be a constant, then we have the following Corollary: Corollary 2 If B is weakly more risk averse than A and either of the two agents has 5 The details are different from those in Lemma and Theorem 2 because agents A and B have different initial wealth. This is also why we can have z = 0 but not ε = 0. 5

16 non-increasing absolute risk aversion, then V ar( c A ) V ar( c B ). Proof: If the non-negative random variable can be chosen to be a constant, then we have E( ε c B ) = 0, i.e., Cov( ε, c B ) = 0. Therefore, V ar( c A ) = V ar( c B ) + V ar( ε) + 2Cov( c B, ε) = V ar( c B ) + V ar( ε) V ar( c B ). IV. Extension to a Multiple-Period Model We now examine our main results in a multiple period model. We assume that each agent s problem is: Problem 2 max c t E[ s.t. E[ T D t U( c t )], t= T ρ t c t ] = w 0, (8) t= where D t is a discount factor (e.g., D t = e κt if the pure rate of time discount κ is constant), U( ) is the utility function U A ( ) or U B ( ), and ρ t is the state price density in period t. Again, we will assume that both agents have optimal random consumptions, called c At and c Bt. The first order condition gives us U ( c t ) = λ ρt D t. Therefore, the first order conditions for the two agents optima are given by i.e., U A( c At ) = λ A ρ t D t, U B( c Bt ) = λ B ρ t D t, ( ) ( ) ρ t ρ t c At = I A λ A, c Bt = I B λ B, D t D t where I A and I B are the inverse function of U A ( ) and U B ( ) respectively, by negativity of the second derivatives, c At and c Bt are decreasing functions of ρ t. By similar arguments in the one period model, we will have the following results Lemma 2 If B is more risk averse than A, then 6

17 . there exists some critical consumption level c t (can be ± ) such that c At c Bt when c Bt c t, and such that c At c Bt when c Bt c t ; 2. if it happens that the budget shares as a function of time are the same for both agents at some time t, i.e., E[ ρ t c At ] = E[ ρ t c Bt ], then E[ c At ] E[ c Bt ], and we have c At c Bt + z t + ε t, where z t 0 and E[ ε t c Bt + z t ] = 0. And if c At c Bt, then neither z t nor ε t is identically zero. In particular, if the budget shares are the same for all t, then this distributional condition holds for all t. The proof of Lemma 2 is the same as that in the one-period model (Lemma, and Theorem 2, part ). If the D t s are not the same for both agents, or the same for the two agents without any restriction on budget shares, then the distributional condition need not hold in any period. For example, if the more risk averse agent B spends most of the money earlier but the less risk averse agent A spends more later, then the mean payoff could be higher in an earlier period for the more risk averse agent, i.e., E[ c Bt ] > E[ c At ]. Now, assume both agents have the same discount factor D t and choose the period and consumption using a mixture model: first choose t with probability µ t = Dt T, t= Dt and then choose ρ t from its distribution. Then, we will show that, under this probability measure c A c B + z + ε. Definition Suppose the original probability space has probability measure P over states Ω with filtration {F t }. Define the discrete random variable τ on associated probability space (Ω, F, P ) so that P (τ = t) = µ t D t /( T t= D t). Define the state of nature in the product space (t, ω) ˆΩ Ω Ω with t and ω drawn independently. The σ-algebra ˆF is the completion of F F τ. The synthetic probability measure is the one consistent with independence generated from ˆP(f, f) = P (f ) P(f) for all subsets f F and subsets f F τ. The synthetic probability measure assigns a probability measure that looks like mixture model, drawing time first assigning probability µ t to time t, and then drawing from ρ t using its distribution in the original problem. Recall that under the original probability measure, each agent s problem is given in (8). Now we want to write down an equivalent problem, in terms of the choice 7

18 of distribution of each c t, but with the new synthetic probability measure. The consumption c under the new probability space over which synthetic probabilities are defined is a function of ρ and t; we identify c(ρ, t) with what used to be c t (ρ). To write the objective function in terms of the synthetic probabilities, we can write T E[ D t U( c t )] = t= T D t E[U( c t )] = t= T T ( D s )µ t Ê[U( c) t] t= s= = ( T D s ) s= T T µ t Ê[U( c) t] = ( t= s= D s )Ê[U( c)], (9) where Ê denotes the expectation under the synthetic probability. T s= D s is a positive constant, so the objective function is equivalent to maximizing Ê[U( c)]. Now, we can write the budget constraint in terms of the synthetic probabilities, T w 0 = E[ ρ t c t ] = t= T t= µ t E[ ρ t µ t c t ] = T t= ρ µ t Ê[ = Ê[ρ (20) µ c t] µ c]. Then we can apply our single-period result (Theorem 2) to derive that the distributional condition holds on a mixture model of the c A and c B over time: Theorem 4 In a multiple-period model, let c A and c B be the optimal consumption of A and B respectively under the synthetic probability measure, if B is more risk averse than A, then, c A c B + z + ε under the synthetic probabilities, where z 0, Ê[ ε c B + z] = 0. Therefore, if the budget shares are not the same for both agents at each time period t, then as we have seen in Lemma 2, the distributional result need not hold period-by-period in a multi-period model with identical weights over time. However, Theorem 4 implies that the distributional condition still holds under the synthetic probabilities in a multi-period model. This result retains the spirit of our main result while acknowledging that changing risk aversion may cause consumption to shift over time. 8

19 V. More Examples In this section, we illustrate our main results using negative exponential, power, quadratic and hyperbolic absolute risk aversion (HARA) utility functions. First we have a result that is useful for analyzing the examples. Lemma 3 For any random variable x, and all m >, x E[x] second order stochastically dominates m(x E[x]). Proof: Let x = x E[x], x 2 = m(x E[x]), we have F x2 (q) = Prob[m(x E(x)) < q] = Prob[x E(x) < q m ] = F x ( q m ), therefore, { Fx2(q) F x(q) q 0 F x2 (q) > F x (q) q < 0. Because + (F x 2 (q) F x (q))dq = 0, we have S(z) = z (F x 2 (q) F x (q))dq 0, z, i.e., x E[x] second order stochastically dominates m(x E[x]). Q.E.D. Example V. (Negative Exponential Utility (CARA)) B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows The first order conditions give us from (2), we have U A (c) = e a c, U B (c) = e a 2c, a < a 2. U A ( c A) U B ( c B) = k, k > 0. i.e., a c A = a 2 c B ln k, (2) E[ρa c A ] = E[ρa 2 c B ] E[ρ ln k], i.e., ln k = a a 2 w 0. E[ρ] Therefore, c A E[ρ] w 0 = a 2 a ( cb E[ρ] w 0 ), 9

20 it follows that c A E[ c A ] = a 2 a ( c B E[ c B ]). From Lemma 3, we get c B E[ c B ] second stochastic dominates c A E[ c A ]. It follows that c A E[ c A ] c B E[ c B ]+ε, i.e., c A c B +E[ c A ] E[ c B ]+ε, and E[ε c B ] = 0. Example V.2 (Quadratic Utility (IARA)) B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows U A (c) = 2 ( ) 2 c, U B (c) = ( ) 2 c, a 2 a 2 The first order conditions give us From (22), we have a i c > 0, i =, 2. a < a 2. U A ( c ( ) A) U B ( c B) = k, k > 0. i.e., c A = k c B, (22) a a 2 k = a E[ρ] w 0 >. a 2 E[ρ] w 0 Therefore, c A E[ c A ] = k( c B E[ c B ]) with k >, from Lemma 3, we have c A E[ c A ] c B E[ c B ] + ε, i.e., c A c B + E[ c A ] E[ c B ] + ε, and E[ε c B ] = 0. Example V.3 (Power Utility (DARA)) B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows U A (c) = c γ γ, U B (c) = c γ2 γ 2, γ i > 0, γ i, i =, 2. The first order conditions give us c A = k c γ 2/γ B, k > 0, (23) 20

21 it is not hard to see that { ca c B c B ( ) γ /(γ 2 γ ) k c A < c B c B < ( γ /(γ 2 γ ) k). From Theorem 2 and 3, it follows that c A c B + E[ c A ] E[ c B ] + ε, and E[ε c B ] = 0. Example V.4 (Hyperbolic Absolute Risk Aversion (HARA))quad B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows U i (c) = { (c ci0 ) γ γ γ > 0, γ log(c c i0 ) γ, where c i0 (i = A, B) is the subsistence consumption for agent A and B, c A0 < c B0. The first order conditions give us c A c A0 = k( c B c B0 ), (24) From (24), we get k = w 0 c A0 E[ρ] w 0 c B0 E[ρ] >, from Lemma 3, we have c A E[ c A ] c B E[ c B ] + ε, i.e., c A c B + E[ c A ] E[ c B ] + ε, E[ε c B ] = 0. The following example provides details for example II.2. It says that the random variable z cannot be chosen to be a constant in some case. Example V.5 B is more risk averse than A, A and B have the same initial wealth w 0 and the utility functions are as follows ( ) na ( ) nb U A (c) = a c, U B (c) = a c, where a c > 0, n A < n B. 2

22 From (5), we get: n A ( a c A ) na = λ ( ) nb A n B λ B a c B, i.e., ( c A = ( a λa n B c a B λ B n A ) nb ) n A. (25) We have: ) (n c A c B c B A λ n B B n A a n B λ A ) (n c A < c B c B < A λ n B B n A a n B λ A. From the proof of Theorem (2), we know that c A c B + z + ε and E[ ε c B +z] = 0. However, we can see that z may not be chosen to be a constant E[ c A ] E[ c B ] from previous discussion in Section II. VI. Concluding Remarks In a complete market, we show that an agent who is less risk averse than another will choose a portfolio whose payoff is distributed as the other s payoff plus a nonnegative random variable plus conditional-mean-zero noise. This result holds for any strictly concave C 2 utility function. If either agent has non-increasing absolute risk aversion, then the non-negative random variable can be chosen to be a constant. The nonincreasing absolute risk aversion condition is sufficient but not necessary. We also provide a counter example, such that, in general, this non-negative random variable cannot be chosen to be a constant. We further show a converse theorem. If the first agent chooses a payoff that is distributed as the second s payoff, plus a non-negative random variable, plus conditionalmean-zero noise in all complete markets, then the first agent is less risk averse than the second agent. We also extend our main results to a multiple period model. Due to shifts in the timing of consumption, agents s optimal consumption at each date may not be ordered when risk aversion changes. However, for agents with the same 22

23 pure rate of time preference, there is a weighting of probabilities across periods that preserves the single-period result. The optimal consumption may not be ordered for agents with different risk aversion when agents utility functions are concave but not strictly concave as we have shown in example II.3. Intuitively, the problem is that even with identical preferences, two different optimal consumptions may not be ordered. We conjecture that our main results hold for weakly concave preferences for some canonical choice of optimal consumption for each agent. We leave this to future research. Our paper derives comparative statics results in complete markets for agents with von Neumann-Morgenstern preferences. Machina (989) has shown that many previous comparative statics results generalize to the broader class of Machina preferences (Machina (982)). Our proofs do not generalize obviously to this class, but we conjecture that our results are still true for Machina preferences. 23

24 References [] Arrow, Kenneth J. (965) Aspects of the Theory of Risk-Bearing Helsinki: Yrjo Jahnssonin Saatio. [2] Arrow, Kenneth J. (97) The Theory of Risk Aversion Chapter 3 in Essays in the Theory of Risk Bearing. New York: American Elsevier, 97. [3] Hadar, J., and W.R. Russell (969) Rules for Ordering Uncertain Prospects. American Economic Review 59, [4] Hart, O. (975) Some negatives results on the existence of comparative static results in portfolio theory. Review of Economic Studies, 42, [5] Kihlstrom, Richard E., David Romer, and Steve Williams (98) Risk Aversion with Random Initial Wealth. Econometrica 49, [6] Machina (982) Expected Utility Analysis without the Independence Axiom. Econometrica, March, 982. [7] Machina (989) Comparative Statics and Non-Expected Utility Preferences. Journal of Economic Theory, April, 989. [8] Pratt, John W. (964) Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large. Econometrica 32, [9] Ross, Stephen A. (97) Risk and Efficiency. Discussion Paper No. 96 [0] Ross, Stephen A. (98) Some Stronger Measures of Risk Aversion in the Small and the Large with Applications. Econometrica 49, [] Rothschild, M. and J.E. Stiglitz (970) Increasing Risk: I. A. Definition. Journal of Economic Theory Vol.2, No.3. [2] Rothschild, M. and J.E. Stiglitz (972) Addendum to Increasing Risk: I. A. Definition. Journal of Economic Theory 5,

25 [3] V. Strassen (965) The Existence of Probability Measures With Given Marginals The Annals of Mathematical Statistics. 36,

Increases in Risk Aversion and the Distribution of Portfolio Payoffs

Increases in Risk Aversion and the Distribution of Portfolio Payoffs Increases in Risk Aversion and the Distribution of Portfolio Payoffs Philip H. Dybvig Yajun Wang July 14, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we derive new comparative statics results in the distribution of portfolio

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1

Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1 Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1 Guenter Franke 2, Richard C. Stapleton 3 and Marti G Subrahmanyam 4 September 23, 2005 1 We are very much indebted to two unknown referees for their excellent comments.

More information

Incremental Risk Vulnerability

Incremental Risk Vulnerability Incremental Risk Vulnerability Guenter Franke 1, Richard C. Stapleton 2 and Marti G Subrahmanyam 3 December 15, 2003 1 Fakultät für Wirtschaftswissenschaften und Statistik, University of Konstanz, email:

More information

Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1

Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1 Incremental Risk Vulnerability 1 Guenter Franke 2, Richard C. Stapleton 3 and Marti G Subrahmanyam 4 June 13, 2005 1 We are very much indebted to two unknown referees for their excellent comments. Section

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION

FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION FINANCIAL OPTIMIZATION Lecture 1: General Principles and Analytic Optimization Philip H. Dybvig Washington University Saint Louis, Missouri Copyright c Philip H. Dybvig 2008 Choose x R N to minimize f(x)

More information

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in Notes on Recursive Utility Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in Section 1 (or Chapter 29, LeRoy & Werner, 2nd Ed.) Let u st be the continuation utility at s t. That

More information

Fundamentals in Optimal Investments. Lecture I

Fundamentals in Optimal Investments. Lecture I Fundamentals in Optimal Investments Lecture I + 1 Portfolio choice Portfolio allocations and their ordering Performance indices Fundamentals in optimal portfolio choice Expected utility theory and its

More information

Measuring the informativeness of economic actions and. market prices 1. Philip Bond, University of Washington. September 2014

Measuring the informativeness of economic actions and. market prices 1. Philip Bond, University of Washington. September 2014 Measuring the informativeness of economic actions and market prices 1 Philip Bond, University of Washington September 2014 1 I thank Raj Singh for some very constructive conversations, along with a seminar

More information

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny.

1 Uncertainty. These notes correspond to chapter 2 of Jehle and Reny. These notes correspond to chapter of Jehle and Reny. Uncertainty Until now we have considered our consumer s making decisions in a world with perfect certainty. However, we can extend the consumer theory

More information

FINM6900 Finance Theory Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium for Multiple Risky Assets

FINM6900 Finance Theory Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium for Multiple Risky Assets FINM69 Finance Theory Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium for Multiple Risky Assets February 3, 212 Reference Anat R. Admati, A Noisy Rational Expectations Equilibrium for Multi-Asset Securities Markets,

More information

(6, 4) Is there arbitrage in this market? If so, find all arbitrages. If not, find all pricing kernels.

(6, 4) Is there arbitrage in this market? If so, find all arbitrages. If not, find all pricing kernels. Advanced Financial Models Example sheet - Michaelmas 208 Michael Tehranchi Problem. Consider a two-asset model with prices given by (P, P 2 ) (3, 9) /4 (4, 6) (6, 8) /4 /2 (6, 4) Is there arbitrage in

More information

Choice under uncertainty

Choice under uncertainty Choice under uncertainty Expected utility theory The agent chooses among a set of risky alternatives (lotteries) Description of risky alternatives (lotteries) a lottery L = a random variable on a set of

More information

Utility Theory CHAPTER Single period utility theory

Utility Theory CHAPTER Single period utility theory CHAPTER 7 Utility Theory 7.. Single period utility theory We wish to use a concept of utility that is able to deal with uncertainty. So we introduce the von Neumann Morgenstern utility function. The investor

More information

Asset Pricing. Chapter V. Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Part I. June 20, 2006

Asset Pricing. Chapter V. Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Part I. June 20, 2006 Chapter V. Risk Aversion and Investment Decisions, Part I June 20, 2006 The Canonical Portfolio Problem The various problems considered in this chapter (and the next) max a EU(Ỹ1) = max EU (Y 0 (1 + r

More information

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2 ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2 Diderik Lund Department of Economics University of Oslo 26 August 2013 Diderik Lund, Dept. of Economics, UiO ECON4510 Lecture 2 26 August 2013 1 / 31 Risk aversion and

More information

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota

Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS. Jan Werner. University of Minnesota Course Handouts ECON 4161/8001 MICROECONOMIC ANALYSIS Jan Werner University of Minnesota FALL SEMESTER 2017 1 PART I: Producer Theory 1. Production Set Production set is a subset Y of commodity space IR

More information

Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions

Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions Stochastic Dominance and Prospect Dominance with Subjective Weighting Functions Haim Levy *, Zvi Wiener * Second version 2/15/98 Please address your correspondence to Haim Levy at Business School, The

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions MICROECONOMICS

Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions MICROECONOMICS Prerequisites Almost essential: Consumption and Uncertainty Probability Distributions RISK MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell July 2017 1 Risk and uncertainty In dealing with uncertainty

More information

A SECOND ORDER STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE PORTFOLIO EFFICIENCY MEASURE

A SECOND ORDER STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE PORTFOLIO EFFICIENCY MEASURE K Y B E R N E I K A V O L U M E 4 4 ( 2 0 0 8 ), N U M B E R 2, P A G E S 2 4 3 2 5 8 A SECOND ORDER SOCHASIC DOMINANCE PORFOLIO EFFICIENCY MEASURE Miloš Kopa and Petr Chovanec In this paper, we introduce

More information

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS MANUELA GHICA We give some necessary conditions for weak efficiency and proper efficiency portfolios for a reinsurance market in nonconvex optimization

More information

Lecture 6: Recursive Preferences

Lecture 6: Recursive Preferences Lecture 6: Recursive Preferences Simon Gilchrist Boston Univerity and NBER EC 745 Fall, 2013 Basics Epstein and Zin (1989 JPE, 1991 Ecta) following work by Kreps and Porteus introduced a class of preferences

More information

Learning and Risk Aversion

Learning and Risk Aversion Learning and Risk Aversion Carlos Oyarzun Texas A&M University Rajiv Sarin Texas A&M University January 2007 Abstract Learning describes how behavior changes in response to experience. We consider how

More information

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1 ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 1 Diderik Lund Department of Economics University of Oslo 18 January 2016 Diderik Lund, Dept. of Economics, UiO ECON4510 Lecture 1 18 January 2016 1 / 38 Administrative

More information

Consumption. Consider a consumer with utility. v(c τ )e ρ(τ t) dτ.

Consumption. Consider a consumer with utility. v(c τ )e ρ(τ t) dτ. Consumption Consider a consumer with utility v(c τ )e ρ(τ t) dτ. t He acts to maximize expected utility. Utility is increasing in consumption, v > 0, and concave, v < 0. 1 The utility from consumption

More information

Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market

Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market 1/51 Competitive Equilibria in a Comonotone Market Ruodu Wang http://sas.uwaterloo.ca/ wang Department of Statistics and Actuarial Science University of Waterloo

More information

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem Sofia Moroni and Jeroen Swinkels April, 23 Abstract We provide a class of counter-examples to existence in a simple moral hazard problem

More information

THE UTILITY PREMIUM. Louis Eeckhoudt, Catholic Universities of Mons and Lille Research Associate CORE

THE UTILITY PREMIUM. Louis Eeckhoudt, Catholic Universities of Mons and Lille Research Associate CORE THE UTILITY PREMIUM Louis Eeckhoudt, Catholic Universities of Mons and Lille Research Associate CORE Harris Schlesinger, University of Alabama, CoFE Konstanz Research Fellow CESifo * Beatrice Rey, Institute

More information

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014

Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility. I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications. Decision Theory Spring 2014 Von Neumann Morgenstern Expected Utility I. Introduction, Definitions, and Applications Decision Theory Spring 2014 Origins Blaise Pascal, 1623 1662 Early inventor of the mechanical calculator Invented

More information

COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY

COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR RANK-DEPENDENT EXPECT- ED UTILITY THEORY John Quiggin Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics University of Maryland Quiggin, J. (1991), Comparative statics for Rank-Dependent

More information

Chapter 4. Applications/Variations

Chapter 4. Applications/Variations Chapter 4 Applications/Variations 149 4.1 Consumption Smoothing 4.1.1 The Intertemporal Budget Economic Growth: Lecture Notes For any given sequence of interest rates {R t } t=0, pick an arbitrary q 0

More information

SUPPLEMENT TO THE COMPARATIVE STATICS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION PROBLEMS (Econometrica, Vol. 75, No. 2, March 2007, )

SUPPLEMENT TO THE COMPARATIVE STATICS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION PROBLEMS (Econometrica, Vol. 75, No. 2, March 2007, ) Econometrica Supplementary Material SUPPLEMENT TO THE COMPARATIVE STATICS OF CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION PROBLEMS (Econometrica, Vol. 75, No. 2, March 2007, 40 43) BY JOHN K.-H. QUAH The purpose of this supplement

More information

University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming

University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists 1 of 63 University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming Peter J. Hammond Autumn 2013, revised 2014 University of

More information

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015

arxiv: v1 [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 2015 Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large under Rank-Dependent Utility arxiv:52.08037v [q-fin.mf] 25 Dec 205 Louis R. Eeckhoudt IESEG School of Management Catholic University of Lille and CORE Louis.Eeckhoudt@fucam.ac.be

More information

Corrections to Theory of Asset Pricing (2008), Pearson, Boston, MA

Corrections to Theory of Asset Pricing (2008), Pearson, Boston, MA Theory of Asset Pricing George Pennacchi Corrections to Theory of Asset Pricing (8), Pearson, Boston, MA. Page 7. Revise the Independence Axiom to read: For any two lotteries P and P, P P if and only if

More information

Minimal Sufficient Conditions for a Primal Optimizer in Nonsmooth Utility Maximization

Minimal Sufficient Conditions for a Primal Optimizer in Nonsmooth Utility Maximization Finance and Stochastics manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Minimal Sufficient Conditions for a Primal Optimizer in Nonsmooth Utility Maximization Nicholas Westray Harry Zheng. Received: date

More information

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies Takashi Kamihigashi September 28, 2015 Abstract We show a simple no-bubble theorem that applies to a wide range of deterministic sequential

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

100 if α=red 0 if α=red f A,r = f A,b =

100 if α=red 0 if α=red f A,r = f A,b = 14.123 Problem Set 2 Solution Suehyun Kwon Q1. There are two urns, A and B, each consisting of 100 balls, some are black and some are red. In urn A there are 30 red balls, but the number of red balls in

More information

market prices 1 Philip Bond, University of Washington July 2015

market prices 1 Philip Bond, University of Washington July 2015 Measuring the informativeness of economic actions and market prices 1 Philip Bond, University of Washington July 2015 1 I thank Mehmet Eckmekci and Raj Singh for some very constructive comments, along

More information

WORKING PAPER MASSACHUSETTS ALFRED P. SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT. c.x CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 50 MEMORIAL DRIVE

WORKING PAPER MASSACHUSETTS ALFRED P. SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT. c.x CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 50 MEMORIAL DRIVE rr u-" '^ " r\ liivjfi >-^ K^- -^.^, c.x WORKING PAPER ALFRED P. SLOAN SCHOOL OF MANAGEMENT A NOTE ON THE NECESSARY CONDITION FOR LINEAR SHARING t AND SEPARATION by Chi-fu Huang" and Robert Li tzenberger"

More information

Pedantic Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion

Pedantic Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Pedantic Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion KC Border May 1996 1 Preliminaries The risk premium π u (w, Z) for an expected utility decision maker

More information

Toward a Systematic Approach to the Economic Effects of Risk: Characterizing Utility Functions

Toward a Systematic Approach to the Economic Effects of Risk: Characterizing Utility Functions Toward a Systematic Approach to the Economic Effects of Risk: Characterizing Utility Functions Christian GOLLIER Toulouse School of Economics Miles S. KIMBALL University of Colorado Boulder March 27, 2018

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

Dynamic Risk Measures and Nonlinear Expectations with Markov Chain noise

Dynamic Risk Measures and Nonlinear Expectations with Markov Chain noise Dynamic Risk Measures and Nonlinear Expectations with Markov Chain noise Robert J. Elliott 1 Samuel N. Cohen 2 1 Department of Commerce, University of South Australia 2 Mathematical Insitute, University

More information

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015

ANSWER KEY. University of California, Davis Date: June 22, 2015 ANSWER KEY University of California, Davis Date: June, 05 Department of Economics Time: 5 hours Microeconomic Theory Reading Time: 0 minutes PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE Please answer four

More information

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B Lecture 2 Giulio Fella c Giulio Fella, 2014 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B - Lecture 2 40/197 Aim of consumption theory Consumption theory aims at explaining consumption/saving decisions

More information

Macroeconomic Theory II Homework 2 - Solution

Macroeconomic Theory II Homework 2 - Solution Macroeconomic Theory II Homework 2 - Solution Professor Gianluca Violante, TA: Diego Daruich New York University Spring 204 Problem The household has preferences over the stochastic processes of a single

More information

f( x) f( y). Functions which are not one-to-one are often called many-to-one. Take the domain and the range to both be all the real numbers:

f( x) f( y). Functions which are not one-to-one are often called many-to-one. Take the domain and the range to both be all the real numbers: I. UNIVARIATE CALCULUS Given two sets X and Y, a function is a rule that associates each member of X with exactly one member of Y. That is, some x goes in, and some y comes out. These notations are used

More information

Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion

Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Notes on the Risk Premium and Risk Aversion KC Border May 1996 1 Preliminaries The risk premium π u (w, Z) for an expected

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Choice Under Uncertainty

Choice Under Uncertainty Choice Under Uncertainty Z a finite set of outcomes. P the set of probabilities on Z. p P is (p 1,...,p n ) with each p i 0 and n i=1 p i = 1 Binary relation on P. Objective probability case. Decision

More information

Online Supplement to Coarse Competitive Equilibrium and Extreme Prices

Online Supplement to Coarse Competitive Equilibrium and Extreme Prices Online Supplement to Coarse Competitive Equilibrium and Extreme Prices Faruk Gul Wolfgang Pesendorfer Tomasz Strzalecki September 9, 2016 Princeton University. Email: fgul@princeton.edu Princeton University.

More information

What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems:

What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems: Moral Hazard in Teams What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems: i) If many agents produce a joint output x, how does one assign the output? There is a free rider problem here as

More information

Joint-Search Theory. Bulent Guler 1 Fatih Guvenen 2 Gianluca Violante 3. Indiana University

Joint-Search Theory. Bulent Guler 1 Fatih Guvenen 2 Gianluca Violante 3. Indiana University Joint-Search Theory Bulent Guler 1 Fatih Guvenen 2 Gianluca Violante 3 1 Indiana University 2 University of Minnesota 3 New York University Indiana University GGV (UT-Austin, NYU) Joint-Search Theory IUB

More information

Uncertain risk aversion

Uncertain risk aversion J Intell Manuf (7) 8:65 64 DOI.7/s845-4-3-5 Uncertain risk aversion Jian Zhou Yuanyuan Liu Xiaoxia Zhang Xin Gu Di Wang Received: 5 August 4 / Accepted: 8 November 4 / Published online: 7 December 4 Springer

More information

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies Takashi Kamihigashi March 26, 2016 Abstract We show a simple no-bubble theorem that applies to a wide range of deterministic sequential

More information

97/29/FIN. * Professor of Finance at INSEAD, Boulevard de Constance, Fontainebleau Cedex, France.

97/29/FIN. * Professor of Finance at INSEAD, Boulevard de Constance, Fontainebleau Cedex, France. MONOTONE RISK AVERSION by L. T. NIELSEN* 97/29/FIN * Professor of Finance at INSEAD, Boulevard de Constance, Fontainebleau 77305 Cedex, France. A working paper in the INSEAD Working Paper Series is intended

More information

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais Microeconomics Fall 2016 Indirect utility and expenditure Properties of consumer demand The indirect utility function The relationship among prices, incomes, and the maximised value of utility can be summarised

More information

Robust Comparative Statics of Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

Robust Comparative Statics of Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Robust Comparative Statics of Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Carmen Camacho Takashi Kamihigashi Çağrı Sağlam June 9, 2015 Abstract A policy change that involves redistribution of income

More information

Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums

Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums Comonotonicity and Maximal Stop-Loss Premiums Jan Dhaene Shaun Wang Virginia Young Marc J. Goovaerts November 8, 1999 Abstract In this paper, we investigate the relationship between comonotonicity and

More information

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 1 7 Moral Hazard: Hidden Actions PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODELS The principal (or uninformed player) is the player who has

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 24 Sep 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 24 Sep 2018 A short note on Anticipative portfolio optimization B. D Auria a,b,1,, J.-A. Salmerón a,1 a Dpto. Estadística, Universidad Carlos III de Madrid. Avda. de la Universidad 3, 8911, Leganés (Madrid Spain b

More information

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory Review of Economic Analysis 4 (01) 67-75 1973-3909/01067 Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory TAPAN BISWAS University of Hull 1 Introduction The axiomatic foundation of the expected

More information

A Test for Risk-Averse Expected Utility

A Test for Risk-Averse Expected Utility A Test for Risk-Averse Expected Utility Christopher P Chambers, Ce Liu, and Seung-Keun Martinez February 29, 2016 Abstract We provide a universal condition for rationalizability by risk-averse expected

More information

Optimal Control. Macroeconomics II SMU. Ömer Özak (SMU) Economic Growth Macroeconomics II 1 / 112

Optimal Control. Macroeconomics II SMU. Ömer Özak (SMU) Economic Growth Macroeconomics II 1 / 112 Optimal Control Ömer Özak SMU Macroeconomics II Ömer Özak (SMU) Economic Growth Macroeconomics II 1 / 112 Review of the Theory of Optimal Control Section 1 Review of the Theory of Optimal Control Ömer

More information

Proving the Regularity of the Minimal Probability of Ruin via a Game of Stopping and Control

Proving the Regularity of the Minimal Probability of Ruin via a Game of Stopping and Control Proving the Regularity of the Minimal Probability of Ruin via a Game of Stopping and Control Erhan Bayraktar University of Michigan joint work with Virginia R. Young, University of Michigan K αρλoβασi,

More information

of space-time diffusions

of space-time diffusions Optimal investment for all time horizons and Martin boundary of space-time diffusions Sergey Nadtochiy and Michael Tehranchi October 5, 2012 Abstract This paper is concerned with the axiomatic foundation

More information

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

September Math Course: First Order Derivative September Math Course: First Order Derivative Arina Nikandrova Functions Function y = f (x), where x is either be a scalar or a vector of several variables (x,..., x n ), can be thought of as a rule which

More information

ИЗМЕРЕНИЕ РИСКА MEASURING RISK Arcady Novosyolov Institute of computational modeling SB RAS Krasnoyarsk, Russia,

ИЗМЕРЕНИЕ РИСКА MEASURING RISK Arcady Novosyolov Institute of computational modeling SB RAS Krasnoyarsk, Russia, ИЗМЕРЕНИЕ РИСКА EASURING RISK Arcady Novosyolov Institute of computational modeling SB RAS Krasnoyarsk, Russia, anov@ksckrasnru Abstract Problem of representation of human preferences among uncertain outcomes

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming

Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming David Laibson 9/04/2014 Outline: 1. Functional operators 2. Iterative solutions for the Bellman Equation 3. Contraction Mapping Theorem

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs

The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs The Asymptotic Theory of Transaction Costs Lecture Notes by Walter Schachermayer Nachdiplom-Vorlesung, ETH Zürich, WS 15/16 1 Models on Finite Probability Spaces In this section we consider a stock price

More information

FIN 550 Practice Exam Answers. A. Linear programs typically have interior solutions.

FIN 550 Practice Exam Answers. A. Linear programs typically have interior solutions. FIN 550 Practice Exam Answers Phil Dybvig. True-False 25 points A. Linear programs typically have interior solutions. False. Unless the objective is zero, all solutions are at the boundary. B. A local

More information

Moral Hazard: Characterization of SB

Moral Hazard: Characterization of SB Moral Hazard: Characterization of SB Ram Singh Department of Economics March 2, 2015 Ram Singh (Delhi School of Economics) Moral Hazard March 2, 2015 1 / 19 Characterization of Second Best Contracts I

More information

Concavity of the Consumption Function with Recursive Preferences

Concavity of the Consumption Function with Recursive Preferences Concavity of the Consumption Function with Recursive Preferences Semyon Malamud May 21, 2014 Abstract Carroll and Kimball 1996) show that the consumption function for an agent with time-separable, isoelastic

More information

Economics 2010c: Lectures 9-10 Bellman Equation in Continuous Time

Economics 2010c: Lectures 9-10 Bellman Equation in Continuous Time Economics 2010c: Lectures 9-10 Bellman Equation in Continuous Time David Laibson 9/30/2014 Outline Lectures 9-10: 9.1 Continuous-time Bellman Equation 9.2 Application: Merton s Problem 9.3 Application:

More information

ECON 2010c Solution to Problem Set 1

ECON 2010c Solution to Problem Set 1 ECON 200c Solution to Problem Set By the Teaching Fellows for ECON 200c Fall 204 Growth Model (a) Defining the constant κ as: κ = ln( αβ) + αβ αβ ln(αβ), the problem asks us to show that the following

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

University of California Berkeley

University of California Berkeley Working Paper #2018-02 Infinite Horizon CCAPM with Stochastic Taxation and Monetary Policy Revised from the Center for Risk Management Research Working Paper 2018-01 Konstantin Magin, University of California,

More information

Risk Aversion and Risk Vulnerability in the Continuous and Discrete Case

Risk Aversion and Risk Vulnerability in the Continuous and Discrete Case Decisions in Economics and Finance manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor Risk Aversion and Risk Vulnerability in the Continuous and Discrete Case A Unified Treatment with Extensions Martin Bohner

More information

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting

Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Traeger, CES ifo 10 p. 1 Intertemporal Risk Aversion, Stationarity, and Discounting Christian Traeger Department of Agricultural & Resource Economics, UC Berkeley Introduce a more general preference representation

More information

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture I Choice under risk. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa Lecture I Choice under risk The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Preferences Let X be some set of alternatives (consumption set). Formally,

More information

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Carmen Camacho Takashi Kamihigashi Çağrı Sağlam February 1, 2016 Abstract A policy change that involves a redistribution of

More information

Foundations of Neoclassical Growth

Foundations of Neoclassical Growth Foundations of Neoclassical Growth Ömer Özak SMU Macroeconomics II Ömer Özak (SMU) Economic Growth Macroeconomics II 1 / 78 Preliminaries Introduction Foundations of Neoclassical Growth Solow model: constant

More information

(a) Write down the Hamilton-Jacobi-Bellman (HJB) Equation in the dynamic programming

(a) Write down the Hamilton-Jacobi-Bellman (HJB) Equation in the dynamic programming 1. Government Purchases and Endogenous Growth Consider the following endogenous growth model with government purchases (G) in continuous time. Government purchases enhance production, and the production

More information

Optimal Saving under Poisson Uncertainty: Corrigendum

Optimal Saving under Poisson Uncertainty: Corrigendum Journal of Economic Theory 87, 194-217 (1999) Article ID jeth.1999.2529 Optimal Saving under Poisson Uncertainty: Corrigendum Klaus Wälde Department of Economics, University of Dresden, 01062 Dresden,

More information

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1904 Afriat from MaxMin John D. Geanakoplos August 2013 An author index to the working papers in the

More information

Large Sharpening Intertemporal Prospect Theory

Large Sharpening Intertemporal Prospect Theory Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 1, 2007, no. 34, 1695-1701 Large Sharpening Intertemporal Prospect Theory Pushpa Rathie Department of Statistics, University of Brasilia 70910-900 Brasilia DF, Brazil

More information

Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming

Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Peter J. Hammond 1 of 81 Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming Peter J. Hammond 2018 September 28th University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Peter

More information

Economic Growth: Lectures 5-7, Neoclassical Growth

Economic Growth: Lectures 5-7, Neoclassical Growth 14.452 Economic Growth: Lectures 5-7, Neoclassical Growth Daron Acemoglu MIT November 7, 9 and 14, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Economic Growth Lectures 5-7 November 7, 9 and 14, 2017. 1 / 83 Introduction

More information

The Revenue Equivalence Theorem 1

The Revenue Equivalence Theorem 1 John Nachbar Washington University May 2, 2017 The Revenue Equivalence Theorem 1 1 Introduction. The Revenue Equivalence Theorem gives conditions under which some very different auctions generate the same

More information

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets

Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Generalized Hypothesis Testing and Maximizing the Success Probability in Financial Markets Tim Leung 1, Qingshuo Song 2, and Jie Yang 3 1 Columbia University, New York, USA; leung@ieor.columbia.edu 2 City

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Competitive Equilibrium when Preferences Change over Time

Competitive Equilibrium when Preferences Change over Time Competitive Equilibrium when Preferences Change over Time Erzo G.J. Luttmer Thomas Mariotti June 24, 2002 Abstract We show the existence of a competitive equilibrium in an economy with many consumers whose

More information