Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ."

Transcription

1 Initial Ordinals We now return to ordinals in general and use them to give a more precise meaning to the notion of a cardinal. First we make some observations. Note that if there is an ordinal with a certain property (expressible by a formula φ(x) of ZF) then there is a least such ordinal since the if φ(α) holds for some ordinal α then the set {β α + 1 φ(β)} is non-empty and its least element is also the least ordinal satisfying φ. Definition by Transfinite Recursion on Ord. If θ(x,u, y) is as in Theorem 7 (see (4), page 45 ) then there is a unique class function F such that for all ordinals α we have θ(α, F α, F(α)). This is because by Theorem 7 for each δ Ord there is a unique f δ with domain δ such that for each α δ we have θ(α, f δ α,f δ (α)), and since it is easy to see that for γ, δ Ord, δ < γ we must have f γ δ = f δ, we can take F to be the union of all f δ over δ Ord (so F δ = f δ for each δ Ord). In order to apply Theorem 7 when dealing with ordinals, it is often convenient to specify the values of the function that is being defined separately: for 0, for successor ordinals in terms of the values for the immediate predecessors, and for limit ordinals. Definition 26 We say that an ordinal κ is an initial ordinal, or a cardinal, if for each ordinal β such that β < κ we have β κ (that is, β κ and β κ). The class of all initial ordinals is denoted Card. Notes 1 If β < κ then β κ by Proposition 48(iii), so β κ holds obviously. The distinguishing feature is that β κ for all β < κ. Note that for example, ω + 1 = ω {ω} is not an initial ordinal since f : ω ω {ω} defined by f(0) = ω, f(m + 1) = m for m ω is a bijection. More generally, no infinite successor ordinal is an initial ordinal by Example We have an apparent clash in terminology here since we have already used the term cardinal (number) in the naive part for something that is shared by equinumerous sets. We will explain the connection shortly. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ. Proof Let α be an ordinal and let c = {γ γ is an ordinal &γ α &α γ}. Clearly α c so c is a nonempty set of ordinals, and as such it has a least element δ. δ is an initial ordinal since if not then there would be some λ < δ such that λ δ but then also λ α so λ c but that cannot be because δ is the least element of c. Hence we can take δ for κ. 63

2 Proposition 58 (i) Each n ω is an initial ordinal. (ii) ω is an initial ordinal. Proof (i) follows by the Pigeonhole Principle for natural numbers (Proposition 5), since if n ω = N and k < n then n k would mean an injection from n to k < n which cannot be. (ii) follows by Proposition 7. Proposition 59 If b is a set of initial ordinals then b is an initial ordinal. Proof By Proposition 49(ii) α = b is an ordinal. Let β < α, that is, β α. By the definition of α there is some γ b such that β γ. Hence β < γ and γ α. If α β was true then we would have γ β (since the restriction of a bijection between α and β to γ is an injection from γ to β) but clearly also β γ, so we would have β γ which contradicts γ being an initial ordinal. Proposition 60 If κ is an initial ordinal then there is an initial ordinal κ + such that κ < κ + and if α < κ + then α κ. Proof Let C = {γ γ is an ordinal & γ κ}. C is non-empty by Theorem 11 and the least element of it has the required properties. Hence we have initial ordinals 0, 1, 2,3,, }{{} ω, ω , ω1, ω2,, ω n, ω ω + }{{}}{{}}{{} 0,,ω ω1, =ω 0 n N }{{} =ω 1 =ω 2 =ω 3 }{{} =ω ω0 +1 =ω ω0 The subscripts 1 are ordinals, for a successor ordinal ω α+1 = ω + α and for a limit ordinal ω α = β<α ω β. The ω α are well defined by Theorem 7 and the above observation about using it for Ord. In more detail, for each ordinal δ there is a unique function f δ with Dom(f δ ) = δ (and Rng(f δ ) Card) such that f δ (0) = ω and { (f f δ δ (α 1)) + if α is a successor (α) = β<α fδ (β) if α is a limit ordinal By Example 8.2, if 0 < δ < γ then f γ δ = f δ so w α is f γ (α) where γ is any ordinal greater than α. By the same Example, any infinite initial ordinal is equal to ω α for some α. Hence we have { Pow(N) R N = ω = ω 0 1 Note that ω n for n ω could also stand for the initial segment N n as we used it before. It is always clear from the context what is meant. ω 1 64

3 The Continuum Hypothesis, which we have mentioned before, asserts that ω 1 R. It cannot be proved, nor shown false, from the ZF axioms. We remark that ω α in their role as initial ordinals are sometimes also written as ℵ α. Recall that we have defined sets a, b to have the same cardinality, a = b if a b, but we have not said what cardinality is. For sets that are equinumerous to an initial ordinal we take their cardinality to be that initial ordinal, and we identify ℵ α and ℵ α. Hence ω α = ℵ α and since ω = ω 0 = N, we have ω = N = ℵ 0. Expressions like a = ℵ 0, b = 2 ℵ0 mean a N, b 2 N as before. We will not use this notation except for ℵ 0 as we have already done in the early part of the course. Theorem 13 For κ an initial ordinal such that ω κ we have κ κ κ. Proof Assume that the theorem fails and let λ be the least infinite initial ordinal such that λ λ λ. Let be the well-ordering of λ λ defined by γ,δ α,β [γ δ < α β (γ δ = α β & (γ < α (γ = α & δ < β)))] (please see Coursework 2 & solutions). By Theorem 8 there is an isomorphism between (λ,<) and λ λ, or between one of them and an initial segment of the other. Assume that λ is isomorphic to some initial segment (λ λ) α,β where α, β λ. Note that α β is equal to the greater of α and β so since λ is an infinite initial ordinal and as such a limit ordinal, γ = (α β) + 1 λ. γ is infinite (exercise) and by definition of we have (λ λ) α,β γ γ so the assumption of λ being isomorphic to (λ λ) α,β means that λ γ γ. Let µ γ be the initial ordinal such that γ µ (it exists by Proposition 57). Then µ < λ so we must have µ µ µ because λ is the first infinite initial ordinal for which it fails, so λ γ γ µ µ µ and hence (using the Schröder Bernstein theorem) λ µ but that contradicts λ being an initial ordinal. It follows that there must be an isomorphism between (λ λ, ) and either λ or an initial segment of it but that means that λ λ λ so since also obviously λ λ λ, λ λ λ by the Schröder Bernstein theorem again, but that contradicts the choice of λ. The result follows. Corollary 8 For every infinite set b which can be well ordered we have b b b. Proof This follows from by the previous theorem, Theorem 10 and Proposition 57 (exercise). 65

4 The Axiom of Choice The Axiom of Choice, AC For b a set, / b there is a function f : b b such that for all x b, f(x) x. In this case we say that f is a choice function on b since for each x b f picks an element of x. Notes 1 From work of Gödel (1937) it is known that AC cannot be disproved from ZF whilst from work of Cohen (1963) (for which he won the Field s Medal), AC cannot be proved from ZF. So AC is independent of ZF (as is the Continuum Hypothesis). 2 The axioms of ZF with AC added to them are referred to as ZFC. If a theorem, lemma or proposition uses AC in its proof we write Theorem (AC) etc. 3 We have already seen an example of AC when we showed that for a countable set u such that all elements of u are countable the set u is countable, which is the contents of Proposition 16: assume that u is a non-empty and countable set of non-empty countable sets. 1 So u = {a 0,a 1,a 2,...} and there is a function t with domain N such that 2 t(n) = { g g is a surjective function from N to a n } for n N Let b = Rng(t) = {t(n) n N}. Each element of b is non-empty since each a n is non-empty and countable, so by AC there is a function f with domain b such that for y = t(n) b, f(y) is a surjective function from N to a n, that is, Defining by f(t(n)) : N a n for n N. h : N N n=0 a n h(n,m) = [f(t(n))](m) for n,m N, noting that h is a surjection and recalling that N N N gives N n=0 a n so the result follows. 4 It is not necessarily always the case that we need to appeal to AC in order to guarantee the existence of a choice function. If the set b is finite then we 1 Recall that u being non-empty and countable means that u = {a 0, a 1, a 2,...}, where a n = r(n) for some surjective function with domain N 2 t exists by Proposition

5 can prove that a choice function exists, see Example 8.3. Even when b is infinite there may be some way of picking out a distinguished element of each x b, and thus we may be able to show that a choice function exists just from ZF alone 1. The following is an important example of this: Lemma 10 If / b and b can be well ordered then b has a choice function. Proof Let be a well ordering of b. Notice that if x b then = x b so x has a (unique) least element with respect to. Defining f : b b by equivalently f(x) = the least element of x wrt, f = { x,y x b & y x & ( z x)y z }, gives the required choice function without using AC. The main purpose of this section is to prove the equivalence of AC with several other well known possible axioms. The first of these is: The Well Ordering Theorem, WOT Every set can be well ordered. Theorem 14 WOT AC. Proof In the direction this is an immediate consequence of Lemma 10. In the other direction assume AC and let c be a set. We need to define a well ordering of c. Let b be the set of non-empty subsets of c and let g be a choice function for b, that is, g : b b and g(x) x for all x b. Note that b = c. Given an ordinal α, by Theorem 7 there is a function f α : α c {c} such that for β α { f α g(c\rng(f (β) = α β)) if c\rng(f α β), c otherwise (13) Notice that if α < λ Ord then f α = f λ α. For if not there would be a β < α such that f α (β) f λ (β). But then there would be a least such β and for this we must have f α β = f λ β and hence from (13), f α (β) = f λ (β), contradiction. Clearly for γ < β < α and f α (β) c, f α (β) f α (γ) since f α (γ) Rng(f α β) and f α (β) = g(c\rng(f α β)) c\rng(f α β) so f α (β) / Rng(f α β). Hence if c / Rng(f α ) then f α is an injection from α into c. 1 Bertrand Russel gave an example of an infinite set of pairs of shoes on the one hand and an infinite set of pairs of socks on the other hand. We can argue that within the former there clearly exists the subset of left shoes but why should there be a subset of the set of socks containing just one from each pair? 67

6 By Theorem 11 there is some ordinal λ such that λ c, so for this λ it must be the case that c Rng(f λ ). Hence for some α < λ, c\rng(f λ α) =. For the least such α then c Rng(f λ α) and for γ < α so f λ (γ) c and Rng(f λ α) = c. c\rng(f λ γ) Recalling that f λ α = f α and putting this together with the fact established above that if c / Rng(f α ) then f α is an injection from α into c we see that f α is a bijection from α to c. By Proposition 44 (applied to (f α ) 1 ) we can well order c, as required. Cardinals By Theorem 10 and Proposition 57 every set which can be well ordered is equinumerous to some, necessarily unique, initial ordinal. Under AC any set can be well ordered so cardinal numbers as we intuitively described them early on can all be identified with initial ordinals (cardinals). A second equivalent of AC is: Law of Trichotomy, LOT For any two sets a, b either a b or b a. Theorem 15 AC LOT. Proof Since WOT is equivalent to AC it is enough to show that WOT is equivalent to LOT. We have done this already, see Corollary 4 and the remark following Hartog s Theorem (Theorem 11). Our third equivalent is commonly applied in mainline Pure Mathematics. It concerns the existence of maximal elements in posets. If (x, ) is a poset and y x we say that y is a chain if for all u, v y, we have u v or v v, that is, if y is a subset of x that is totally ordered by the restriction of. We say that w x is an upper bound for y if for all u y we have u w. Recall that s is a maximal element of x if ( u x) s u. Zorn s Lemma, ZL Let x, be a poset such that every chain has an upper bound. Then x has a maximal element. Theorem 16 ZL AC. Proof Assume ZL. We shall show LOT. Let a,b be sets and let x be the set of bijections from a subset of a to a subset of b, that is x = {f ( c a)( d b)f : c d}. 68

7 Please check that it is a set as an exercise. For f, g x let f g f g. Then x, clearly is a poset, and if y x is a chain then y is also bijection from a subset of a to a subset of b, so y x, and y is an upper bound for y. See Example 8.5 for details. Hence by ZL there is a maximal element f x. It must be the case that either Dom(f) = a, in which case f : a b, or Rng(f) = b, in which case f 1 : b a. Otherwise we would have Dom(f) a and Rng(F) b so there would exist some u a\dom(f) and v b\rng(f) which would mean f { u, v } x and f f { u,v }, contradicting the maximality of f. It follows that ZL implies LOT, and hence AC. For the other direction assume WOT. Let x, be a poset such that every chain has an upper bound. By WOT x can be well ordered and hence by Theorem 10 there is an ordinal α and a function g such that g : α x. By Theorem 7 there is a function h : α x such that { g(β) if ( γ < β) [ h(γ) g(β) g(β) h(γ)], h(β) = g(0) otherwise. Notice that the first case holds when β = 0, and that h(0) = g(0). We shall show that Rng(h) x is a chain. Let u, v Rng(h) and suppose u = h(γ), v = h(δ) with, say, γ < δ. Then by the choice of h(δ) either h(δ) = g(δ) and h(γ) h(δ) h(δ) h(γ), or h(δ) = g(0) = h(0) so again, if h(γ) = g(0) then h(δ) = g(0) = h(γ) and otherwise h(γ) = g(γ) and h(δ) = h(0) h(γ) h(γ) h(0) = h(δ). Since Rng(h) is a chain, by the assumption on x, it has an upper bound. Let s x be an upper bound for Rng(h). This s must be a maximal element of x (with respect to ). Otherwise there would be some u x such that s u, say u = g(β), β α. Then for all v Rng(h), v s u so v u. But since Rng(h β) Rng(h) this means that ( γ < β)h(γ) g(β) so h(β) = g(β) = u and hence u Rng(h) and u s, contradiction. Hence s is indeed a maximal element of x. It follows that WOT, and hence AC, implies ZL. Zorn s Lemma has a number of applications outside of Set Theory, for (nonexaminable) example: Proposition 61 (AC) Every vector space has a basis. 69

8 Proof Let V be a vector space over a field F 1 and let x be the set of linearly independent subsets of V. Consider the poset x, (somewhat abusing the notation, we mean x with the restriction of to x). If y x is a chain then the vectors in y are also linearly independent (exercise) so y x, and y is an upper bound for y. Hence x satisfies the assumption of ZL. By ZL there is a maximal element b of x. Since the vectors in b are linearly independent to show that b is a basis it is enough to show that b spans V. Suppose not, say u V but u cannot be written in the form r 1 v 1 + r 2 v r n v n for any r 1,r 2,...,r n F and v 1,v 2,...,v n b. Then the vectors in b {u} are still linearly independent, so this set is in x but b b {u} which contradicts b being a maximal element of x. So b is the required base. This is obviously a result which algebraists would welcome. However it already hints at a darker side to AC: Corollary 9 There is a non-linear function f : R R satisfying the equation f(x + y) = f(x) + f(y), By non-linear we mean that f is not of the form f(x) = ax for any constant a R. Proof Using Proposition 61 let b R be a basis for the vector space of the reals over the field of rationals (a Hamel Basis). Pick v 0 b. Then any x R can be written as x = r 0 v 0 + r 1 v 1 + r 2 v r m v m for some r 0,r 1,r 2,...,r m Q and v 1,v 2,...v m b, where none of v 1,v 2,...,v m is equal to v 0. Furthermore, r 0 in this representation is unique (it may be 0). Define f(x) = r 0. Noticing that if x = r 0 v 0 + r 1 v 1 + r 2 v r m v m, y = p 0 v 0 + p 1 w 1 + p 2 w p n w n, with r 0,r 1,...,r m,p 0,p 1,...,p n Q and v 1,v 2,...,v m,w 1,w 2,...,w n b and v 0 distinct from any of v 1, v 2,...,v m, w 1,w 2,...,w n then x + y = (r 0 + p 0 )v 0 + r 1 v r m v m + p 1 w p n w n 1 Recall that a vector space over a field F (with operations + F, F) is a set V that is an Abelian group under vector addition (which we denote +), with a scalar multiplication assigning rv V to each r F and v V, such that that the appropriate properties of distributivity, and of compatibility of the multiplications hold. A set a V is linearly independent if for any finite subset {v 1,...,v n} of a (with v 1,...,v n distinct) and r 1,... r n F, if r 1 v r n v n = 0 then r 1 = = r n = 0. A set a V is a basis for V if it is linearly independent and any u V can be expressed as a linear combination of elements of a, i.e. as r 1 v r nv n for some v 1,...,v n a and r 1,, r n F. 70

9 so f(x + y) = r 0 + p 0 = f(x) + f(y) though f is clearly not linear (it only takes rational values and is not identically zero). Just for interest we now give another, rather surprising equivalent of AC. Theorem 17 AC a a a for every infinite set a. Proof Left to right follows from Corollary 8 In the other direction given a set b it is enough to show that assuming the right hand side b can be well ordered. We can obviously assume that b is non-empty. Let α be such that not α b (in Theorem 11 such an ordinal α has been shown to exist, without using AC). Clearly we may assume that α ω 0. To simplify the notation without loss of generality assume that b α = (otherwise we can take e.g. b {α} in place of b; there is an obvious bijection between this set and b, so showing that it can be well ordered implies that b can be well ordered and (b {α}) α = - exercise ). We first show that b α b α using the Schröder-Bernstein Theorem. We have b α (b b) (b α) (α b) (α α) = (b α) (b α) b α. Now pick x 0 b. The function f : b α b (α α) defined by f(x) = x, 0,0 for x b, f(β) = x 0, β,1 is an injection, so b α b (α α). This gives for β α b α b (α α) b α. Hence we have some function g : b α b α. There are two possibilities, either for some x 0 b we have g(x 0,β) b for all β α, or for every x b there is some β α such that g(x,β) α. In the first case the function f : α b defined by f(β) = g(x 0,β) for β α gives an injection from α into b, contradicting the choice of α. So assume that for every x b there is some β α such that g(x,β) α, and define z : b α by z(x) = the least β such that g(x,β) α for x b. Then the function f : b α defined by f(x) = g(x,z(x)) for x b gives an injection from b into α, so b can be well ordered (Proposition 44). 71

Well Ordered Sets (continued)

Well Ordered Sets (continued) Well Ordered Sets (continued) Theorem 8 Given any two well-ordered sets, either they are isomorphic, or one is isomorphic to an initial segment of the other. Proof Let a,< and b, be well-ordered sets.

More information

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction (David Ross, UH-Manoa Dept. of Mathematics) 1 Cardinality Recall the following notions: function, relation, one-to-one, onto, on-to-one correspondence,

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. 20 Definition 20.1. A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. (a) Each natural number n is an ordinal. (b) ω is an ordinal. (a) ω {ω} is an ordinal.

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University Sets, Models and Proofs I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University 2000; revised, 2006 Contents 1 Sets 1 1.1 Cardinal Numbers........................ 2 1.1.1 The Continuum

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Cardinality and ordinal numbers Cardinality and ordinal numbers The cardinality A of a finite set A is simply the number of elements in it. When it comes to infinite sets, we no longer can speak of the number of elements in such a set.

More information

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id: Name: Student Id: There are nine problems (check that you have 9 pages). Solutions are expected to be short. In the case of proofs, one or two short paragraphs should be the average length. Write your

More information

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction Benedikt Löwe Universiteit van Amsterdam Grzegorz Plebanek Uniwersytet Wroc lawski ESSLLI 2011, Ljubljana, Slovenia

More information

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Part II Logic and Set Theory Part II Logic and Set Theory Theorems Based on lectures by I. B. Leader Notes taken by Dexter Chua Lent 2015 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS 1. Cardinal number of a set The cardinal number (or simply cardinal) of a set is a generalization of the concept of the number of elements

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers August 29, 2013 1 Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols and the variables,,,, =, (, ) v j

More information

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC CHRISTOPHER WILSON Abstract. We present a basic axiomatic development of Zermelo-Fraenkel and Choice set theory, commonly abbreviated ZFC. This paper is aimed in particular

More information

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS TH. SCHLUMPRECHT 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols,,,, =, (, ) and the variables v j : where j is a natural number.

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001 Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001 Definitions. A set together with a binary relation < is called a partially ordered set (poset in short) if x (x < x) x y z ((x < y y < z)

More information

The Axiom of Choice and Some Equivalences:

The Axiom of Choice and Some Equivalences: The Axiom of Choice and Some Equivalences: A Senior Exercise Tate Deskins Department of Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 1 CONTENTS Contents 1 Introduction and Motivation 3 1.1 Overview..............................

More information

Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis

Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis Tali Magidson June 6, 2017 Synopsis In June 2002, "Two Classical Surprises Concerning the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum

More information

Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory

Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory Short Introduction to Admissible Recursion Theory Rachael Alvir November 2016 1 Axioms of KP and Admissible Sets An admissible set is a transitive set A satisfying the axioms of Kripke-Platek Set Theory

More information

A Logician s Toolbox

A Logician s Toolbox A Logician s Toolbox 461: An Introduction to Mathematical Logic Spring 2009 We recast/introduce notions which arise everywhere in mathematics. All proofs are left as exercises. 0 Notations from set theory

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Appendix to Basic cardinal arithmetic

Appendix to Basic cardinal arithmetic Appendix to Basic cardinal arithmetic Notations 1.1. (a) For sets a and b define a+ set b:={0} a {1} b. (b) Let a (set b) :={f f : b a}. (c) Let α,β On. Then α+ ord β, α ord β and α (ord β) denote respectively

More information

Introduction to Set Theory

Introduction to Set Theory Introduction to Set Theory George Voutsadakis 1 1 Mathematics and Computer Science Lake Superior State University LSSU Math 400 George Voutsadakis (LSSU) Set Theory June 2014 1 / 67 Outline 1 Ordinal Numbers

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017 Definition: A set A is finite if there exists a nonnegative integer c such that there exists a bijection from A

More information

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues. Math 310 Class Notes 6: Countability Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues. Theorem 1. Let I n := {k N : k n}. Let f : I n N be a one-toone function and let Im(f)

More information

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018 1 Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics June 19, 2018 Basics Numbers 2 We have: Relations (subsets on their domain) Ordered pairs: The ordered pair x, y is the set {{x, y}, {x}}. Cartesian products

More information

1 of 8 7/15/2009 3:43 PM Virtual Laboratories > 1. Foundations > 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 6. Cardinality Definitions and Preliminary Examples Suppose that S is a non-empty collection of sets. We define a relation

More information

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n 10. Algebraic closure Definition 10.1. Let K be a field. The algebraic closure of K, denoted K, is an algebraic field extension L/K such that every polynomial in K[x] splits in L. We say that K is algebraically

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}.

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}. CARDINALS II James T. Smith San Francisco State University These notes develop the part of cardinal arithmetic that depends on the axiom of choice. The first result is the comparability theorem: every

More information

A CRITERION FOR THE EXISTENCE OF TRANSVERSALS OF SET SYSTEMS

A CRITERION FOR THE EXISTENCE OF TRANSVERSALS OF SET SYSTEMS A CRITERION FOR THE EXISTENCE OF TRANSVERSALS OF SET SYSTEMS JERZY WOJCIECHOWSKI Abstract. Nash-Williams [6] formulated a condition that is necessary and sufficient for a countable family A = (A i ) i

More information

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS

INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS INFINITY: CARDINAL NUMBERS BJORN POONEN 1 Some terminology of set theory N := {0, 1, 2, 3, } Z := {, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, } Q := the set of rational numbers R := the set of real numbers C := the set of complex

More information

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets Introduction In this short article, we will describe some basic notions on cardinality of sets. Given two

More information

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Section 7.5: Cardinality Section 7: Cardinality In this section, we shall consider extend some of the ideas we have developed to infinite sets One interesting consequence of this discussion is that we shall see there are as many

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Trees and generic absoluteness

Trees and generic absoluteness in ZFC University of California, Irvine Logic in Southern California University of California, Los Angeles November 6, 03 in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches The method of forcing

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

This paper is also taken by Combined Studies Students. Optional Subject (i): Set Theory and Further Logic

This paper is also taken by Combined Studies Students. Optional Subject (i): Set Theory and Further Logic UNIVERSITY OF LONDON BA EXAMINATION for Internal Students This paper is also taken by Combined Studies Students PHILOSOPHY Optional Subject (i): Set Theory and Further Logic Answer THREE questions, at

More information

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS CAPSTONE MATT LUTHER 1 INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS 2 1. Introduction This paper will summarize many of the ideas from logic and set theory that are

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS MATH 109 - FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS Answer: Answer: 1. Cardinality (1) Let a < b be two real numbers and define f : (0, 1) (a, b) by f(t) = (1 t)a + tb. (a) Prove that f is a bijection. (b) Prove that any

More information

Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory

Math 280A Fall Axioms of Set Theory Math 280A Fall 2009 1. Axioms of Set Theory Let V be the collection of all sets and be a membership relation. We consider (V, ) as a mathematical structure. Analogy: A group is a mathematical structure

More information

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES NATHANIEL GALLUP 1. Introduction Number theory begins as the study of the natural numbers the integers N = {1, 2, 3,...}, Z = { 3, 2, 1, 0, 1, 2, 3,...}, and sometimes

More information

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma Any indexed family of sets A ={Ai: i I} may be conceived as a variable set, to wit, as a set varying over the index set I. Each Ai is then the value of the variable

More information

MATH 220C Set Theory

MATH 220C Set Theory MATH 220C Set Theory L A TEX by Kevin Matthews Spring 2017 (Updated January 7, 2018) Continuum Hypothesis Definition 0.0.1 (Same Cardinality). Two sets A, B have the same cardinality iff there is a bijection

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability

CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability CITS2211 Discrete Structures (2017) Cardinality and Countability Highlights What is cardinality? Is it the same as size? Types of cardinality and infinite sets Reading Sections 45 and 81 84 of Mathematics

More information

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties Near the end of Section V I.4 we listed several basic questions about transfinite cardinal numbers, and we shall restate them here for the sake of convenience:

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics October 15, 2018 2 Contents 1 Basic Set Theory 5 1.1 Basic Set Theory....................................... 5 1.1.1 Union and Intersection of Sets...........................

More information

Contents. Index... 15

Contents. Index... 15 Contents Filter Bases and Nets................................................................................ 5 Filter Bases and Ultrafilters: A Brief Overview.........................................................

More information

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System 21-355 Principles of Real Analysis I Fall 2004 I. The Real Number System The main goal of this course is to develop the theory of real-valued functions of one real variable in a systematic and rigorous

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

ORDER AND ARITHMETIC OF CARDINALITIES

ORDER AND ARITHMETIC OF CARDINALITIES ORDER AND ARITHMETIC OF CARDINALITIES PETE L. CLARK Here we pursue Cantor s theory of cardinalities of infinite sets a bit more deeply. We also begin to take a more sophisticated approach in that we identify

More information

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Zachary Mesyan March 11, 2018 Abstract The goal of this paper is to generalize the theory of triangularizing matrices to linear transformations of an arbitrary vector

More information

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS 3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS Definition 3.1 Let X be a topological space. A subset D of X is dense in X iff D = X. X is separable iff it contains a countable dense subset. X satisfies the first

More information

Souslin s Hypothesis

Souslin s Hypothesis Michiel Jespers Souslin s Hypothesis Bachelor thesis, August 15, 2013 Supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Mathematical Institute, Leiden University Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Trees 2 3 The -Principle 7 4 Martin

More information

The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox The Axiom of Choice and the Banach-Tarski Paradox Department of Mathematical Sciences Lakehead University March 2011 The Axiom of Choice Axiom of Choice (Suppes 1960) For any set A there is a function

More information

On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers

On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers IOSR Journal of Mathematics (IOSR-JM) e-issn: 2278-5728, p-issn: 2319-765X. Volume 14, Issue 4 Ver. IV (Jul - Aug 2018), PP 17-21 www.iosrjournals.org On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers J N Salunke* and B

More information

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW

SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW SETS AND FUNCTIONS JOSHUA BALLEW 1. Sets As a review, we begin by considering a naive look at set theory. For our purposes, we define a set as a collection of objects. Except for certain sets like N, Z,

More information

Finite and Infinite Sets

Finite and Infinite Sets Chapter 9 Finite and Infinite Sets 9. Finite Sets Preview Activity (Equivalent Sets, Part ). Let A and B be sets and let f be a function from A to B..f W A! B/. Carefully complete each of the following

More information

Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal),

Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal), 3. Cardinal Numbers Cardinality Two sets X, Y have the same cardinality (cardinal number, cardinal), (3.1) X = Y, if there exists a one-to-one mapping of X onto Y. The relation (3.1) is an equivalence

More information

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY About the Class Evaluation. Final grade will be based 25%, 25%, 25%, 25%, on homework, midterm 1, midterm 2, final exam. Exam dates. Midterm 1: Oct 4. Midterm 2:

More information

The cardinal comparison of sets

The cardinal comparison of sets (B) The cardinal comparison of sets I think we can agree that there is some kind of fundamental difference between finite sets and infinite sets. For a finite set we can count its members and so give it

More information

S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions

S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions You can find solutions to some of these problems on the next page. These questions only pertain to material covered since Exam 2. The final exam is cumulative, so you

More information

Foundations of Mathematics

Foundations of Mathematics Foundations of Mathematics L. Pedro Poitevin 1. Preliminaries 1.1. Sets We will naively think of a set as a collection of mathematical objects, called its elements or members. To indicate that an object

More information

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6 The Axiom of Choice Contents 1 Motivation 2 2 The Axiom of Choice 2 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4 4 Zorn s Lemma 5 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6 6 More equivalences of AC 11 7 Consequences of the Axiom of

More information

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf)

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf) PAYNE, CATHERINE ANN, M.A. On ψ (κ, M) spaces with κ = ω 1. (2010) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 30pp. S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the natural numbers together with

More information

FORCING SUMMER SCHOOL LECTURE NOTES

FORCING SUMMER SCHOOL LECTURE NOTES FORCING SUMMER SCHOOL LECTURE NOTES SPENCER UNGER Abstract. These are the lecture notes for the forcing class in the 2014 UCLA Logic Summer School. They are a revision of the 2013 Summer School notes.

More information

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality. These are two series of problems with specific goals: the first goal is to prove that the cardinality of the set of irrational numbers is continuum, and the second

More information

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6

MAGIC Set theory. lecture 6 MAGIC Set theory lecture 6 David Asperó Delivered by Jonathan Kirby University of East Anglia 19 November 2014 Recall: We defined (V : 2 Ord) by recursion on Ord: V 0 = ; V +1 = P(V ) V = S {V : < } if

More information

EXCLUDING SUBDIVISIONS OF INFINITE CLIQUES. Neil Robertson* Department of Mathematics Ohio State University 231 W. 18th Ave. Columbus, Ohio 43210, USA

EXCLUDING SUBDIVISIONS OF INFINITE CLIQUES. Neil Robertson* Department of Mathematics Ohio State University 231 W. 18th Ave. Columbus, Ohio 43210, USA EXCLUDING SUBDIVISIONS OF INFINITE CLIQUES Neil Robertson* Department of Mathematics Ohio State University 231 W. 18th Ave. Columbus, Ohio 43210, USA P. D. Seymour Bellcore 445 South St. Morristown, New

More information

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms Elizabeth Lauri 1 Introduction Faculty Mentor: David Fernandez Breton Forcing is a technique that was discovered by Cohen in the mid 20th century, and it is particularly

More information

USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE

USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE USING ULTRAPOWERS TO CHARACTERIZE ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCE MIKAYLA KELLEY Abstract. This paper will establish that ultrapowers can be used to determine whether or not two models have the same theory. More

More information

Zangwill s Global Convergence Theorem

Zangwill s Global Convergence Theorem Zangwill s Global Convergence Theorem A theory of global convergence has been given by Zangwill 1. This theory involves the notion of a set-valued mapping, or point-to-set mapping. Definition 1.1 Given

More information

Chapter 2 Axiomatic Set Theory

Chapter 2 Axiomatic Set Theory Chapter 2 Axiomatic Set Theory Ernst Zermelo (1871 1953) was the first to find an axiomatization of set theory, and it was later expanded by Abraham Fraenkel (1891 1965). 2.1 Zermelo Fraenkel Set Theory

More information

PMA603: Set Theory by P. G. Dixon

PMA603: Set Theory by P. G. Dixon PMA603: Set Theory 1998-99 by P. G. Dixon Contents Page 1 Introduction.......................................................................... 1 2 The axioms of Zermelo Fraenkel set theory...........................................

More information

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory?

Axiomatic set theory. Chapter Why axiomatic set theory? Chapter 1 Axiomatic set theory 1.1 Why axiomatic set theory? Essentially all mathematical theories deal with sets in one way or another. In most cases, however, the use of set theory is limited to its

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 125 Chapter 5. Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 5.1. Semilattices and lattices. Many of the partially ordered sets P we have seen have a further valuable property: that for any two

More information

Review of Linear Algebra

Review of Linear Algebra Review of Linear Algebra Throughout these notes, F denotes a field (often called the scalars in this context). 1 Definition of a vector space Definition 1.1. A F -vector space or simply a vector space

More information

Cantor and sets: La diagonale du fou

Cantor and sets: La diagonale du fou Judicaël Courant 2011-06-17 Lycée du Parc (moving to Lycée La Martinière-Monplaisir) Outline 1 Cantor s paradise 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Countable sets 1.3 R is not countable 1.4 Comparing sets 1.5 Cardinals

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

A topological set theory implied by ZF and GPK +

A topological set theory implied by ZF and GPK + 1 42 ISSN 1759-9008 1 A topological set theory implied by ZF and GPK + ANDREAS FACKLER Abstract: We present a system of axioms motivated by a topological intuition: The set of subsets of any set is a topology

More information

Filters in Analysis and Topology

Filters in Analysis and Topology Filters in Analysis and Topology David MacIver July 1, 2004 Abstract The study of filters is a very natural way to talk about convergence in an arbitrary topological space, and carries over nicely into

More information

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe: Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe: Ultimate L W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University IMS Graduate Summer School in Logic June 2018 Ordinals: the transfinite numbers is the smallest ordinal: this is

More information

CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS

CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS CHAPTER II THE HAHN-BANACH EXTENSION THEOREMS AND EXISTENCE OF LINEAR FUNCTIONALS In this chapter we deal with the problem of extending a linear functional on a subspace Y to a linear functional on the

More information

GENERAL TOPOLOGY JESPER M. MØLLER

GENERAL TOPOLOGY JESPER M. MØLLER GENERAL TOPOLOGY JESPER M. MØLLER Contents 1. Sets, functions and relations 3 1.1. Sets 3 1.2. Functions 3 1.5. Relations 4 2. The integers and the real numbers 7 3. Products and coproducts 9 4. Finite

More information

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University January 9, 2017 V : The Universe of Sets The power set Suppose X is a set. The powerset of X

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

Introduction to Proofs

Introduction to Proofs Introduction to Proofs Notes by Dr. Lynne H. Walling and Dr. Steffi Zegowitz September 018 The Introduction to Proofs course is organised into the following nine sections. 1. Introduction: sets and functions

More information

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. This paper attempts to serve as an introduction to abstract model theory. We introduce the notion of abstract logics, explore first-order logic as an instance

More information

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY VICTOR ZHANG Abstract. We demonstrate how several problems of algebraic geometry, i.e. Ax-Grothendieck, Hilbert s Nullstellensatz, Noether- Ostrowski, and Hilbert s

More information