SUBSTANTIVALISM, RELATIONISM, AND STRUCTURAL SPACETIME REALISM 1

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "SUBSTANTIVALISM, RELATIONISM, AND STRUCTURAL SPACETIME REALISM 1"

Transcription

1 Forthcoming in Foundations of Physics, 2000, 30, pp SUBSTANTIVALISM, RELATIONISM, AND STRUCTURAL SPACETIME REALISM 1 Mauro Dorato Department of Philosophy University of Rome 3 Via Ostiense 234, Rome, Italy dorato@uniroma3.it 1. Manifold substantivalism or metric field substantivalism? A historian of 20 th century philosophy of science that were to consider the recent renaissance of studies on the ontological status of spacetime would certainly notice a significant shift of interest toward metaphysical issues previously scorned by neopositivists philosophers. 2 Some philosophers more inclined toward historical analysis have complained about the audacious tendency of some contemporary philosophers of space and time to portray Newton and Leibniz (see Alexander 1956) as defenders of views that, like substantivalism and relationism, do not always represent in an accurate way the positions really taken by these historical figures (see Stein 1967 and DiSalle 1994). However, worse than such moderate forms of interpretive violence perpetrated on 17 th century natural philosophers which in any case are not motivated by unfair attempts to add significance to one s pet philosophical problem by ennobling its historical pedigree is the fact that the current participants to the debate don t even seem to agree about how to formulate spacetime substantivalism 3 within the fundamental spacetime theory of contemporary physics, the general theory of relativity. For example, it is not clear whether one should identify spacetime with the bare manifold or with the metric field. As is often the case when there is no agreement even about the nature of the problem, there is a natural tendency to affirm that 1 I want to thank Robert Rynasiewicz and Robert DiSalle for having read a previous version of this paper and having helped to remove some of my misinterpretations of their views. I am the only responsible for the remaining mistakes. 2 Such foundational studies were revived in the late eighties by the so-called hole argument due to John Earman and John Norton (1987). See Earman (1989), Butterfield (1989), Maudlin (1990), Rynasiewicz (1994), Healey (1995), DiSalle (1995) for discussions of the philosophical and metaphysical issues. The tendency to misrepresent Leibniz and Newton as defenders of relationism and substantivalism respectively was decisively more present in the philosophy of space and time of the first part of the century, and especially in Reichenbach. 3 Substantivalism is usually presented as the doctrine that space and time (spacetime) exist over and above the objects and events of the physical world, while relationism is regarded as a denial of just this thesis: a relationist about spacetime regards physical events and objects as the primary constituents of the world, and space and time as relations instantiated by such entities. 1

2 the problem itself is not genuine or is purely verbal, a matter of arbitrary choice between two preferred ways of speaking (Rynasiewicz 1996). This confusing situation is especially evident in two of the most recent papers on the subject, Rynasiewicz s (1996) and Hoefer s (1998), the former claiming that the dispute between substantivalists and relationists is outmoded, as it was a genuine problem only at the time of Descartes, Leibniz and Newton (before the emergence of the so-called electromagnetic view of nature in the late 19 th century), the latter arguing that the debate for better or worse still goes on, as it plays an important role even in current attempts at building a quantum theory of gravity. The fact is that while Rynasiewicz presents substantivalism as a doctrine presupposing a clear difference between matter and space, or between content and container, Hoefer proceeds by simply ignoring such a critical point, and by claiming that spacetime substantivalism has to do with the ontological status of the metric field in the general theory of relativity, thereby advocating metric field substantivalism. To the extent that the metric field, as is well known and universally recognized, cannot be identified with empty spacetime or with the bare manifold which is, essentially, a set of points with a topological and a differential structure in order to answer to Rynasiewicz s challenge one faces the question of showing that the choice of metric field substantivalism over manifold substantivalism to represent spacetime is not arbitrary. An argument against the arbitrariness of such a choice had already been given by Earman and Norton, who claimed that the metric field, qua physical field, cannot be regarded unlike the manifold, in their opinion as the container of the other physical fields (1987, ). As a consequence, they defended the view that substantivalists should embrace manifold substantivalism, which they then claim to have rejected via the hole argument. 4 Against this view, however, Maudlin correctly points out that a manifold, devoid of a metric (and affine) structure, can be attributed none of the paradigmatic spatio-temporal properties (distance, difference between spatial and temporal intervals, light cone structure, etc.) (1988, 87), and cannot be considered to be representing, let alone be identical with, physical spacetime. Consequently, I take it that arguing pro or against substantivalism or on the meaningfulness of the related debate really presupposes that we try to establish first which of these two versions of substantivalism is more plausible within the general theory of relativity, 5 by keeping our mind open to the possibility defended by Rynasiewicz that in that theory neither version is plausible. Rather than a battle about words, I claim that this 4 Rynasiewicz (1994) argues that the hole argument does not establish this conclusion, but is just an example of the problem of the indeterminacy of reference. 5 Maudlin (1988) and Hoefer (1996) have begun to study this problem. 2

3 question is just another piece of evidence that the general theory of relativity is like quantum mechanics, though for different reasons in need of an interpretation. 6 Such an interpretive task should not viewed as the addition or juxtaposition of a philosophical/metaphysical view to the physical theory, but as a necessary restructuring of our understanding of the latter in terms of new concepts, always remaining in the safe tradition of plain, old natural philosophy. Once we agree on this diagnosis, it will be easier to see why the debate can be solved by advancing a tertium quid, or a third option between classical substantivalism and relationism. This option, which I call structural spacetime realism, sides with the latter doctrine in defending the relational nature of spacetime, but argues with the former that spacetime exists, at least in part, independently of particular physical objects and events, the degree of independence being given by the extent to which geometrical laws exist over and above physical events exemplifying them. By showing that structural spacetime realism is the natural outcome of a semantic, model-theoretic approach to the nature of scientific theories an approach to which Marisa Dalla Chiara has given significant contributions during her scientific carrier 7 in the last part of the paper I will argue that the notion of partial isomorphic representation is the most plausible candidate to act as a natural bridge between physical models and reality. 2. The metric field as a guide to a third way between substantivalism and relationism It must be recognized that Rynasiewicz is correct in pointing out that, within general relativity, any philosophical view presupposing a clear separation of space and matter available in various brands of the 17 th century corpuscular philosophies would be grossly misleading. But then it could be replied that a charitable reading of the current debate between substantivalists and relationists should not be construed as presupposing a distinction between empty space-time and a matter-filled universe à la Descartes, precisely because such a distinction in the general theory of relativity is not available. Are we thereby changing the subject to which early modern natural philosophers dedicated so much efforts? Perhaps, but what matters is whether the reformulated problem is genuine, fruitful, and similar enough to the original one to be worth calling it by the same name. 6 For quite different reasons, having to do with the quantum theory of gravity, this thesis has been advocated by Belot (1996). 7 See, for instance, her seminal paper with Toraldo (1973). 3

4 To the extent that spacetime substantivalism implies, as Rynasiewicz correctly has it, the issue of the independent existence of space and time, the fact that the main spatiotemporal properties in the general theory of relativity (except perhaps the topological relation of betweeness ) are provided by the metric field cannot be disregarded as ininfluential to the nature of the debate. However, Rynasiewicz mentions the status of the metric field only in a footnote (1996, 301, fn 45), where he contrasts Earman and Norton s filing the metric tensor in the folder labeled physical contents of spacetime (1987, 519) with Friedman s remark that the criterion of being unoccupied for spacetime points can only be yielded by the vanishing of the stress-energy tensor, and not by any features of the metric tensor (1983, 221-2). Here, I take Rynasiewicz to be suggesting that the metric tensor can count neither as matter nor as space, if these terms are now given the meaning they had in the 17 th century. Once we agree with this remark, it is still not clear to me why it implies, as Rynasiewicz has it, that the dispute about the ontological status of spacetime after 1916 has become merely verbal. Suppose that, following Einstein, we agree, as I claim we should, that there can be no space nor any part of space without gravitational potentials [that is, without the metric/gravitational field]; for these confer upon space its metrical qualities, without which it cannot be imagined at all (Einstein 1923, 21, my addition in square brackets). Then we should simply reject those views advocating that substantivalism is committed to the independent existence of the bare manifold without the metric field, or to the existence of unoccupied spacetime points endowed with primitive identity (Field 1980, Mundy 1983, Friedman 1983). In view of well-known difficulties raised by the identification of spacetime points independently of a prior assignment of a metric to the manifold (Stachel 1993), it has been plausibly argued that manifold substantivalism cannot be the correct option, so that the substantivalism/relationism dispute must involve the ontological status of the metric field (Hoefer 1996). To this, Rynasiewicz could perhaps retort that his diagnosis of the whole debate applies to Hoefer s specific proposal of metric field substantivalism as well: the question whether the metric tensor should be understood as being more like empty space or rather more like any other matter fields is either to be regarded as a matter of an arbitrary choice of a preferred manner of speaking, or has a negative answer in both alternatives. Furthermore, he could add that such an ambiguity might even explain why, in the literature, we find two possible actors for the role of substantival spacetime namely, the manifold and the metric field. The choice between them might depend on the equally acceptable and therefore arbitrary options of regarding the metric field (1) as being more matter-like which then pushes one toward consider the manifold as being the object of the ontological debate or (2) as being more spacetime-like, in which case the metric field itself becomes the object of the 4

5 controversy. Clearly, if we cannot decide in a non-arbitrary way whether the metric field should be equated with a matter field like any other or not, then we cannot conclude that it is the best candidate to become the subject of the dispute between substantivalism and relationism, and the project of clarifying the ontological status of spacetime in the general theory of relativity should be abandoned. Despite these skeptical remarks, I take it that Earman and Norton s hole argument, besides the various responses that have been given to it, can be interpreted as showing that the bare manifold with its points is not a good candidate for being the main character in the debate, and that the metric field is the only candidate for that role. The reason for this claim is two-fold, involving (a) the issue of the individuation of spacetime points on the one hand, and (b) a methodologically pregnant remark about the relation between models and reality on the other. Given that such arguments have mainly been given elsewhere, here I will report them in a very brief fashion as a recapitulation, with the main intent to lay my cards on the table and prepare the field for my own analysis of the issue. As to (a), Stachel (1993), Healey (1995) and Pauri (1996) have made abundantly clear that, against Earman and Norton s principle of Leibniz equivalence, the assumption that two diffeomorphically related models 8 should represent the same physical state of affairs must be regarded as being eminently plausible even for a substantivalist, no matter how different such models are from a purely mathematical viewpoint. As Pauri put it: physically, a gravitational field does not correspond to a single metric tensor, but to an equivalence class of metric tensors, related one to the other by active diffeomorphisms (Pauri 1996, 104, my translation). The essential remark in this context is that spacetime points can only be identified by the relational structure provided by the gravitational field. Given that the points of a manifold have no intrinsic identity, on the basis of the well-known principle due to Quine, neither can they be regarded as entities. 9 The additional, less noted difficulty for manifold substantivalism is that if the points of a manifold, its elementary parts, are not substances, and any substance has usually other substances as its parts, it becomes difficult to defend the view that the fusion of such non-substantial parts (the manifold) can be a substance. 10 Finally, another reason pointing in the same direction is given by the already mentioned fact that the topological structure of the manifold, an essential component of its definition, depends on the metric field in the sense that not only must 8 A diffeomorphism of a manifold onto another is a bijective, infinitely differentiable map preserving topological and differential structure. 9 The slogan is no entity without identity. 10 This remark, which here I cannot expand, could cause trouble to Healey s proposal of a substantial spacetime composed of parts (points) that are less than substances. 5

6 the former be chosen in such a way as to be compatible with the latter, but it also cannot be determined prior to the solutions to Einstein s field equations (see Pauri 1996, 105). It is in this sense that we must interpret Einstein s above quoted remark that there cannot be spacetime without the gravitational potentials. With respect to the latter reason (b), and by recalling arguments due to Maudlin (1988), Stachel (1993), Auyang (1995), and Hoefer (1996), here I will just say that the bare manifold with its points and its other purely mathematical properties (differentiability, orientability, etc.) simply cannot be identified with physical spacetime, since this would be an instance of a fallacious identification of the properties of a mathematical model with the physical objects which it purports to represent. In a word, we would exchange the map for the territory. As Healey put it: Minimal substantivalist holds that spacetime exists, but not that it is identical to any model of a local spacetime theory. Given the highly abstract character of such models, this identification would make the minimal substantivalist into a Platonist! (1995, 290). This quotation presents the additional advantage of calling attention to a point that will become crucial in the following: unless we say more about how mathematical models in general, and the metric field in particular, represent the physical properties they are supposed to denote, we will be at a loss in trying to give a clear formulation to the problem of the existence of spacetime. If these remarks are sufficient to establish that debates about the ontology of spacetime should concern the reality of the metric field and not of the manifold, it is certainly much more difficult to respond to Rynasiewicz s challenge if it is also taken to involve the question whether such a field resembles more space or should be treated like any other matter field. Even though such a question does not seem just a matter of an arbitrary linguistic choice after all, it lies at the core of currents attempts at building a quantum theory of gravity 11 I think it fair to side with Rynasiewicz in claiming that the metric field can neither be equated with space-time nor with any other matter field, since it has features that are typical of both of these classical notions. Here we are facing another much less studied but not less important case of inapplicability of dual classical notions, similar to the more familiar difficulties raised, say, by the classical concepts of waves and particles with respect to quantum entities. In an analogous way, the metric field, by carrying energy and momentum, and by being capable of both acting and being acted upon, should be regarded, on the one hand, as material. On the other, by providing a distinction between the spatial and the temporal directions of all the other material fields, it performs the typical individuating functions of classical space and time regarded as principia individuationis, and is therefore not a matter field like any other. 6

7 The main claim that I want to advance in this paper is that such a dialectical synthesis between space and matter enacted by the metric field calls for a new philosophical view on the nature of spacetime. Having established that the interpretative task raised by the substantivalism/relationism debate essentially involves the metric field, the undeniable ambiguity between matter and space that such a field embodies suggests dropping both substantivalism insofar as it requires empty spacetime and relationism insofar as it requires an antirealist stance about spacetime and embracing a new position as an often invoked tertium quid to the debate, which I will refer to as structural spacetime realism. As I see it, such a position allows us to capture the best assumptions up to now separately associated with substantivalism and relationism, that is, those assumptions that, at least within the general theory of relativity, substantivalists and relativists must share. Structural spacetime realism is a synthesis between these two traditional positions in exactly the same sense in which the metric field is both matter and spacetime, 12 since it defends at the same time the relational character of space and time (by defending a structural-role identity for spacetime points), while claiming that the geometrical structure used to represent them is really, mind-independently exemplified by the physical world. 13 As a final comment on Rynasiewicz s thought-provoking paper, I should add that the historical importance of the substantivalism/relationism debate in 20 th century physics should in any case not be downplayed. Considered it in an historical light, the question of substantival versus relational spacetime can in fact be also described as a conflict between two heuristically conflicting research programs of 20 th century physics, appropriately labelled by Tian Yu Cao strong and weak geometric program respectively (Cao 1997, ). Even though this distinction seems to presuppose an implausible separation between the metric and the gravitational field, the essential difference between the two programs can still be clearly formulated. While the strong geometrical program regards the geometrical structure of spacetime as physically real as the other fields, and seeks to reduce the latter (gravitational, electromagnetic etc.) to the world geometry in the sense of Weyl (1918a,b) Eddington (1921) and Wheeler s geometrodynamics (1962), the weak program which at the moment seems much more popular treats spacetime as a structural quality of other fields or, more generally, 11 See for instance Rovelli (1997), who considers the metric field as a matter field like any other, and stresses the relational character of any measurement in general relativity. 12 A different sort of tertium quid has been advocated by Earman with the Leibniz algebras program (1989, 190-3). See Rynasiewicz for a critical evaluation of this program (1992). 13 In this paper, I am not discussing the problem whether structural realism is a tenable interpretation of the ontological status of other fields as well, like the electromagnetic field, or more in general, of the so-called theoretical entities (see Psillos 1995). What I claim is that it is particularly appropriate for interpreting the metric field. 7

8 of other entities, and not as existing independently or in a fundamental way. 14 As Cao puts it: according to this view [the weak program], the geometrical structure manifests itself only in the behavior of rods and clocks, and is determined wholly by the interaction between the gravitational field on the one hand, and rods and clocks a on the other. Rods and clocks, in addition to their function as probes of the metric of spacetime, can also influence the gravitational field. But the field itself, according to Einstein, is sufficient to constitute the metric of spacetime (Cao 1997, 101, my addition in square parentheses). Leaving aside for the time being the fact that in the formulation of the weak geometrical program, the notion of field may in its turn be taken to presuppose spacetime, 15 the essentially heuristic nature of the two programs calls forth two methodological caveats. The first is that any extensive philosophical discussion of the strong and the weak geometrical program (or alternatively, of substantivalism and relationism) should be supplemented by an historical analysis or a case study, something that here cannot be provided. The second is that even though the following comments are rigorously limited to classical (non-quantum) general relativity, the substantivalist-relationist debate and structural spacetime realism as its possible solution should always be judged in terms of their heuristic role in supporting current (and future) efforts at unifying quantum mechanics and general relativity. 3 Structural spacetime realism as a synthesis of relationism and substantivalism The idea of applying to the philosophy of space and time the principles of structural realism as elaborated by Worral (1989), Zahar (1994), Cao (1997), Chakravartty (1998) Ladyman (1998) and French (1999), has never been explored, despite a seminal but quite condensed anticipation contained in a widely-read paper written more than thirty years ago (Stein 1967). In trying to reconstruct Newton s doctrine of absolute space and time vis à vis Leibniz s relationism, Stein in fact writes: If the distinction between inertial frames and those that are not inertial is a distinction that has a real application to the world; that is, if the structure I described [...] is in some sense really exhibited by the world of events; and if this structure can legitimately be regarded as an explication of Newton s absolute space and time ; then the question whether, in addition to characterizing the world in just the indicated sense, this structure of space-time also really exists, surely seems supereroga- 14 The expression structural quality of the field is Einstein s. 15 This problem will be discussed below. 8

9 tory (1967, 193, my italics). I suggest that, mutatis mutandis, we should apply the same lesson to the issue of spacetime substantivalism in the general theory of relativity. Note first of all that Stein does not claim that spacetime exists over and above the physical world of events, as in typical definitions of substantivalism: he rather regards the question whether the structure of space-time really exists as supererogatory. 16 By using a later paper of his, I read him as claiming that the traditional dispute between substantivalism and relationism is completely analogous to that between realism and antirealism as he views it: neither position is tenable (Stein 1989). Antirealism in spacetime theories would amount to a position denying that the world of events really exhibits a certain geometrical structure, something that he instead explicitly grants, while realism would be equivalent to the supererogatory claim that the spatiotemporal structure really exist, where really exists plausibly refers to the independent existence ( over and above physical events ) required by standard substantivalism. Isn t Stein s view as it is expressed in the quotation relationism in disguise? After all, why couldn t a relationist be a realist about the spatiotemporal relations? Since I regard these objections as plausible, I have to disagree with Stein by claiming that there are at least three different senses in which one can meaningfully ask whether spatiotemporal structure really exists. In a first sense, the really is synonymous with mindindependently : someone like Kant, for instance, would deny the mind-independence of the spatio-temporal relations. 17 In a second sense, the really exists may refer to a kind of platonic realism about the mathematical structure used to describe the physical world. In a third sense, the question of the independent existence of spatiotemporal structure calls into play the status of natural laws and their existence as being partially nonsupervenient upon physical state of affairs and events. Structural spacetime realism as I view it accepts the first and last senses of realism and rejects the second, by developing what, in effect, could be called a quasi-platonic view of scientific theories, where the quasi comes from the fact that the Forms, i.e., the geometrical structure, do not exist separately from the world of phenomena: this claim would indeed be supererogatory. Such a world, however, is understandable only insofar as it truly and mind-independently participates ( exemplifies ) the Forms. 18 On the one hand, to the extent that the Forms (the structure) are denied separate existence, structural spacetime realism does indeed 16 As Kant uses this term, an act is supererogatory when it is neither against one s duty, nor called by it, despite the fact that it may appear as particularly saintly. 17 Of course, this question would take us to a different aspect of the problem, but it is important to remind ourselves of this side of the debate. 18 The issue of how such an exemplification is achieved will be analyzed in the last section of the paper. 9

10 sound like relationism, in the trivial sense that geometrical structure does not exists as a non-instantiated universal. On the other hand, to the extent that relationists are usually instrumentalist about spacetime that is, they deny its existence tout court it is extremely important to note that structural spacetime realist is nonrelationist either, simply because it need not be antirealist about spacetime. In other words, structural spacetime realism can dissolve the substantivalism/relationism debate on the basis of the plausibility of the following meaning stipulation: (MS) To say that spacetime exists just means that the physical world exemplifies, or instantiate, a web of spatiotemporal relations that are described mathematically. According to (MS), spacetime is granted existence not as a substance, but rather as a bundle of universals or a web of relations contingently exemplified by physical systems. Since a mathematical structure necessarily involves relations, 19 structural spacetime realism can embody the best intuitions associated to relationism, namely the fact that in relativity all the most important spatio-temporal determinations are essentially relational in character ( later than, simultaneous with, to the future of, being spacelike separated with, etc., being a certain invariant spatio-temporal distance from etc.). Furthermore, to the extent that real relations, as it is plausible, presuppose the existence of relata, then spatiotemporal relation presuppose physical systems and events, as classical relationism has it. However, this supervenience of relations on relata is not metaphysically necessary for structural spacetime realism. An ontology in which individuals simply are bundles of (polyadic) universals (Armstrong 1989), with no enduring haecceity, may well make room for non-supervenient relations. In such a thoroughly relationalist ontology, the identity of individual physical entities (say, pointlike events) would be constituted, in the limit of inquiry, by a growing number of relations in which they are embedded. Cao has recently defended this structuralist ontology with respect to 20 th century field theories in general: while structural relations are real in the sense that they are testable, the concept of unobservable entities that are involved in the structural relations always has some conventional element, and the reality of the entities is constituted by, or derived from, more and more relations in which they are involved. (Cao 1997, 5). Be that is it may, given its conceptual proximity with relationism, one could saddle structural spacetime realism with the difficulties usually associated with the former position. We have seen that a spacetime realist should be a realist about the metric field; in the general theory of relativity, however, the metric is a variable, 10

11 dynamical entity, depending in part on the distribution of matter, as dictated by the equations of the theory. As far as I can tell, the strongest argument in favor of substantivalism is the fact that a general relativistic spacetime is not a passive arena in which events and processes unfold, but is essentially dynamical in that it acts and is acted upon by other physical fields. In view of the unity of the gravitational and the chronogeometrical field, such an argument makes direct reference to the spatiotemporal, geometric structure as a cause as when physicists say that the curvature of spacetime deflects the orbits of massive bodies and seems to require the independent existence of spacetime as a cause, and therefore substantivalism. However, a realist about the spatiotemporal structure has no difficulty in responding to such arguments. By using the spatiotemporal structure as an explanatory tool, and declaring it to be a mind-independent property of certain physical systems, structural realists about spacetime may rely on the fact that properties (spatiotemporal ones included) simply are, in any respectable metaphysical theories, the causal powers of the entities having them. It is in this sense that structural spacetime realism is a synthesis of both relationism and substantivalism. What causes the deflection of the orbit of the massive body is the gravitational field, a thoroughly physical field, via its geometrical, causally active relational properties: in this way, however, one avoids a superfluous reification of spacetime regarded as a substance possessing causal powers. Well, a substantivalist could reply, doesn t the gravitational field presuppose space by being, exactly as any other field, a physical state of space? This objection, if it does not beg the issue, is however ineffective and misleading, because it erroneously presupposes the possibility of separating the spatiotemporal features of the gravitational field from the field itself, as if we could initially have an empty space with topological and metric properties but devoid of physical qualities, subsequently to be filled with some physical content. We have already seen that the general theory of relativity forbids any such separation between empty space and material fields. In this sense, even though structural realists can adopt causal talks typical of substantivalists, they need not do so, and can thereby refuse to accept causal explanations invoking spacetime as a theoretical entity. If need arises, they can easily avoid the sort of criticism recently raised by DiSalle against arguments regarding spacetime as a possible cause of spatiotemporal relations or observable motions: the nature of spacetime is a question, not of whether a theoretical entity [spacetime] provides a causal explanation for appearances, but of whether the physical processes of measurement conform to geometrical laws [...] Spatial measurement has been 19 Plus certain mappings connecting elements of the models with individuals in reality to which we will soon 11

12 defined by coordination with a basic physical process (motion of rigid bodies). To claim that space is Euclidean only means that measurement agree with the Euclidean metric; Euclidean geometry, if true, can t causally explain those measurements, because it only expresses the constraints to which those measurements will conform (1995, 323-4). On the other hand, being able to attribute any causal efficacy to spacetime structure rather than to spacetime itself, a structural realist could also flexibly reply to critics that might want to charge her position with an underestimation of the importance of causal explanations in spacetime theories. 20 Coming now to the third, most important sense of really exists broached above, a structural spacetime realist must admit that geometrical laws exist independently of our minds, to the extent that such laws partially constitute the structure (or the relations) that phenomena exemplify. 21 The laws I am referring to are relational constraints making it the case that, say, free particles travel on geodesics of the spacetime, and in which geometry and physics are inextricably coordinated with our experience. A new, interesting question to ask in a context equating the structure of a physical theories with its laws involves the degree of independence structures have from entities they relate. Given the assumption of the beginning of the paragraph, this question is basically equivalent to asking how independent geometrical laws are from the entities (bodies or events) they structure. 22 An answer to this question depends in its turn on the plausibility of a Humean view about the supervenience of natural laws on the intrinsic properties of local events or physical bodies. A Humean regularist will tend to regard laws or structures as being strictly supervenient on the latter entities, and therefore as being more dependent on the properties of bodies, while the non-humean will be willing to grant a higher degree of independence to such a nomological structure. This question, by involving the nature of natural laws, cannot be developed here. Nevertheless, I will not refrain from suggesting the following thesis as a possible line of future research: to ask the typical substantivalist question about the independent existence of spacetime is really to ask a question about the supervenience of geometrical laws on the intrinsic properties of physical events. 4. The semantic conception of scientific theories and structural realism come back. 20 As DiSalle has kindly explained to me in private correspondence, he claims that the same kind of theoretical supposition is involved both in saying that spacetime has a certain structure, and in saying that there are certain spatio-temporal relations, a position not altogether different from the one defended here. 21 I say partially because, of course, not all relations between entities are lawlike. 22 This point is implicitly suggested by DiSalle, where he suggests that Newton s essential point is that there is a geometrical system of constraints of the motion of bodies that is independent of those bodies (1994, 274). 12

13 Interestingly, the various forms of spacetime realism that we have been discussing so far can be regarded as a by product of different views of the nature of scientific theories. If spacetime is understood as a theoretical entity in the tradition of a linguistic approach to scientific theories, attempts at justifying its introduction as an unobservable entity typically usually call into play causal explanations. If, on the contrary, the semantic, modeltheoretic aspect of scientific theories is emphasized in the sense of Dalla Chiara and Toraldo (1974), van Fraassen (1980), Giere (1988) and Suppe (1989), strategies advocating some form of partial isomorphism between spacetime models and the physical world are much more plausible, and structural spacetime realism emerges as a natural outcome. Since defenders of manifold substantivalism have often fallen prey of a confusion between aspects of the manifold as an abstract mathematical model and features of physically concrete spacetime, some reflections on how mathematical theories represent the physical world seem particularly appropriate, given that they will also help us to give some more detail on the notion of a structure associated to a physical theory. In the recent years a new approach to scientific theories has called attention to a non-linguistic dimension of science. The neopositivists had regarded theories mainly as sets of sentences, to be analyzed by purely syntactic means within a formalized language. Reacting to such an obsession with language, philosophers like Marisa Dalla Chiara and Giuliano Toraldo (1973) in Italy, or Patrick Suppes (1967), Bas Van Fraassen (1980), Ronald Giere (1988) and Frederic Suppe (1989) in the United States, have begun to regard scientific theories mainly as abstract, non-linguistic structures or, simply, models. In the technical sense of logic, a model M = <D, f > is whatever satisfies a set of axioms couched in a language L, namely an abstract domain of discourse D (a set of individuals), together with a function f assigning n-tuples of individuals in D to predicates (n = 1) and relations (n> 1) of L. Within the semantic conception of theories, the general theory of relativity is standardly constituted by the structure M = < M, g, T >, where M is a four dimensional, Riemannian manifold, g is the metric tensor and T is the stress energy tensor, or the matter field. If we try to formulate structural spacetime realism in this semantic framework, we basically have two different options: (O 1 ) the set of theoretical relations holding among spacetime points in M + g is totally or partially isomorphic to the set of spatio-temporal and physical relations exemplified by real events; (O 2 ) the set of mathematical relations among spacetime points in M postulated by g resembles, or is in some sense similar to, the set of temporal and physical relations exemplified by real events. A third option (O 3 ), which, however, does not typically belong to the semantic, but rather to the linguistic conceptions of theories, consists in claiming that the abstract, mathematical objects M + g in the structure M 13

14 genuinely refers to physical spacetime. The way (O 3 ) is put, and in particular the use of the verb to refer, makes it evident that the reality of spacetime in this case is regarded as a particular instance of the more general problem of establishing the reality of the so-called theoretical, unobservable entities. 23 Within the received view of scientific theories (Suppe 1977), such entities are those that are putatively referred to by terms of the language of the theory T that belong to its so-called theoretical vocabulary. It should also be obvious why, within such a linguistic framework in which the realist tries to establish some sort of referential relation (typically a causal one) between the word Riemannian manifold and its putative denotatum the model-theoretical approach, with its emphasis on relational structure rather than on relata, loses its relevance. Note that I am not claiming that within the semantic approach the third option cannot be formulated, or that a causal account of theoretical entities cannot be advocated by semantic theorists believing in entity realism. 24 Nor do I mean to endorse a distinction between observable and theoretical entities in van Fraassen sense, as I mention it only to present an antirealist argument essentially related to the received, linguistic view of science. By discussing these three options in turn, my two-fold aim is rather to argue that the spatiotemporal structure postulated by our best models (spacetime theories) is really exemplified by the physical world and to further clarify structural spacetime realism by defending it from some foreseeable objections. 4.1 Structural spacetime realism and isomorphic representations According to the first option (O 1 ), any claim about the reality of spacetime is equivalent to the claim that a model of general relativity correctly represents the physical universe via isomorphic relations between models and world. The idea that the relationship between a model and reality is one of isomorphic representation is essentially due to van Fraassen (1980, 43-46): given a bijection F from the model M (or a part thereof) to a set R of real objects or events ( reality ), we can establish an isomorphism between M and R if and only if the relations between elements of the model and those between entities of the real world are preserved by F. If we claim that F holds only when it acts on the empirical substructure of the model, its domain is restricted to the part of the model that is linked via F to observable entities. By such a restriction, we can draw the distinction, dear to van Fraassen s heart, between accepting the theory as empirically adequate and believing it to be true (1980, 46). The former epistemic attitude is reserved to the theoretical substructure of the theory M, since F 23 Here unobservable means unobservable with our unaided senses. 14

15 guarantees only the existence of directly observable entities. Van Fraassen does not exclude that the isomorphism F can be extended to the theoretical substructure of M, but in this case the set of theoretical relations attributed to the theoretical entities may or may not exist. Consequently, in van Fraassen s view, the problem of establishing whether the structure of spacetime is real would amount to decide whether the spatiotemporal substructure of the model corresponding to general relativity belongs to the empirical or the theoretical substructure. In this context, by insisting on a distinction between observable motions and spacetime regarded as a theoretical entity, one could argue, against structural spacetime realism, that if one has to be delivered by metaphysics, as Van Fraassen recommends, one must remain agnostic as to whether the spatio-temporal structure postulated by the Riemannian manifold is really exemplified by physical spacetime. There are two possible strategies to block this form of antirealism about the spatiotemporal structure. The first relies on the inapplicability of the distinction between observable and unobservable to spacetime; the second, more efficient to our purpose, consists in using the very weapons of the constructive empiricist to affirm that an essential component of the spacetime structure is real simply because it is directly observable. Within the first strategy, but for somewhat different purposes, DiSalle has argued that observations in physical geometry are essentially theory-laden, so that any distinction between observable and non-observable is, at least with respect to spacetime structure, groundless (1995, 318). According to him, Reichenbachian coordinative definitions do not correspond to simple physical operations, but rather require a whole system of natural laws, and are therefore theoretical throughout. This point, however, does not detract from the fact that, at least within the special theory of relativity and therefore within the local tangent space of any point of a general relativistic spacetime we do observe part of the spatio-temporal structure as directly as it gets. This gives us the second strategy: don t we directly perceive that an event is before another event, or that two spatially contiguous events are simultaneous? Recall that the relation of temporal succession ( before or after ) is so important in Minkowski spacetime that it, by itself, suffices to build up its whole geometrical and causal structure (Robb 1914). On the other hand, the spatiotemporal coincidence of two events, ascertainable by a single act of perception, must be regarded as sufficient to attribute them absolute simultaneity, since if we cannot judge that, say, a light ray intersecting the surface of a mirror is simultaneous with a certain position of the hands of a spatially contiguous clock, no empirical foundation of any physical theory would ever be 24 Giere is an example of a semantic theorist defending entity realism (1988, ch. 5). 15

16 possible. In this sense, and even independently from arguments à la DiSalle, within the constructive empiricist position advocated by Van Fraassen, spacetime structure must be regarded, at least in part, as belonging to the empirical substructure of the theory, and therefore as being as real as any observable relation between phenomena. In the same vein we should interpret Einstein s often quoted point-coincidence argument, on the strength of which, considering spatiotemporal coordinates as devoid of physical value, the only epistemically ascertainable relations are meeting of the material points of our measuring instruments with other material points (1916, 117). And though we certainly cannot reconstruct the global structure of a general relativistic spacetime just by patching together such strictly local intersections of worldlines, for our purpose it suffices to point out that if we don t admit that at least these intersections are directly observable, no spacetime theory can ever be built. Consequently, antirealist arguments claiming that spacetime structure is in any case unobservable are untenable. 4.2 Structural spacetime realism and resemblance theories of representation The second option (O 2 ) has been defended by Giere, who claims that resemblance to a certain degree and in certain respects is the correct relation between models and reality (1988, 81). Such a requirement is clearly weaker than that of isomorphism but despite its vagueness, has some degree of confirmation from the cognitive sciences, in particular from empirical studies concerning mental images and schemes, whose representational features are mostly pictorial. According to Giere, the relationship between model and reality cannot be linguistic, because neither models nor reality are linguistic entities, but it must be expressed by a linguistically formulated theoretical hypothesis, which states the existence of some degrees of similarity (under certain respects) between model and world. According to Giere, the relation linking models and reality cannot be given by isomorphisms, because there are obviously many relationships between entities in the models that are not instantiated by corresponding entities in reality and viceversa: natural laws for Giere are strictly true only in the model. Resemblance, on the contrary, has the advantage of expressing a typical feature of the scientific enterprise, essentially involving errors and approximations (Mayo 1996). Besides the obvious vagueness of the relation of resemblance under certain respects, another problem of this proposal is that it seems to hold, strictly speaking, only between images and aspects of objects; in this sense, it necessarily presupposes visual perceptions or intuitions. In fact, it is implausible to claim that other 16

17 sensory modalities are capable of bearing the relation of resemblance with their intentional objects. Consequently, in order to claim the existence of a relationship of resemblance between models and reality, one must give center stage to visual features of models. So Giere s proposal can be challenged with the following dilemma: either the relation of resemblance has some definite meaning, and then it clearly implies preservations of spatial relations between images and represented objects (e.g. angles, distances, shapes, contiguity of parts, etc.), or it is so vague that it does not mean anything at all and cannot be used to specify the relation between models and reality. With respect to the issue of the visualizability of models, the weakness of O 2 as applied to spacetime physics is evident. For features as abstract as those involved in the mathematical models of general relativistic spacetimes, it is extremely restrictive to ask that such models have visualizable features. Just to give an example: is the infinite differentiability of charts defining a manifold interpretable as resembling the continuity of perceived space or that of physical space? The trouble is that the vagueness of similar under certain respect and in certain degrees leaves too much freedom for establishing a precise correspondence between a model and parts of the world. What may work for a simple, one-dimensional spring with respect to real life springs will not work for theories as abstract as quantum field theory or general relativity. One need not subscribe to reconstructions of the development of contemporary physics stressing the progressive loss of visualizability of physical models (Capek 1961) to admit that the latter requirement cannot be imposed a priori to a theory for it to be representing the world. Finally, as a last objection against (O 2 ), we should remark that despite the geometrization and the spatialization of time on the one hand, and the connection between our experience and measurement of time with the motion of objects in space on the other, time as it is represented in spacetime models portrays events as given in block, the spatiotemporal carrier of our body being a tube in four-dimensional spacetime. While this representation of time is certainly adequate for purposes of the physical description of the world, it would be quite outlandish to argue that it resembles in some respect to the time of our bodies regarded as physical systems. The least that we can say is that it certainly does not resemble the time of our experience, since, within the latter, we are always aware of a single, ontologically privileged moment that we call present, despite the fact that our experience may occur in a tenselessly conceived time. And even if one were to claim that the relation of being greater than on the real line (which we use to represent time and its instants) is similar under certain respects to the relation of temporal succession between instants, this certainly would not help, since it would amount to 17

Lecture 5: Leibniz equivalence and Putnam s paradox

Lecture 5: Leibniz equivalence and Putnam s paradox Lecture 5: Leibniz equivalence and Putnam s paradox 5.1 Recap: Responses to the hole argument Let M 1 = M, g, T and M 2 = M, d g, d T be two models of GR where d is a non-trivial diffeomorphism, possibly

More information

What s Observable in Special and General Relativity?

What s Observable in Special and General Relativity? What s Observable in Special and General Relativity? Oliver Pooley oliver.pooley@philosophy.oxford.ac.uk Oriel College, Oxford ESF Conference 24 March 2004; What s Observable in Special and General Relativity?

More information

Spacetime Realism and Quantum Gravity

Spacetime Realism and Quantum Gravity Spacetime Realism and Quantum Gravity Oliver Pooley Oriel College, University of Oxford oliver.pooley@philosophy.ox.ac.uk 6 July, 2000 Abstract Sophisticated substantivalism is defended as a response to

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism 17.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 69-82. We will now try to assess the impact of Relativity Theory on the debate

More information

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space 12.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 19-25. Now that we have seen Newton s and Leibniz

More information

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 58 (2007), 777 786 Sklar s Maneuver Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Sklar ([1974]) claimed that relationalism about ontology the doctrine that space and time do not exist is compatible with

More information

Topics in Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North

Topics in Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North Topics in Philosophy of Physics: Philosophy of Space and Time Philosophy 426 T 1:10-4:10pm, 210 Miller Hall J. North (j.north@rutgers.edu) We will focus on the following question. Do space and time exist

More information

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv + 408 pages by Bradley Monton June 24, 2009 It probably goes without saying that

More information

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011

Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 Review of Gordon Belot, Geometric Possibility Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011 (The Philosophical Review 122 (2013): 522 525) Jill North This is a neat little book (138 pages without appendices, under 200 with).

More information

Holism and structural realism

Holism and structural realism Holism and structural realism Michael Esfeld & Vincent Lam University of Lausanne, Department of Philosophy CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland Michael-Andreas.Esfeld@unil.ch, Vincent.Lam@unil.ch (published

More information

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate Structuralism with an empiricist face? Bas Van Fraassen s Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective is a rich, masterful study of a wide range of issues arising from the manifold ways in which

More information

Buckets of Water and Waves of Space

Buckets of Water and Waves of Space by Tim Maudlin 1. Introduction Maudlin reviews the substantivalism/relationism controversy. This material should seem quite familiar. 2. The Bucket Newton s bucket and the two globes arguments are rehearsed,

More information

Lecture 3: General Covariance and the Hole Argument

Lecture 3: General Covariance and the Hole Argument Lecture 3: General Covariance and the Hole Argument 3.1 Substantivalism and relationalism Substantivalism: space (or spacetime) is a substance (Reductive) Relationalism: the denial of substantivalism (not

More information

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007 Russell s logicism Jeff Speaks September 26, 2007 1 Russell s definition of number............................ 2 2 The idea of reducing one theory to another.................... 4 2.1 Axioms and theories.............................

More information

Once Upon a Spacetime. Bradford Skow

Once Upon a Spacetime. Bradford Skow Once Upon a Spacetime by Bradford Skow A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy New York University September,

More information

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL THOMAS HOFWEBER PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL 1. PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AND HILBERT S PROGRAM Hilbert s program in the philosophy of mathematics comes in two parts. One part is a

More information

Category-Theoretic Radical Ontic Structural Realism

Category-Theoretic Radical Ontic Structural Realism Category-Theoretic Radical Ontic Structural Realism Jonathan Bain Department of Technology, Culture and Society Tandon School of Engineering, New York University Brooklyn, New York 1. No Structures Without

More information

16. Einstein and General Relativistic Spacetimes

16. Einstein and General Relativistic Spacetimes 16. Einstein and General Relativistic Spacetimes Problem: Special relativity does not account for the gravitational force. To include gravity... Geometricize it! Make it a feature of spacetime geometry.

More information

CATEGORICAL PRIORITY AND CATEGORICAL COLLAPSE

CATEGORICAL PRIORITY AND CATEGORICAL COLLAPSE II L. A. PAUL CATEGORICAL PRIORITY AND CATEGORICAL COLLAPSE I explore some of the ways that assumptions about the nature of substance shape metaphysical debates about the structure of Reality. Assumptions

More information

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Universalism Entails Extensionalism Universalism Entails Extensionalism Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York [Final version published in Analysis, 69 (2009), 599 604] 1. Universalism (also known as Conjunctivism,

More information

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification By Wesley Salmon Analysis by Margarita Georgieva, PSTS student, number 0102458 Van Lochemstraat 9-17 7511 EG Enschede Final Paper for Philosophy of Science

More information

Brown and Janssen on the Arrow of. Explanation in Special Relativity

Brown and Janssen on the Arrow of. Explanation in Special Relativity Brown and Janssen on the Arrow of Explanation in Special Relativity Abstract I examine the debate between Michel Janssen and Harvey Brown over the arrow of explanation in special relativity. Brown argues

More information

What Comes After Structural Realism?

What Comes After Structural Realism? Homotopy Type Theory and Constructive Identity 23 novembre 2012 How To Be a Realist After Kant? Two Issues About Scientific Realism Mathematical and Physical Objecthood and Objectivity Structuralism is

More information

In defence of classical physics

In defence of classical physics In defence of classical physics Abstract Classical physics seeks to find the laws of nature. I am of the opinion that classical Newtonian physics is real physics. This is in the sense that it relates to

More information

The structural metaphysics of quantum theory and general relativity

The structural metaphysics of quantum theory and general relativity The structural metaphysics of quantum theory and general relativity Vincent Lam and Michael Esfeld University of Queensland, School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics, v.lam@uq.edu.au University

More information

Regarding the Hole Argument

Regarding the Hole Argument Regarding the Hole Argument James Owen Weatherall Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine, CA 92697 Abstract I argue that the Hole Argument is based on a misleading

More information

The singular nature of space-time

The singular nature of space-time The singular nature of space-time March 13, 2006 Abstract We consider to what extent the fundamental question of space-time singularities is relevant for the philosophical debate about the nature of space-time.

More information

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006

Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University Draft: 3 Feb. 2006 Avoiding the Block Universe: A Reply to Petkov Peter Bokulich Boston University pbokulic@bu.edu Draft: 3 Feb. 2006 Key Points: 1. Petkov assumes that the standard relativistic interpretations of measurement

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 17/11/15 Neo-Fregeanism Last week, we considered recent attempts to revive Fregean logicism. Analytic

More information

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism

[Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008 [Handout 23] John Hawthorne, Three-Dimensionalism vs. Four-Dimensionalism Professor JeeLoo Liu The debate: On the nature of persisting material objects [Three-Dimensionalism]:

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational?

The Philosophy of Physics. Is Space Absolute or Relational? The Philosophy of Physics Lecture Two Is Space Absolute or Relational? Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Newton s Absolute Motion and Acceleration Is Space Absolute or Relational? Newton

More information

A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism

A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism Candidate Number: 26386 Programme: MSc in Philosophy of Science Academic adviser: Miklós Rédei August 21, 2014 Word count: 9856 obtained via: (http://app.uio.no/ifi/texcount/online.php)

More information

Comments on Sklar s Barbour s Relationist Metric of Time

Comments on Sklar s Barbour s Relationist Metric of Time Comments on Sklar s Barbour s Relationist Metric of Time Oliver Pooley Oriel College, University of Oxford 12 July, 2004 Professor Sklar s paper (Sklar, 2003 4) illustrates very well the vitality of the

More information

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. Mind Association Response to Colyvan Author(s): Joseph Melia Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 111, No. 441 (Jan., 2002), pp. 75-79 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association

More information

A Way of Getting Rid of Things:

A Way of Getting Rid of Things: A Way of Getting Rid of Things: Higher-order Langauges, Priorian Nominalism, and Nihilism: Cian Dorr Rutgers Workshop on Structural Realism and the Metaphysics of Science 1. Higher-order quantification

More information

has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general relativity.

has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general relativity. http://preposterousuniverse.com/grnotes/ has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general relativity. As with any major theory in physics, GR has been framed

More information

Galilean Spacetime (Neo-Newtonian Spacetime) P t = 2

Galilean Spacetime (Neo-Newtonian Spacetime) P t = 2 (Neo-Newtonian Spacetime) Figure V t t t = t* vt x P t = 2 t = 1 t = 0 O x x vt x I used figure V above to show you how to change the coordinates of point P in the coordinate system S to coordinates in

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms Part 2: Theoretical Terms 1. What Apparatus Is Available for Carrying out Analyses?

More information

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality?

What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality? What Does Quantum Mechanics Suggest About Our Perceptions of Reality? Quantum mechanics suggests that we perceive at most a tiny sliver of reality. Of course we already knew that! We knew that the visible

More information

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science Brian Hepburn Wichita State University Nov 5, 2017 Presentation time: 20 mins Abstract Here is a phrase never uttered before: Euler s philosophy of science. Known

More information

Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism

Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism Journal reference: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2007) 626 Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism László E. Szabó Theoretical Physics Research

More information

Spacetime Substantivalism and Einstein s Cosmological Constant

Spacetime Substantivalism and Einstein s Cosmological Constant Spacetime Substantivalism and Einstein s Cosmological Constant David J. Baker January 9, 2005 Abstract I offer a novel argument for spacetime substantivalism: we should take the spacetime of general relativity

More information

*a * * *b * * *c *d *

*a * * *b * * *c *d * K. MCDANIEL DISTANCE AND DISCRETE SPACE Let us say that space is discrete if and only if every finite extended region of space is composed of finitely many atomic regions of space. I assume here that regions

More information

Office Hours Michelle Wingerter: Monday 11:15am-12:15pm, 344 Goldwin Smith Hall Professor North: Tuesday 1:00-2:00pm, 235 Goldwin Smith Hall

Office Hours Michelle Wingerter: Monday 11:15am-12:15pm, 344 Goldwin Smith Hall Professor North: Tuesday 1:00-2:00pm, 235 Goldwin Smith Hall Philosophy 3850/Physics 2202: Philosophy of Physics, Spring 2014 TTh 11:40 12:55, Rockefeller 122 Professor North (north@cornell.edu) Michelle Wingerter (mw742@cornell.edu ) This course is an introduction

More information

Accelerated Observers

Accelerated Observers Accelerated Observers In the last few lectures, we ve been discussing the implications that the postulates of special relativity have on the physics of our universe. We ve seen how to compute proper times

More information

THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS THE SYDNEY SCHOOL AN ARISTOTELIAN REALIST PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS INTRODUCTION Mathematics is a science of the real world, just as much as biology or sociology are. Where biology studies living things

More information

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! Jerry Fodor and his Special Sciences So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! ) The use of special in

More information

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM Michele Caponigro ISHTAR, Bergamo University Abstract From conceptual point of view, we argue about the nature of reality inferred from EPR

More information

Incompatibility Paradoxes

Incompatibility Paradoxes Chapter 22 Incompatibility Paradoxes 22.1 Simultaneous Values There is never any difficulty in supposing that a classical mechanical system possesses, at a particular instant of time, precise values of

More information

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS

ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS ON THE FAITHFUL INTERPRETATION OF PURE WAVE MECHANICS JEFFREY A. BARRETT In the long version of his Ph.D. thesis, Hugh Everett III developed pure wave mechanics as a way of solving the quantum measurement

More information

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Rohan French Abstract In Wehmeier (2004) we are presented with the subjunctive modal language, a way of dealing with the expressive inadequacy of modal logic by marking

More information

Are Shapes Intrinsic?

Are Shapes Intrinsic? Are Shapes Intrinsic? Bradford Skow 1 Introduction Are shapes intrinsic? Intuitively, an intrinsic property is a property that characterizes something as it is in itself. What intrinsic properties something

More information

The Metaphysics of Super-Substantivalism

The Metaphysics of Super-Substantivalism The Metaphysics of Super-Substantivalism Dennis Lehmkuhl Einstein Papers Project and Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences California Institute of Technology lehmkuhl@caltech.edu June 25, 2015

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime The Philosophy of Physics Lecture Five Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Special Relativity a quick refresher Special Relativity and Minkowski

More information

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Darrell P. Rowbottom This paper shows that Popper s measure of corroboration is inapplicable if, as Popper also argued, the logical probability of synthetic

More information

Against Option 1, Healey notes that in non-abelian Yang-Mills theories, two distinct gauge potential fields may give rise to the same gauge

Against Option 1, Healey notes that in non-abelian Yang-Mills theories, two distinct gauge potential fields may give rise to the same gauge Richard Healey, Gauging What s Real: The Conceptual Foundations of Contemporary Gauge Theories. Oxford: Oxford University Press (2007), 240 pp., $99.00 (cloth). This well-researched and authoritative book

More information

0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION

0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION 0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION In a very rough sketch we explain what algebraic geometry is about and what it can be used for. We stress the many correlations with other fields of research, such as

More information

Einstein s Hole Argument and its Legacy

Einstein s Hole Argument and its Legacy Einstein s Hole Argument and its Legacy Hanns Hagen Goetzke Hughes Hall University of Cambridge 2.7.2011 Contents 1 Introduction 3 2 The hole argument 5 3 Substantivalism 10 4 A threat to substantivalism

More information

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Ted Sider Modality seminar 1. Methodology The title of this book may sound to some readers like Good as Evil, or perhaps Cabbages as Kings. If logic and metaphysics

More information

Disregarding the Hole Argument

Disregarding the Hole Argument Disregarding the Hole Argument Bryan W. Roberts Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method London School of Economics and Political Science Houghton Street, London WC2A 2AE Abstract. Jim Weatherall

More information

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts CAUSATION Chapter 14 Causation and the Direction of Time 14.1 Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts What reasons are there for thinking that at least those tenseless

More information

Super-Relationism: Combining Eliminativism about Objects and Relationism about Spacetime. Baptiste Le Bihan

Super-Relationism: Combining Eliminativism about Objects and Relationism about Spacetime. Baptiste Le Bihan Super-Relationism: Combining Eliminativism about Objects and Relationism about Spacetime Baptiste Le Bihan Baptiste.LeBihan@univ-rennes1.fr Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies Penultimate Draft Abstract:

More information

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism CAUSATION CAUSATION Chapter 10 Non-Humean Reductionism Humean states of affairs were characterized recursively in chapter 2, the basic idea being that distinct Humean states of affairs cannot stand in

More information

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time

On the Evolution of the Concept of Time On the Evolution of the Concept of Time Berislav Žarnić Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences Research Centre for Logic, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science University of Split Physics & Philosophy

More information

Searle on Emergence. Vladimír Havlík. The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague

Searle on Emergence. Vladimír Havlík. The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague Searle on Emergence Vladimír Havlík The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Prague Abstract: Searle s conception of ontological emergence is a basis for his explanation of mind and consciousness

More information

has been falsified by the development of special relativity. In this paper, I identify and reject an

has been falsified by the development of special relativity. In this paper, I identify and reject an Presentism as an empirical hypothesis Abstract Within philosophy of physics it is broadly accepted that presentism as an empirical hypothesis has been falsified by the development of special relativity.

More information

Space, time, and spacetime, part I. Newton s bucket to Einstein s hole

Space, time, and spacetime, part I. Newton s bucket to Einstein s hole : from Newton s bucket to Einstein s hole http://philosophy.ucsd.edu/faculty/wuthrich/ Osher Lifelong Learning Institute, UCSD 5 October 2010 Organization of talk 1 Philosophy of space from Newton to Mach

More information

Consequences of special relativity.

Consequences of special relativity. PHYS419 Lecture 12 Consequences of special relativity 1 Consequences of special relativity. The length of moving objects. Recall that in special relativity, simultaneity depends on the frame of reference

More information

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp. 72-81. The Bundle Theory is compatible with distinct but indiscernible particulars GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. The Bundle Theory I shall discuss is a theory about

More information

Hilbert and the concept of axiom

Hilbert and the concept of axiom Hilbert and the concept of axiom Giorgio Venturi Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa Giorgio Venturi (SNS) Hilbert and the concept of axiom 1/24 First period Axiomatic method in the first period The actual

More information

Mathematical versus physical meaning of classical mechanics quantities

Mathematical versus physical meaning of classical mechanics quantities Apeiron, Vol. 17, No. 2, April 2010 173 Mathematical versus physical meaning of classical mechanics quantities Mirosław Zabierowski Opole Technology University, Poland miroslaw_zabierowski@o2.pl Three

More information

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014 ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014 OUTLINE Methodology Primitive Ontology Local Beables Primitive Ontology The Role of Mathematics in Physical

More information

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate Richard Johns Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia johns@interchange.ubc.ca January 19, 2005 There are usually considered to be three main views

More information

Consequences of special relativity.

Consequences of special relativity. PHYS419 Lecture 12 Consequences of special relativity 1 Consequences of special relativity. The length of moving objects. Recall that in special relativity, simultaneity depends on the frame of reference

More information

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Ontology on Shaky Grounds 1 Ontology on Shaky Grounds Jean-Pierre Marquis Département de Philosophie Université de Montréal C.P. 6128, succ. Centre-ville Montréal, P.Q. Canada H3C 3J7 Jean-Pierre.Marquis@umontreal.ca In Realistic

More information

Leibniz s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii

Leibniz s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Leibniz s Ultimate Theory Soshichi Uchii Abstract This is a short summary of my new interpretation of Leibniz s philosophy, including metaphysics and dynamics. Monadology is the core of his philosophy,

More information

Extrinsic Temporal Metrics. Bradford Skow

Extrinsic Temporal Metrics. Bradford Skow Extrinsic Temporal Metrics Bradford Skow 1 Introduction When distinguishing absolute, true, and mathematical time from relative, apparent, and common time, Newton wrote: absolute, true, and mathematical

More information

Temporal Extension. 1. Time as Quantity

Temporal Extension. 1. Time as Quantity 1 Boris Hennig IFOMIS Saarbrücken Draft version as of July 17, 2005 Temporal Extension Abstract. Space and time are continuous and extensive quantities. But according to Aristotle, time differs from space

More information

Against a structural realist understanding of spacetime: the disanalogy between points and particles

Against a structural realist understanding of spacetime: the disanalogy between points and particles Against a structural realist understanding of spacetime: the disanalogy between points and particles Oliver Pooley Oriel College, Oxford oliver.pooley@philosophy.ox.ac.uk UIC, 22 April 2004 The financial

More information

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem

Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem Why the Difference Between Quantum and Classical Physics is Irrelevant to the Mind/Body Problem Kirk Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611-8545 U.S.A. kludwig@phil.ufl.edu

More information

Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories

Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories Substantival vs. relational space(-time) 1: Pre-relativistic theories Pt. II Philosophy of Physics Lecture 1, 16 January 2015, Adam Caulton (aepw2@cam.ac.uk) 1 Newton s three laws From Newton s The Mathematical

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus February 18 Smart, The Tenseless Theory of Time aka the B-Theory Marcus, Modern Philosophy, Spring 2010, Slide 1 The Presentist A-Theory

More information

Minimality, Geometry and Simultaneity

Minimality, Geometry and Simultaneity Claudio Calosi Abstract: I give two new uniqueness results for the standard relation of simultaneity in the context of metrical time oriented Minkowski spacetime. These results improve on the classic ones

More information

Refining the Motivational Approach to Symmetry-to-(un)reality Inferences

Refining the Motivational Approach to Symmetry-to-(un)reality Inferences Refining the Motivational Approach to Symmetry-to-(un)reality Inferences Case Study: Aharonov-Bohm Effect Niels Martens Foundations2018, Utrecht 12 July 2018 A1. Virtual particles A2. Naturalness A3. LHC,

More information

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 5: E = mc 2 ; Philosophical Significance of Special Relativity

Einstein for Everyone Lecture 5: E = mc 2 ; Philosophical Significance of Special Relativity Einstein for Everyone Lecture 5: E = mc 2 ; Philosophical Significance of Special Relativity Dr. Erik Curiel Munich Center For Mathematical Philosophy Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität 1 Dynamics Background

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 01/12/15 Classical mathematics Consider the Pythagorean argument that 2 is irrational: 1. Assume that

More information

The Solvability of Probabilistic Regresses. A Reply to Frederik Herzberg

The Solvability of Probabilistic Regresses. A Reply to Frederik Herzberg The Solvability of Probabilistic Regresses. A Reply to Frederik Herzberg David Atkinson and Jeanne Peijnenburg Abstract We have earlier shown by construction that a proposition can have a well-defined

More information

Ontic structural realism as a metaphysics of objects

Ontic structural realism as a metaphysics of objects Ontic structural realism as a metaphysics of objects Michael Esfeld and Vincent Lam 1 University of Lausanne, Department of Philosophy, Michael-Andreas.Esfeld@unil.ch University of Queensland, School of

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 25, Metaphysics, 2011 THE BARE NECESSITIES Shamik Dasgupta We talk of material bodies being situated in space andofeventsasoccurring at times. And

More information

carroll/notes/ has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general

carroll/notes/ has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general http://pancake.uchicago.edu/ carroll/notes/ has a lot of good notes on GR and links to other pages. General Relativity Philosophy of general relativity. As with any major theory in physics, GR has been

More information

07. Interpreting Special Relativity 1. Two Interpretations of Special Relativity

07. Interpreting Special Relativity 1. Two Interpretations of Special Relativity 07. Interpreting Special Relativity 1. Two Interpretations of Special Relativity Basic Question: What would the world be like if special relativity were true? (1) Spacetime Substantivalist Interpretation.

More information

Leibniz s Possible Worlds. Liu Jingxian Department of Philosophy Peking University

Leibniz s Possible Worlds. Liu Jingxian Department of Philosophy Peking University Leibniz s Possible Worlds Liu Jingxian Department of Philosophy Peking University 1 Contents 1. Leibniz s Motivation 2. Complete Concepts and Possible Individuals 3. Compossibility 3.1. Analytically or

More information

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles arxiv:1210.1463v1 [quant-ph] 4 Oct 2012 Joe Henson February 10, 2019 Abstract Rédei and san Pedro

More information

Aristotle, Space and Time

Aristotle, Space and Time Mann, S., 2013. Aristotle, space and time. In M. Tsianikas, N. Maadad, G. Couvalis, and M. Palaktsoglou (eds.) "Greek Research in Australia: Proceedings of the Biennial International Conference of Greek

More information

A Remark About the Geodesic Principle in General Relativity

A Remark About the Geodesic Principle in General Relativity A Remark About the Geodesic Principle in General Relativity Version 3.0 David B. Malament Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science 3151 Social Science Plaza University of California, Irvine Irvine,

More information

Motion Fundamentals. 1 Postulates. 2 Natural Progression. Thomas Kirk

Motion Fundamentals. 1 Postulates. 2 Natural Progression. Thomas Kirk Motion Fundamentals Thomas Kirk I was asked by the Editor to respond to comments by the editorial referee on my article, Derivation of Reciprocal System Mathematics", and also to comment on K.V.K. Nehru

More information

The singular nature of space-time

The singular nature of space-time The singular nature of space-time Vincent Lam University of Lausanne January 30, 2007 Abstract We consider to what extent the fundamental question of space-time singularities is relevant for the philosophical

More information

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Iñaki San Pedro Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of the Basque Country, UPV/EHU inaki.sanpedro@ehu.es Abstract

More information

Leibniz on Motion Reply to Edward Slowik. Anja Jauernig, University of Notre Dame

Leibniz on Motion Reply to Edward Slowik. Anja Jauernig, University of Notre Dame Leibniz on Motion Reply to Edward Slowik Anja Jauernig, University of Notre Dame I n his contribution to this volume of The Leibniz Review, Another Go-Around on Leibniz on Rotation, Edward Slowik critically

More information

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere Identity in Physics and Elsewhere Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL 33124, USA E-mail: otaviobueno@mac.com 1. INTRODUCTION Is identity a fundamental concept? Of

More information