A Nucleolus for Stochastic Cooperative Games

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A Nucleolus for Stochastic Cooperative Games"

Transcription

1 A Nucleolus for Stochastic Cooperative Games JEROEN SUIJS 1 Abstract This paper extends the definition of the nucleolus to stochastic cooperative games, that is, to cooperative games with random payoffs to the coalitions. It is shown that the nucleolus is nonempty and that it belongs to the core whenever the core is nonempty. Furthermore, it is shown for a particular class of stochastic cooperative games that the nucleolus can be determined by calculating the traditional nucleolus introduced by Schmeidler (1969) of a specific deterministic cooperative game. KEYWORDS: Nucleolus, cooperative game theory, random variables, preferences. 1 Department of Econometrics and CentER, Tilburg University, PO Box 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands

2 2 1 Introduction In stochastic cooperative games, the payoffs individuals can obtain by cooperating with each other are random variables instead of deterministic amounts. Moreover, the players are not allowed to await the realizations of these payoffs before they decide upon an allocation of these payoffs. These kinds of cooperative games fall outside the scope of traditional (deterministic) cooperative game theory. Models that can deal with such situations were introduced by Charnes and Granot (1973) and, more recently, by Suijs, Borm, De Waegenaere and Tijs (1995). The major difference between these two models is that the first model assumes risk neutral behaviour of all the players while the latter model incorporates risk neutral as well as risk averse and risk loving behaviour of the players. This paper introduces a nucleolus for the games introduced by Suijs et al. (1995). The nucleolus, a solution concept for deterministic cooperative games, originates from Schmeidler (1969). This solution concept yields an allocation such that the maximal excess of the coalitions is minimized. The excess describes how dissatisfied a coalition is with the proposed allocation. The larger the excess of a particular allocation, the more a coalition is dissatisfied with this allocation. For Schmeidler s nucleolus the excess is defined as the difference between the payoff a coalition can obtain when cooperating on its own and the payoff received by the proposed allocation. So, when less is allocated to a coalition, the excess of this coalition increases and the other way around. Since the nucleolus depends mainly on the definition of the excess, other nucleoli are found when different definitions of excesses are used. Such a general approach can be found in Potters and Tijs (1992). They introduced the general nucleolus as the solution that minimizes the maximal excess of the coalitions, using generally defined excess functions. A similar argument holds for stochastic cooperative games. If we can specify the excesses we can define a nucleolus for these games. Unfortunately, this is not that simple. Defining excess functions for stochastic cooperative games appears to be not as straightforward as for deterministic cooperative games. Indeed, how should one quantify the difference between the random payoff a coalition can achieve on its own and the random payoff received by the proposed allocation when the behaviour towards risk can differ

3 3 between the members of this coalition? Furthermore, the excess of one coalition should be comparable to the excess of another coalition. Charnes and Granot (1976) introduced a nucleolus for cooperative games in stochastic characteristic function form. There, the excess was based on the probability that the payoff a coalition can obtain when cooperating on its own, exceeds the payoff they obtained in the proposed allocation. Indeed, it is quite reasonable to assume that a coalition is less satisfied with the proposed allocation if this probability increases. For the excess defined in this paper we interpret the excess of Schmeidler s nucleolus in a slightly different way. Bearing the conditions of the core in mind, this excess can be interpreted as follows. Given an allocation of the grand coalition s payoff we distinguish two cases. In the first case, a coalition wants to leave the grand coalition. Then the excess equals the minimal amount of money a coalition needs on top of what they already get such that this coalition is willing to stay in the grand coalition. In the second case, a coalition has no incentive to leave the grand coalition. Then the excess equals minus the maximal amount of money that can be taken away from this coalition such that this coalition still has no incentive to leave the grand coalition. This interpretation is used to define the excess for stochastic cooperative games. The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 consists mainly of preliminaries. It briefly recalls the definition of a cooperative game with stochastic payoffs. Furthermore it states the assumptions we make on the preferences of the players and it introduces the necessary definitions and notations. Then in Section 3 the excess functions are introduced and, subsequently, a nucleolus. Moreover, it is shown that this nucleolus is a well defined solution concept in the sense that it always yields a nonempty subset of allocations. Section 4 shows that the nucleolus is a subset of the core whenever the core is nonempty. Moreover, it shows that for the class of stochastic cooperative games introduced in Suijs and Borm (1996) the nucleolus can be determined by calculating Schmeidler s nucleolus of a specific deterministic cooperative game.

4 2 Stochastic cooperative games 4 A stochastic cooperative game is described by a tuple Γ=(N, (X S ) S N, ( i ) i N ). Here, the set of players is denoted by N. The payoff a coalition S N can achieve by cooperating is denoted by a random variable X S. So, there is a probability space (Ω, H, IP) such that for each S N the payoff function X S : Ω IR is measurable, that is, XS 1 (B) Hforeach element B of R, the Borel σ-algebra. Since coalitions are not allowed to await the realization of X S before they decide on the allocation, the random payoff X S has to be allocated. An allocation of the random payoff X S among the members of S is described by a pair (d, r) H S S,whereH S ={d IR S i S d i 0} and S = {r IR S i S : r i 0, i S r i =1}. The random payoff to player i S then equals d i +r i X S.So,rallocates fractions of the random payoff X S to the members of S and d denotes the transfer payments. Note that these transfer payments need not be efficient. Moreover, it should be noted that for notational reasons the definition of an allocation used in this paper differs from its original definition in Suijs et al. (1995). Originally, d was an allocation of the expected payoff E(X S ) and r was an allocation of the residual payoff X S E(X S ). Finally, note that the random payoff d i + r i X S to player i S is measurable with respect to the probability space (Ω, H, IP). Next, define L(Γ) = {d + rx S d IR,r [0, 1],S N}. (1) Then L(Γ) is the set of all random payoffs player i N can receive in the game Γ. Finally, i are the complete and transitive preferences of player i over the set L(Γ). Examples of situations where this model may apply appear in insurance. Individuals facing losses that can occur to them in the future have to decide now if they want an insurance for these losses or not and, if so, which premium they want to pay for it. Furthermore, groups of individuals may benefit from taking a collective insurance instead of many individual ones. Another example appears when considering linear production games with random prices. Here, a coalition has to decide which goods to produce given the resources they posses without exactly knowing the revenues that are generated by these goods.

5 5 In the remainder of this paragraph we go through some necessary preliminaries. Therefore, consider again the set L(Γ). Denote by F X the distribution function of the random variable X L(Γ). Thus, F X (t) =IP({ω X(ω) t})for all t IR. Next, define F(Γ) = {F X X L(Γ)} to be the set of distribution functions corresponding to the random payoffs in L(Γ). Now, let (F k ) k IN be a sequence in F(Γ). Then the sequence (F k ) k IN weakly converges to F F(Γ), denoted by F w k F,iflim k F k (t) =F(t) for all t {t IR F is continuous in t }. Subsequently, we say that a sequence (X k ) k IN of random variables converges to the random variable X if and only if the corresponding sequence (F k ) k IN of probability distribution functions weakly converges to the probability distributionfunction F of X. Furthermore, let (F(Γ),ρ)be a metric space with ρ(f, G) = F (t) G(t) e t dt for all F, G F(Γ). The following two results can be found in Feller (1950) and Feller (1966). Proposition 2.1 F k w F if and only if lim k ρ(f k,f)=0. Proposition 2.2 Let (d k ) k IN and (r k ) k IN be convergent sequences in IR with limits d and r, respectively. Take X L(Γ). Denote by F the distribution function of d + rx and by F k the distribution function of d k + r k X for all k IN. Then F w k F. This proposition has the following implication which will be frequently used in the remainder of this paper. Let a subset O F(Γ) be called open if for each F O there exists ε>0such that {G F(Γ) ρ(f, G) <ε} O. Furthermore, let (d k ) k IN and (r k ) k IN be convergent sequences in IR with limits d and r, respectively. Take X L(Γ) and denote by F and F k the distribution function of d + rx and d k + r k X, respectively. Next, let O F(Γ) be an open set such that F O. Proposition 2.2 and the definition of an open subset then imply that there exists k 0 such that F k O for all k>k 0.

6 6 For the introduction of a nucleolus we focus on cooperative games with stochastic payoffs Γ=(N, (X S ) S N, ( i ) i N ) where the preferences of each player satisfy the following additional conditions: (C1) continuity, i.e., {F X F(Γ) X i Y } and {F X F(Γ) X i Y } are closed sets in (F(Γ),ρ)for all Y L(Γ), 12 (C2) for any X, Y L(Γ) there exist d, d IR such that X + d i Y i X + d, (C3) for all X L(Γ) and all d>0we have that X + d i X. Example 2.3 Let the preferences αi with α i (0, 1) be such that X αi Y if and only if u X α i := sup{t F X (t) <α i } u Y α i := sup{t F Y (t) <α i },whereu X α i denotes the α i - quantile of X. This type of preferences may appear in insurance problems. They are used by insurance companies if the premium is determined on the basis of the percentile principle. This type of preferences satisfies conditions (C1) - (C3). To see this, note that u d i+r i X α i = d i + r i u X α i. Then, it is clear that αi satisfies (C2) and (C3). For continuity, take Y L(Γ). We have to show that the set {X L(Γ) X αi Y } is a closed set. Therefore, let (d k i + ri k X) k IN be a convergent sequence in {X L(Γ) X αi Y } and denote its limit by X. So, d k i+ riu k X α i u Y α i for all k IN. It is sufficient to show that X αi Y, i.e., u X αi u Y α i. Since the sequence converges we know from Lemma A.3 in Appendix A that there exist convergent subsequences (d l i ) l IN and (ri l) l IN with limits d i and r i, respectively, such that d i + r i X = X. Since d l i+ rix l αi Y implies d l i + riu l X α i u Y α i it follows that d i + r i u X α i u Y α i. Consequently, we have that u X αi u Y α i. 1 Since the preferences are complete, an equivalent statement is that {F X F(Γ) X i Y } and {F X F(Γ) X i Y } are open sets in (F(Γ),ρ)for all Y L(Γ). 2 For ease of notation, the sets {F X F(Γ) X i Y } and {F X F(Γ) X i Y } are often denoted by {X L(Γ) X i Y } and {X L(Γ) X i Y }, respectively.

7 7 Example 2.4 Let b i with b i IR describe the following preferences. For X, Y L(Γ) it holds that X b i Y if E(X) +b i V(X) E(Y)+bi V(Y),whereEdenotes the expectation and V the variance. This type of preferences can be found for example in portfolio decision theory, where an agent s evaluation of a portfolio depends on the expected revenue of the portfolio and the standard deviation of the revenue. These preferences satisfy conditions (C1) - (C3). To see this, note that E(d i + r i X)+b i V(d i +r i X)=d i +r i E(X)+b i r i V(X) holds for d i IR and r i [0, 1]. Then the same arguments as in Example 2.3 can be used to show that b i satisfies conditions (C1) - (C3). Example 2.5 Let i describe the preferences of an expected utility maximizing player. So, X i Y if E(u i (X)) E(u i (Y )), whereedenotes the expectation and u i is the monotonically increasing utility function of player i. These preferences satisfy conditions (C1)-(C3)ifforallS Neither X S 0 or X S 0. So, the random payoff of a coalition cannot have both positive and negative realizations. From the fact that u i is increasing it follows that (C2) and (C3) are satisfied. For the continuity condition (C1) we refer to Lemma A.4 in Appendix A. In order to define a nucleolus one needs to specify for each coalition S N an excess function E S. The excess function assigns to each allocation (d, r) of the grand coalition N a real number representing the complaint of coalition S. The larger the complaint of a coalition the more this coalition is dissatisfied with the proposed allocation. For the excess function introduced in this paper we need the following notation. Define I S (Γ) = {(d, r) IR S R S i S : d i + r i X S i X {i} }, as the set of possibly nonfeasible individually rational allocations for coalition S. Here, an allocation (d, r) I S (Γ) is called feasible if i S d i 0. Furthermore, define IR S (Γ) = {(d, r) I S (Γ) d i 0}, i S

8 8 as the set of feasible individually rational allocations for coalition S and PO S (Γ) = {(d, r) IR S (Γ) (d,r ) IR S (Γ) i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X S }, as the set of feasible Pareto optimal allocations for S. Note that assumption (C3) implies that i S d i =0whenever (d, r) PO S (Γ). Finally, we make another assumption, namely, (C4) I S (Γ) for all S N. Note that this assumption is satisfied if Γ is superadditive 3. Moreover, it should be noted that a coalition S is unlikely to be formed when I S (Γ) =. Since in that case for every allocation of X S there is at least one member of S whose payoff is not individually rational. Hence, he would be better off by leaving coalition S and form a coalition on his own. Finally, denote by CG(N) the class of all cooperative games with stochastic payoffs with player set N satisfying conditions (C1) - (C4). For gaining a clearer insight into the situation and the (forthcoming) mathematics in particular, we make use of a simplified graphical representation of the problem. At the moment this might seem a bit overdone, but for the remainder of this paper these figures might turn out to be very helpful. The notions introduced in the preceding paragraph are illustrated in Figure 1. Figure 1 represents a cooperative game with stochastic payoffs with two expected utility maximizing players. The axes represent the utility levels of the players. For simplicity, we have assumed that payoffs are individually rational if and only if the corresponding expected utility is greater than or equal to zero. So, the set I S (Γ) is represented by the positive orthant. Furthermore, the set IR S (Γ) of individually rational allocations is depicted by the shaded area, and the set PO S (Γ) of Pareto optimal allocations is depicted by the 3 AgameΓ=(N, (X S ) S N, ( i ) i N ) is called superadditive if for all disjunct S, T N the following statement is true. For each allocation (d S,r S ) of X S and each allocation (d T,r T ) of X T there exists an allocation (d, r) of X S T such that d i +r i X S T i d S i +ri S X S for all i S and d i +r i X S T i d T i +ri T X S for all i T. So whatever the allocation of X S and X T are, there is always an allocation of X S T such that all members of S T are (weakly) better off.

9 9 u 2 I S( Γ) PO S( Γ) IR S( Γ) 0 u1 FIGURE 1: Individually rational and Pareto optimal allocations in a two-player example. bold printed curve. Finally, note that this and the forthcoming figures do not arise from a concrete example. In Figure 1 both IR S (Γ) and PO S (Γ) are compact subsets. The following propositions show that this holds in general for the class CG(N) of cooperative games with stochastic payoffs. Proposition 2.6 IR S (Γ) is a compact subset of I S (Γ) for each coalition S N. PROOF: See Appendix B. 2 Proposition 2.7 The set of Pareto optimal allocations PO S (Γ) is a compact subset of I S (Γ) for each coalition S N. PROOF: See Appendix B. 2

10 10 Furthermore, we need to consider the following sets. Define for each S N PD S (Γ) = {(d, r) I S (Γ) (d,r ) PO S (Γ) i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X} as the set of (possibly nonfeasible) allocations that are (weakly) dominated by a Pareto optimal allocation, and NPD S (Γ) = {(d, r) I S (Γ) (d,r ) PO S (Γ) i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X} as the set of (possibly nonfeasible) allocations that are not dominated by Pareto optimal allocations. Note that IR S (Γ) PD S (Γ). The reverse, however, need not be true, as the next example shows. Example 2.8 Consider the following two player example. Let X S be such that X S is exponentially distributed with expectation equal to 1 for all S N. Furthermore let players 1 and 2 be expected utility maximizers with utility functions u 1 (t) = e 0.5t and u 2 (t) = e 0.25t, respectively. Then E(u 1 (d 1 + r 1 X {1,2} )) = e d r 1 and E(u 2 (d 2 r 2 X {1,2} )) = e d r 2. An allocation (d, r) I {1,2} (Γ) is individually rational if E(u 1 (d 1 + r 1 X {1,2} )) 2and E(u 2 (d 2 + r 2 X {1,2} )) Furthermore, (d, r ) is Pareto optimal if and only if r1 = 1 and 3 r 2 = 2 (see Wilson (1968)). Now, consider the 3 allocation (d, r) with d 1 =0.1,d 2 =0.1,r 1 =1and r 2 =0. Since d 1 + d 2 > 0 this allocation is nonfeasible. However, the Pareto optimal allocation (d,r )with d 1 = 0.9, d 2 =0.9,r 1 =1 and 3 r 2 = 2 is feasible and preferred by both players. Indeed, 3 and E(u 1 (d 1 + r 1 X {1,2})) = > = E(u 1 (d 1 + r 1 X {1,2} )) E(u 2 (d 2 + r 2X {1,2} )) = > = E(u 2 (d 2 + r 2 X {1,2} )). So even nonfeasible allocations can be Pareto dominated. The next proposition states a very intuitive result. Namely that for every Pareto dominated allocation (d, r) and every non-pareto dominated allocation (d,r ), which all members

11 11 of S weakly prefer to the Pareto dominated allocation (d, r), there exists a Pareto optimal allocation such that for each player the Pareto optimal allocation is weakly better than (d, r) but weakly worse than (d,r ). Proposition 2.9 Let Γ CG(N). Take (d, r) PD S (Γ) and ( d, r) NPD S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i di + r i X S for all i S. Then there exists ( ˆd, ˆr) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i ˆdi +ˆr i X S i di + r i X S for all i S. PROOF: See Appendix B. 2 A direct consequence of this proposition is that for each allocation (d, r) IR S (Γ) there exists a Pareto optimal allocation (d,r ) such that d i + r i X S i d i + r i X S for all i S. Moreover, since I S (Γ) is nonempty by assumption (C4) we have that for each (d, r) NPD S (Γ) there exists (d,r ) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r ix S i d i + r i X S for all i S. Finally, we introduce three more sets. Therefore, let (d, r) IR N (Γ) be an individually rational allocation for the grand coalition N. TakeS Nand define W S ((d, r)) = {(d,r ) IR S (Γ) i S : d i + r i X S i d i + r i X N } as the set of individually rational allocations for coalitions S which are weakly worse than the payoff d i + r i X N for every member of S, and, B S ((d, r)) = {(d,r ) IR S (Γ) i S : d i + r i X S i d i + r i X N } as the set of individually rational allocations for coalition S which are weakly better than the payoff d i + r i X N for every member of S. Furthermore, define POS((d, r)) = (W S ((d, r)) B S ((d, r))) PO S (Γ), as the set of Pareto optimal allocations for coalition S which are either weakly worse than d i + r i X N for all members of S or weakly better than d i + r i X N for all members of S. These three sets are illustrated in Figure 2. Note that B S ((d, r)) can be empty.

12 12 u 2 2 u (d,r) PO *((d,r)) S PO *((d,r)) S (d,r) B ((d,r)) S W ((d,r)) S W ((d,r)) S u u FIGURE 2: Examples of W S ((d, r)), B S ((d, r)) and PO S((d, r)). 3 A nucleolus for stochastic cooperative games With the definitions and notions introduced in the previous section we can now define an excess function and, consequently, a nucleolus for cooperative games with stochastic payoffs. The excess function E S : IR N (Γ) IR of coaltition S is defined as follows. Take (d, r) IR N (Γ). Then the excess for coalition S is defined by E S ((d, r)) = min (d,r ) POS ((d,r)){ δ i i S : δ i IR and d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N + δ i }. i S For an interpretation of the excess, let us focus on the core conditions. So, given a proposed allocation (d, r) does a coalition S have an incentive to leave the grand coalition or not. First, consider again the excess as used in Schmeidler (1969). There, the excess can be interpeted as the minimum amount of money a coalition needs on top of what they already receive from the proposed allocation such that they are indifferent between staying in the grand coalition and leaving the grand coalition. This interpretation is now applied to stochastic cooperative games. For this, note that given an allocation (d, r) IR N (Γ) a coalition S is indifferent between staying in the grand coalition N and leaving if there exists an allocation (d,r ) POS((d, r)) such that each player i S is indifferent between

13 13 receiving the payoff d i + r ix S and the payoff d i + r i X N. So, coalition cannot do strictly better by leaving the grand coalition but if they do split off they can allocate their payoff in such a way that no member is strictly worse off. Now, suppose that a coalition S has an incentive to part company with the grand coalition N. So, there exists an allocation ( d, r) IR S (Γ) such that each player i S strictly prefers the payoff d i + r i X S to the payoff d i + r i X N. To keep this coalition in the grand coalition the payoff to the members of S must increase. This can be done by giving each member i S a deterministic amount of money δ i. Hence, their payoff becomes d i + δ i + r i X N. The excess of coalition S then equals the minimal amount of money they need so that they are just willing to stay in the grand coalition. Next, suppose that a coalition S does not have an incentive to split off from the grand coalition. Hence, this coalition receives more than they can achieve on their own. Consequently, one can decrease the payoff of each member i S with a deterministic amount δ i. Then the excess equals the maximal amount of money that can be taken away from this coalition such that they are still staying in the grand coalition. Summarizing, the excess E S ((d, r)) represents the minimum amount of money that coalition S needs in order to be satisfied with the allocation (d, r). Moreover, if (d, r) and (d,r )are allocations of X N such that each player i S prefers d i +r i X N to d i+r ix N then E S ((d, r)) <E S ((d,r )). Hence, the excess decreases when each player i S improves his payoff. So, in a specific way the excess E S ((d, r)) describes how much coalition S is satisfied with the allocation (d, r). Finally, since all players preferences are monotonically increasing in the amount of money d they receive (see assumption (C3)) it is reasonable to say that one coalition is more satisfied with a particular allocation than another coalition if the first coalition needs less money to be satisfied than the latter one, or, in other words, if the excess of the first coalition is less than the excess of the latter. This last observation leads to the following definition of a nucleolus. Let Γ=(N, (X S ) S N, ( i ) i N ) be a cooperative game with stochastic payoffs and let E S ((d, r)) = min (d,r ) POS ((d,r)){ δ i i S :(d,r ) i i (d, r) i + δ i }. (2) i S

14 14 describe the excess of coalition S at allocation (d, r) IR N (Γ). Next, denote by E((d, r)) the vector of excesses at allocation (d, r) and let θ E((d, r)) denote the vector of excesses ordered in a decreasing order. The nucleolus N (Γ) of the game Γ CG(N) is then defined by N (Γ) = {(d, r) IR N (Γ) (d,r ) IR N (Γ) : θ E((d, r)) lex θ E((d,r ))}, (3) where lex is the lexicographic ordering. Next, we show that the nucleolus is a well defined solution concept for the games discussed in this paper. In proving the nonemptiness of the nucleolus N (Γ) we make use of the results stated in Maschler, Potters and Tijs (1992). They introduced a nucleolus for a more a general framework and showed that the nucleolus is nonempty if the domain is compact and the excess functions are continuous. Thus, we have to show that IR N (Γ) is compact and that E S ((d, r)) is continuous in (d, r) for each (d, r) IR N (Γ) and each S N. The compactness of IR N (Γ) follows immediately from Proposition 2.6. The continuity proof is a bit more complicated and consists of the following parts. First we show that POS((d, r)) is a nonempty compact subset of PO S (Γ). Then we introduce the following multifunction E S ((d, r)) = { δ i (d,r ) POS ((d,r)) : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N + δ i }. i S Hence, E S ((d, r)) = min E S ((d, r)). In the next step we show that E S ((d, r)) is a compact subset of IR for each allocation (d, r) IR N (Γ). This implies that the minimum in (2) exists. Subsequently, we show that this multifunction is both upper and lower semi continuous, which then implies that the excess function E S is continuous. Proposition 3.1 PO S((d, r)) is a nonempty compact subset of PO S (Γ). PROOF: That POS((d, r)) is compact follows from the facts that W S ((d, r)) and B S ((d, r)) are closed by the continuity condition (C1) and PO S (Γ) is compact. To show that it is nonempty let us distinguish two cases.

15 15 First, let B S ((d, r)). Then there exists (d,r ) IR S (Γ) such that d i +r ix S i d i + r i X S for all i S. Since(d,r ) IR S (Γ) we know from Proposition 2.9 that there exists ( d, r) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i d i+r ix S for all i S. Hence, ( d, r) PO S (Γ) and ( d, r) B S ((d, r)). Consequently, ( d, r) POS((d, r)). Second, let B S ((d, r)) =. Take( d, r) I S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i d i +r i X N for all i S. FromB S ((d, r)) = it follows that ( d, r) NPD S (Γ). Proposition 2.9 then implies that there exists ( d, r) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i di + r i X S for all i S. Hence, ( d, r) W S ((d, r)) and, consequently, ( d, r) POS((d, r)). 2 Next, consider again the multifunction E S : IR N (Γ) IR defined by E S ((d, r)) = { i S δ i (d,r ) PO S ((d,r)) : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N + δ i }. Proposition 3.2 Let (d, r) IR N (Γ). Then E S ((d, r)) is a compact subset of IR. P ROOF: We have to show that E S ((d, r)) is closed and bounded. That E S ((d, r)) is bounded follows from the compactness of POS((d, r)) and the fact that for each (d,r ) POS((d, r)) the number δ i is uniquely determined by conditions (C1) - (C2). To see that E S ((d, r)) is closed, let ( i S δi k ) k IN be a convergent sequence 4 in E S ((d, r)) with limit i S δ i. We have to show that i S δ i E S ((d, r)). Therefore, let (( d k, r k )) k IN be a sequence in POS((d, r)) such that d k i + r ix k S i d i +δi k +r i X N for all i S. Since POS((d, r)) is compact there exists a convergent subsequence (( d l, r l )) l IN with limit ( d, r) POS ((d, r)). Take δ i IR such that d i + r i X S i d i + δ i +r i X N for all i S. Note that δ i S i E S ((d, r)). The proof is finished if we can show that δ i = δ i for all i S. Therefore, let ε>0and i S. Define V ε i ={Y L(Γ) d i + r i X S ε i Y i di + r i X S +ε}. 4 Formally, it would be more correct to start with a convergent sequence (a k ) k N in E S ((d, r)). Then a k E S ((d, r)) and the definition of E S imply that there exist δ k i such that d i + δ k i + r ix N i d i + r i X S (i S) forsome(d,r ) POS ((d, r)) and i S δk i = a k. Consequently, the sequence (a k ) k IN can be replaced by a sequence ( i S δk i ) k IN.

16 16 Since V ε i is open by the continuity of i, ( d l, r l ) ( d, r) and d i + r i X S V ε i L ε IN such that d l i + rl i X S V ε i there exists for all l>l ε. This implies that d i + δ l i + r ix N V ε i for all l>l ε.sinceε>0was arbitrarily chosen it follows that ( ) lim di + δi l + rix l N = di + δ i + r i X N ε>0 Vi ε. l Hence, d i + δ i + r i X N i di + r i X S. Since by definition it holds that d i + r i X S i d i + δ i +r i X N it follows by assumption (C3) that δ i = δ i. 2 Lemma 3.3 E S ((d, r)) is upper semi continuous in (d, r) for all (d, r) IR N (Γ). PROOF: Let((d k,r k )) k IN be a sequence in IR N (Γ) converging to (d, r). Take i Sδi k E S ((d k,r k )) such that i S δi k converges to i S δ i. For upper semi continuity to be satisfied it is sufficient to show that i S δ i E S ((d, r)). First, take ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )) such that d k i + r ix k S i d k i +δi k +rix k N for all i S. Since (( d k, r k )) k IN is a sequence in the compact set PO S (Γ) there exists a convergent subsequence (( d l, r l )) l IN with limit ( d, r) PO S (Γ). Moreover, it holds that d i + r i X S i d i +δ i +r i X N for all i S. To see this, take ε>0and i S. Define V ε i Since V ε i ={Y L(Γ) d i + r i X S ε i Y i di + r i X S +ε}. is open by the continuity of i, ( d l, r l ) ( d, r) and d i + r i X S V ε i L ε IN such that d l i + rl i X S V ε i there exists for all l>l ε. This implies that d l i + δl i + rl i X N V ε i for all l>l ε.sinceε>0is arbitrary we have that ( ) lim d l i + δi l + rix l N = di + δ i + r i X N i di + r i X S. l The proof is finished if we can show that ( d, r) POS((d, r)). Therefore, take ε>0 and define W ε S((d, r)) = {(d,r ) IR S (Γ) i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N + ε}, B ε S((d, r)) = {(d,r ) IR S (Γ) i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N ε}, PO ε S ((d, r)) = (W ε S((d, r)) B ε S((d, r))) PO S (Γ).

17 17 u 2 2 u ε S B ((d,r)) ε S PO * ((d,r)) PO *((d,r )) S l l (d,r) (d,r) B ((d,r )) S l l ε S W ((d,r)) W ((d,r )) u 0 0 S l l (d,r ) 1 1 l l u FIGURE 3: A graphical representation of PO ε S ((d, r)) and PO S((d l,r l )). We refer to the left figure of Figure 3 for a graphical interpretation of these sets. Note that W S ((d, r)) = ε>0 WS ε((d, r)), B S((d, r)) = ε>0 BS ε ((d, r)) and PO S ((d, r)) = ε>0 POS ε ((d, r)). Furthermore, define V ε = {Y L(Γ) S i S : d i + r i X N ε i Y i i d i + r i X N + ε}. Since V ε is open by the continuity of i, (d l,r l ) (d, r) and (d i + r i X N ) i S V ε there exists L ε IN such that (d l i + rl i X N) i S V ε for all l>l ε. This implies that (d l,r l ) WS((d, ε r)) and (d l,r l ) BS((d, ε r)) for all l>l ε (see also the right figure in Figure 3). Hence, W S ((d l,r l )) WS((d, ε r)) and B S ((d l,r l )) BS((d, ε r)) for all l>l ε. Consequently, we have for all l>l ε that POS ((dl,r l )) POS ε ((d, r)). In particular, we have ( d l, r l ) POS ε ((d, r)) for all l>l ε. Hence, lim ( d l, r l )=( d, r) ε>0 POS ε ((d, r)) = l PO S ((d, r)). 2 Lemma 3.4 E S ((d, r)) is lower semi continuous in (d, r) for all (d, r) IR N (Γ).

18 18 PROOF: Let((d k,r k )) k IN be a sequence converging to (d, r) and let i S δ i E S ((d, r)). To prove lower semi continuity it suffices to show that there exists a sequence ( i S δi k) k IN with i S δi k E S ((d k,r k )) for all k IN such that i S δi k converges to i S δ i. First, note that since IR N (Γ) is compact and E S is upper semi continuous that E S (IR N (Γ)) = (d,r) IRN (Γ)E S ((d, r)) is a compact subset of IR. Second, note that if there exists a sequence ( i S δ k i ) k IN with i S δi k E S ((d k,r k )) for each k IN such that every convergent subsequence ( i S δi) l l IN converges to i S δ i then the compactness of E S (IR N (Γ)) implies that the sequence ( i S δi k ) k IN converges to i S δ i. Take ( d, r) POS ((d, r)) such that d i + r i X S i d i +δ i +r i X N for all i S. Let ε>0and define V ε = Y L(Γ)S i S : Y i i di + r i X S εor i S : Y i i di + r i X S +ε, and C ε = Y L(Γ)S i S : Y i i di + r i X S εor i S : Y i i di + r i X S +ε. Note that V ε is open and C ε is closed by the continuity of i for each i S. Next, we show that if (d k i + ri k X N ) i S V ε then there exists ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )) such that ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V ε. Therefore, let k IN be such that (d k,r k ) V ε and let ( d, r) I S (Γ) be such that d i + r i X S i d k i +rix k N for all i S. We distinguish the following three cases. First, suppose that ( d, r) NPD S (Γ). Since ( d i + r i X S ) i S V ε it holds that d i + r i X S i di + r i X S εfor all i S. From ( d 1(ε,ε,...,ε), r) PD 2 S(Γ) and Proposition 2.9 it follows that there exists ( d k, r k ) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S 1 2 ε i dk i + r k ix S i di + r i X S for all i S. Thus, ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V ε.since d i + r i X S i d k i +rix k N for all i S it holds that ( d k, r k ) W S ((d k,r k )). Hence, ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )).

19 19 Second, suppose that ( d, r) PD S (Γ) and that d i + r i X S i di + r i X S +εfor all i S. Since the Pareto optimality of ( d, r) implies that ( d + 1(ε,ε,...,ε), r) NPD 2 S(Γ) it follows from Proposition 2.9 that there exists ( d k, r k ) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i dk i + r i k X S d i i + r i X S + 1ε 2 for all i S. Thus, ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V ε.since d i + r i X S i d k i +rix k N for all i S it holds that ( d k, r k ) B S ((d k,r k )). Hence, ( d k, r k ) POS ((dk,r k )). Finally, suppose that ( d, r) PD S (Γ) and that d i + r i X S i di + r i X S εfor all i S. Then Proposition 2.9 implies that there exists ( d k, r k ) PO S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S ε i di + r i X S i dk i + r k ix S for all i S. Thus, ( d k, r k ) B S ((d k,r k )). Therefore we have that ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )). Moreover, ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V ε. Now we are able to construct a sequence ( i S δi k) k IN with i S δi k POS ((dk,r k )) for each k IN such that each convergent subsequence converges to i S δ i. Let (ε m ) m IN be a strictly decreasing sequence such that ε m > 0 for all m IN and lim m ε m = 0. Hence, (V εm ) m IN is a decreasing sequence in the sense that V εm V εm if m>m.definev 0 = ε>0 V ε.from( d, r) POS ((d, r)) it follows that (d i + r i X N ) i S V 0. Hence, (d i + r i X N ) i S V ε for all ε>0.since(d k,r k )converges to (d, r) there exists K 1 IN such that for all k>k 1 it holds that (d k i + ri k X S ) i S V ε1. Next, take k IN. If k K 1 then take i S δi k E S ((d k,r k )) arbitrary. If k>k 1 we distinguish the following two cases. In the first case, suppose that (d k i + ri k X N ) i S V 0. Then ( d, r) POS((d k,r k )) and ( d i + r i X S ) i S V 0. So, we can take ( d k, r k ) equal to ( d, r) (See the left figure of Figure 4). In the second case, let (d k i + rk i X N) i S V 0. Then there exists m(k) IN such that (d k i + ri k X N ) i S V εm(k) \V εm(k)+1. Subsequently, take ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )) such that ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V εm(k) (See the right figure of Figure 4, where the bold printed curve represents the set of allocations that belong to both POS ((dk,r k )) and V εm(k) ). That

20 20 u 2 2 k k (d,r ) (d,r) u k k (d,r ) _ k _ k (d,r ) (d,r) (d k,r k)=(d,r ) (d,r ) u 0 0 V V 0 0 ε1 1 1 V V V V ε m(k)+1 ε m(k) ε1 u FIGURE 4: The choice of the allocation (d k,r k )for the two different cases. such ( d k, r k ) exists can be seen as follows. Let (d,r ) I S (Γ) be such that d i + r ix S i d k i + rk i X N for all i S. Then either (d,r ) PD S (Γ) or (d,r ) NPD S (Γ). For the case that (d,r ) PD S (Γ) then (d k i + ri k X N ) i S V εm(k) implies that (d i + r ix S ) i S V εm(k) and, consequently, that d i + r i X S d i i + r i X S ε m(k) for all i S or d i + r ix S i di + r i X S +ε m(k) for all i S. If the first statement is true then it follows from Proposition 2.9 that there exists ( d k, r k ) PO S (Γ) such that d k i + r ix k S i d i+r ix S for all i S. This implies that ( d k i + r i k X S ) i S V εm(k) and ( d k, r k ) POS((d k,r k )). If the second statement is true then it follows from (d,r ) PD S (Γ) and Proposition 2.9 that there exists ( d k, r k ) PO S (Γ) satisfying d k i + r k i X N i d i + r ix S i dk i + r k ix S i di + r i X S +ε m(k) for all i S. Hence, ( d k, r k ) PO S((d k,r k )) and ( d k i + r k ix S ) i S V εm(k).

21 21 For the case that (d,r ) NPD S (Γ) a similar argument holds. Next, let δi k be such that d k i + rk i X S i d k i +rk i X N +δi k for all i S. Note that for k>k 1 we have i S δi k E S ((d k,r k )) and ( d k i + r i k X S ) i S V 0 if (d k i +ri k X N ) i S V 0 and ( d k i + r ix k S ) i S V εm(k) if (d k i +ri k X N ) i S V 0.Since( i Sδi) k k IN is a sequence in the compact set E S (IR S (Γ)) there exists a convergent subsequence ( i S δi) l l IN with limit δ i S i. Corresponding to this convergent subsequence there is a sequence ( d l i + rl i X S) l IN such that ( d l i + r l ix S ) i S V 0 if (d l i + r l ix N ) i S V 0 and ( d l i + r l ix S ) i S V εm(l) if (d l i + rix l N ) i S V 0. Moreover, it holds that dl i + r ix l S i d l i+rix l N +δi l for all i S. This implies that (d l i + rix l N + δi) l i S V 0 if (d l i + rix l N ) i S V 0 and (d l i + rl i X N + δi l) i S V εm(l) if (d l i + rl i X N) i S V 0.FromV 0 = l IN V εm(l) it follows that lim l (dl i + rl i X N + δ l i ) i S = (d i +r i X N + δ i ) i S V 0. This implies that d i +r i X N + δ i i di + r i X S for all i S. Since d i + r i X S i d i +r i X N +δ i for all i S assumption (C3) implies that δ i = δ i for all i S. Consequently, it holds that lim δi l = δ i = δ i. l i S i S i S So, each convergent subsequence ( i S δ l i) l IN converges to i S δ i. Hence, ( i S δ k i ) k IN converges to i S δ i, which completes the proof. 2 Proposition 3.5 The excess function E S ((d, r)) is continuous in (d, r) for each (d, r) IR S (Γ). PROOF: Let ((d k,r k )) k IN be a sequence in IR N (Γ) converging to (d, r) IR N (Γ). We have to show that lim k E S ((d k,r k )) = E S ((d, r)). Since(E S ((d k,r k ))) k IN is a sequence in the compact set E S (IR N (Γ)) there exists a convergent subsequence (E S ((d l,r l ))) l IN with limit η. Note that the upper semi continuity of E S implies that

22 22 η E S ((d, r)). Since E S is lower semi continuous there exists a sequence ( i S δ l i) l IN such that i S δ l i E S((d l,r l )) for all l IN and lim l i S δ l i = E S((d, r)). Then lim l E S ((d l,r l )) lim l i S δi l = E S ((d, r)) η = lim l E S ((d l,r l )). Hence, lim l i S E S ((d l,r l )) = E S ((d, r)). Thus, every convergent subsequence of (E S ((d k,r k ))) k IN converges to E S ((d, r)). The compactness of E S (IR N (Γ)) then implies that lim k E S ((d k,r k )) = E S ((d, r)). 2 Summarizing, it is shown that the domain IR N (Γ) is compact and that the excess function E S is continuous for each coalition S N. From the results stated in Maschler et al. (1992) it then follows that the nucleolus N (Γ) as defined in (3) is a nonempty subset of IR N (Γ) for each stochastic cooperative game Γ CG(N). 4 The nucleolus, the core and deterministic equivalents For deterministic cooperative games it is known that the nucleolus as defined in Schmeidler (1969) is a core allocation whenever the core is nonempty. A similar result can be derived for the nucleolus N (Γ) introduced in this paper. For this, recall that an allocation (d, r) IR N (Γ) is a core allocation for the game Γ if for each coalition S N there exists no allocation ( d, r) IR S (Γ) such that d i + r i X S i d i +r i X N for all i S. Thesetofall core allocations is denoted by Core(Γ). Theorem 4.1 Let Γ CG(N).IfCore(Γ) then N (Γ) Core(Γ). PROOF: Take(d, r) IR N (Γ) and S N. Let( d S, r S ) I S (Γ) be such that d S i + r S i X S i d i + r i X N for all i S. Moreover, let ( d, r) PO S((d, r)) and δ IR S be such that d i + r i X S i d i +r i X N +δ i for all i S and i S δ i = E S ((d, r)). Regarding the sign of the excess, we distinguish three cases.

23 23 First, suppose ( d S, r S ) PD S (Γ)\PO S (Γ). Then d i + r i X S i ds i + r ix S S for all i S. Hence, δ i 0 for all i S. Since ( d S, r S ) is not Pareto optimal there exists j S such that d j + r j X S j ds j + r jx S S j d j +r j X N. Then δ j > 0 and, consequently, E S ((d, r)) = i S δ i > 0. Second, suppose ( d S, r S ) PO S (Γ). This implies that 0 E S ((d, r)). Hence, E S ((d, r)) 0. Third, suppose ( d S, r S ) NPD S (Γ)\PO S (Γ). Then d i + r i X S i ds i + r ix S S for all i S. Hence, δ i 0 for all i S. Moreover, since ( d S, r S ) is not Pareto optimal there exists j S such that d j + r j X S j ds i + r jx S S j d j +r j X N. So, δ j < 0 and, consequently, E S ((d, r)) = i S δ i < 0. Now we show that the excess vector corresponding to a core allocation is lexicographically smaller then the excess vector corresponding to an allocation that does not belong to the core. This implies that the latter allocation cannot belong to the nucleolus of the game whenever core allocations exist. Hence, the nucleolus must be a subset of the core. Take (d, r) Core(Γ) and (d,r ) Core(Γ). Since(d, r) Core(Γ) it follows from the core conditions that ( d S, r S ) NPD S (Γ) for all S N. Hence, E S ((d, r)) 0 for all S N. Since (d,r ) Core(Γ) there exists a coalition S N and an allocation ( ˆd, ˆr) IR S (Γ) for S such that ˆd i +ˆr i X S i d i+r ix N for all i S. Hence, ( d S, r S ) PD S (Γ)\PO S (Γ) and, consequently, E S ((d,r )) > 0. This implies that θ E S ((d, r)) < lex θ E S ((d,r )). Thus (d,r ) N (Γ). 2 Next, consider the class MG(N) of cooperative games with stochastic payoffs introduced in Suijs and Borm (1996). For this particular class of games it was shown that the core of a game Γ=(N, (X S ) S N, ( i ) i N ) is nonempty if and only if the core of a corresponding deterministic game Γ =(N, (x S ) S N, ( i ) i N ) is nonempty. This deterministic game Γ is called the deterministic equivalent of Γ. The preferences i of a game Γ MG(N) are such that there exists a function m i : L 1 (IR) IR satisfying (M1) for all X L 1 (IR) : X i m i (X), (M2) for all X, Y L 1 (IR) : X i Y if and only if m i (X) m i (Y ),

24 24 (M3) for all d IR : m i (d)=d, (M4) for all X L 1 (IR) and all d IR : m i (X + d)=d+m i (X), with L 1 (IR) the set of all random variables with finite expectation. Here, m i (X) represents the deterministic equivalent of the random payoff X according to player i. So, player i is indifferent between receiving the random payoff X and receiving the amount m i (X) with certainty. Furthermore, the payoff x S of coalition S in the game Γ is defined by x S = max m i (d i + r i X S ), (d,r) IR S (Γ) i S for all S N. Moreover, Suijs and Borm (1996) also showed that an allocation (d, r) IR S (Γ) is Pareto optimal if and only if for the corresponding allocation (m i (d i +r i X S )) i S in Γ it holds that i S m i (d i + r i X S )=x S. Finally, note that i satisfies conditions (C2) and (C3) for all i N and that the preferences discussed in Example 2.3 and Example 2.4 satisfy (M1) - (M4). Moreover, if the utility functions discussed in Example 2.5 are exponential then conditions (M1) - (M4) are also satisfied. In the remainder of this section we show that the nucleolus N ( Γ ) of the deterministic equivalent coincides with the nucleolus introduced by Schmeidler (1969). Moreover, we show that an allocation (d, r) IR N (G) belongs to the nucleolus N (Γ) if and only if the corresponding allocation (m i (d i + r i X N )) i N in the deterministic equivalent Γ belongs to the nucleolus N ( Γ ) of Γ. Let Γ CG(N) be such that conditions (M1)-(M4) are satisfied. For the deterministic equivalent Γ of Γ it holds that I S ( Γ )={y IR S i S : y i x {i} } is the set of (non feasible) individually rational allocations for coalition S, IR S ( Γ )={y I S (Γ) y i x S } i S is the set of feasible individually rational allocations for S and PO S ( Γ )={y IR S ( Γ ) y IR S ( Γ ) i S : y i >y i },

25 25 is the set of Pareto optimal allocations of S. Obviously, IR S ( Γ ) and PO S ( Γ ) are compact. Next, note that for each allocation y IR N ( Γ ) and each S N we have that W S (y) = {y IR S ( Γ ) i S : y i y i}, B S (y) = {y IR S ( Γ ) i S : y i y i}, PO S(y) = (W S (y) B S (y)) PO S ( Γ ). So POS(y)is the set of Pareto optimal allocations for S such that all members of S prefer the allocation y to such a Pareto optimal allocation or all members of S prefer the Pareto optimal allocation to y. The excess function E S : IR N ( Γ ) IR can now be rewritten as E S (y) = min y POS (y){ δ i i S : y i = y i + δ i }. i S Since δ i = y i y i and i S y i = x S it follows that E S (y) =x S i Sy i. Hence, N ( G ) coincides with the traditional nucleolus for the game Γ. Now, take (d, r) IR N (Γ). The excess of coalition S then equals E S ((d, r)) = min (d,r ) POS ((d,r)){ δ i i S : d i + r ix S i d i + r i X N + δ i } i S = min (d,r ) POS ((d,r)){ δ i i S : m i (d i + r ix S )=m i (d i +r i X N +δ i )} i S = min (d,r ) POS ((d,r)){ δ i i S : m i (d i + r ix S )=δ i +m i (d i +r i X N )} i S = min (m i (d i + r i X S) m i (d i + r i X N )) (d,r ) PO S ((d,r)) i S = x S i S m i (d i + r i X N ) = E S ((m i (d i + r i X N )) i N ). So, the excess of coalition S at allocation (d, r) equals the excess introduced by Schmeidler (1969) of coalition S at the corresponding allocation (m i (d i +r i X N )) i N in the deterministic equivalent Γ. Moreover, for each allocation (d, r) PO N (Γ) in Γ the vector (m i (d i + r i X N )) i N is an allocation of x N in Γ and, vice versa, for each allocation y of x N in Γ there exists an allocation (d, r) PO N (Γ) in Γ such that m i (d i + r i X N )=y i for all i N. This result has the following three implications. First, since the deterministic equivalent of a deterministic cooperative game is the deterministic game itself it follows that the nucleolusn coincides with Scmeidler s nucleolus on the class of deterministic cooperative games.

26 26 Second, an allocation (d, r) belongs to the nucleolus N (Γ) of the game Γ if and only if the corresponding allocation (m i (d i + r i X N )) i N belongs to the nucleolus N ( Γ ) of the corresponding deterministic equivalent Γ. Third, the nucleolus N ( Γ ) is nonempty if IR N ( Γ ). Hence, for all games Γ MG(N) the nucleolus N (Γ) is nonempty if IR N ( Γ ). This is in particular interesting since Suijs and Borm (1996) also showed that the relation between stochastic cooperative games Γ MG(N) and their deterministic equivalents Γ also holds if the following more general definition of an allocation is used. Instead of a pair (d, r) H S S an allocation of the random payoff X S is described by a pair (d, Y ) H S L 1 (IR) S,where Y is an S-dimensional vector of random variables such that i S Y i = X S. Furthermore, note that the preferences discussed in Example 2.3, Example 2.4 and Example 2.5 are not continuous on the set L 1 (IR) of all random variables with finite expectation. Hence, condition (C1) is not satisfied in case this definition of an allocation is used. For a stochastic cooperative game Γ MG(N), however, the nucleolus still exists. Example 4.2 Consider the following three player game Γ. Let X {i} Exp(1) for i =1,2,3and let X S = i S X {i} if S 2. So, each player individually faces a random cost which is exponentially distributed with expectation equal to 1. The cost of a coalition then equals the sum of the cost of the members of this coalition. Furthermore, all players are expected utility maximizers with utility functions u 1 (t) = e 0.5t,u 2 (t)= e 0.33t and u 3 (t) = e 0.25t, respectively. For the deterministic equivalent m i it holds that m i (d i + r i X S ) = u 1 i (E(u i (d i + r i X S ))). For the deterministic equivalent Γ of Γ we then get x {1} = , x {2} = , x {3} = , x {1,2} = , x {1,3} = , x {2,3} = and x {1,2,3} = The nucleolus N ( Γ ) of this game is equal to ( , , ). To determine the nucleolus N (Γ) note that an allocation (d, r) is Pareto optimal if and only if r = 1 (2, 3, 4). Then the only 9 allocation (d, r) for which (m i (d i + r i X N )) i N = N ( Γ ) is the allocation (d,r ) with d =( , , ) and r = 1(2, 3, 4). Hence, N (Γ) = 9 {(d,r )}.

27 27 Appendix A For the following lemma stated in this appendix we use the following notation. Let X, Y L(Γ) and let (d k ) k IN and (r k ) k IN be sequences in IR and [0, 1], respectively. Denote by F, F k and G the probability distribution functions of X, d k + r k X and Y, respectively. Moreover, note that if r k 0. F k (t) =IP({ω d k +r k X(ω) t})=ip({ω X(ω) t δk })=F( t dk ), r k r k Lemma A.3 If F k w G then there exists d IR and r [0, 1] such that Y = d + rx. PROOF: First, since (r k ) k IN is a sequence in [0, 1] we may assume without loss of generality that (r k ) k IN converges to r [0, 1]. Second, note that F k w G implies that lim k F k (t) =G(t)for all t C G = {t IR G is continuous in t}. Note that IR\C G is a countable set. Consider the following two cases. I: r =0. In this case we have that Y is a degenerate random variable, i.e, IP({ω Y (ω )= d})=1forsome d IR. Hence, F k w G implies that lim k d k = d. II: r>0. In this case we show that lim k d k = d for some d IR. Suppose that the sequence (d k ) k IN does not converge. Then there are three possibilities. First, it holds that lim k d k =+. Then lim k F k (t) = lim k F ( t dk )=0 r k for all t C G. Consequently, it must hold that G(t) =0for all t C G. Clearly, this is a contradiction. Second, it holds that lim k d k =. Then lim k F k (t) = lim k F ( t dk )=1 r k for all t C G. Consequently, it must be true that G(t) =1for all t C G. Again, this is a contradiction. Third, there exist convergent subsequences (d l ) l IN and (d m ) m IN with limits d and d, respectively, such that d> d. Let t 1 C G. Since lim k F k (t 1 )=G(t 1 )

28 28 it follows that lim l F l (t 1 ) = lim l F ( t 1 dl )=G(t r l 1 )and lim m F m (t 1 )= lim m F ( t 1 dm )=G(t r m 1 ). So, lim l F ( t 1 dl ) = lim r l m F ( t 1 dm ). From the r m fact that probability distribution functions are nondecreasing and continuous from the right it follows that F is constant on the interval [ t 1 d r, t 1 d ). To be more precisely, r F (t) = lim l F ( t 1 dl ) for all t [ t r l 1 d, t 1 d ). This implies that G is constant on the r r interval [t 1,t 1 +d d). To see this, take τ [t 1,t 1 +d d).ifgis continuous in τ then it follows from F k either τ d r [ t 1 d r w G that G(τ) = lim l F ( τ dl r l, t 1 d τ d ) or r r [ t 1 d r ) = lim m F ( τ dm ). Since r m, t 1 d ) it holds that G(τ) = lim r l F ( t 1 dl ). r l If G is not continuous in τ then there exists τ 1,τ 2 C G such that t 1 τ 1 < τ < τ 2 < t 1 + d d. Hence, by the same argument as above we have that G(τ 1 )=G(τ 2 ) = lim l F ( t 1 dl ).SinceGis nondecreasing it holds that G(τ r l 1 ) G(τ) G(τ 2 ). Thus G(τ) = lim l F ( t 1 dl ). Consequently, G is constant on the r l interval [t 1,t 1 +d d). Next, take t [t 1,t 1 +d d). By the same argument as above it follows that F is constant on [ t d t d, ) and that G is constant on [t, t + d d). Hence, G is constant on r r the interval [t 1,t 1 +2(d d)). Repeating this argument yields that G is constant on (t 1, ). Finally, since this holds for all t 1 C G it follows that G is constant on IR. Obviously, this is a contradiction. Next, let F d denote the probability distribution function of d+rx. Sincelim k d k = d and lim k r k = r it follows that F k w F d. Hence, F d (t) =G(t)for all t C G.Since F d and G are continuous from the right it follows that F d (t) =G(t)for all t IR. Consequently, Y = d + rx. 2 Lemma A.4 The preference relation i arising from an expected utility maximizing player satisfies the continuity condition (C1). PROOF: LetXbe random variable and let (d k i + rk i X) k IN be a convergent sequence with limit X. From Lemma A.3 we know that there exists d i and r i such that lim k d k i = d i,

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games Theo Driessen, Vito Fragnelli, Ilya Katsev, Anna Khmelnitskaya Twente University, The Netherlands Universitá del Piemonte Orientale, Italy St. Petersburg

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

No CHARACTERIZING CONVEXITY OF GAMES USING MARGINAL VECTORS. By Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde. February 2003 ISSN

No CHARACTERIZING CONVEXITY OF GAMES USING MARGINAL VECTORS. By Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde. February 2003 ISSN No 003 CHARACTERIZING CONVEXITY OF GAMES USING MARGINAL VECTORS By Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde February 003 ISSN 094-785 Characterizing convexity of games using marginal vectors Bas van

More information

A Cooperative Approach to Queue Allocation of Indivisible Objects

A Cooperative Approach to Queue Allocation of Indivisible Objects A Cooperative Approach to Queue Allocation of Indivisible Objects Herbert Hamers a Flip Klijn b Marco Slikker c Bas van Velzen d September 2004 Abstract We consider the allocation of a finite number of

More information

Chapter 5. Nucleolus. Core(v) := {x R n x is an imputation such that e(x, S) 0 for all coalitions S}.

Chapter 5. Nucleolus. Core(v) := {x R n x is an imputation such that e(x, S) 0 for all coalitions S}. Chapter 5 Nucleolus In this chapter we study another way of selecting a unique efficient allocation that forms an alternative to the Shapley value. Fix a TU-game (N, v). Given a coalition S and an allocation

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

Cooperative Game Solution Concepts That Maximize Stability under Noise

Cooperative Game Solution Concepts That Maximize Stability under Noise Cooperative Game Solution Concepts That Maximize Stability under Noise Yuqian Li and Vincent Conitzer Department of Computer Science Duke University {yuqian, conitzer}@cs.duke.edu Abstract In cooperative

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Coincidence of Cooperative Game Theoretic Solutions in the Appointment Problem. Youngsub Chun Nari Parky Duygu Yengin

Coincidence of Cooperative Game Theoretic Solutions in the Appointment Problem. Youngsub Chun Nari Parky Duygu Yengin School of Economics Working Papers ISSN 2203-6024 Coincidence of Cooperative Game Theoretic Solutions in the Appointment Problem Youngsub Chun Nari Parky Duygu Yengin Working Paper No. 2015-09 March 2015

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Noncooperative continuous-time Markov games

Noncooperative continuous-time Markov games Morfismos, Vol. 9, No. 1, 2005, pp. 39 54 Noncooperative continuous-time Markov games Héctor Jasso-Fuentes Abstract This work concerns noncooperative continuous-time Markov games with Polish state and

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007 Game Theory Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India November 2007 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY 6. Other Solution Concepts Note:

More information

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS

EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS EFFICIENT, WEAK EFFICIENT, AND PROPER EFFICIENT PORTFOLIOS MANUELA GHICA We give some necessary conditions for weak efficiency and proper efficiency portfolios for a reinsurance market in nonconvex optimization

More information

On the Convexity of Precedence Sequencing Games

On the Convexity of Precedence Sequencing Games On the Convexity of Precedence Sequencing Games Herbert Hamers a, Flip Klijn b, 1, Bas van Velzen a a CentER and Department of Econometrics and Operational Research, Tilburg University, The Netherlands

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Worst case analysis for a general class of on-line lot-sizing heuristics

Worst case analysis for a general class of on-line lot-sizing heuristics Worst case analysis for a general class of on-line lot-sizing heuristics Wilco van den Heuvel a, Albert P.M. Wagelmans a a Econometric Institute and Erasmus Research Institute of Management, Erasmus University

More information

Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales

Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales Fundamental Inequalities, Convergence and the Optional Stopping Theorem for Continuous-Time Martingales Prakash Balachandran Department of Mathematics Duke University April 2, 2008 1 Review of Discrete-Time

More information

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam Cooperative Games Stéphane Airiau Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam 12th European Agent Systems Summer School (EASSS 2010) Ecole Nationale Supérieure des Mines

More information

On the Balancedness of m-sequencing Games

On the Balancedness of m-sequencing Games On the Balancedness of m-sequencing Games Herbert Hamers Flip Klijn Jeroen Suijs Department of Econometrics and CentER, Tilburg University, P.O.Box 90153, 5000 LE Tilburg, The Netherlands March 4, 1998

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

No ASSIGNMENT SITUATIONS WITH MULTIPLE OWNERSHIP AND THEIR GAMES. By Silvia Miquel, Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde.

No ASSIGNMENT SITUATIONS WITH MULTIPLE OWNERSHIP AND THEIR GAMES. By Silvia Miquel, Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde. No. 2005 78 ASSIGNMENT SITUATIONS WITH MULTIPLE OWNERSHIP AND THEIR GAMES By Silvia Miquel, Bas van Velzen, Herbert Hamers, Henk Norde June 2005 ISSN 0924-7815 Assignment situations with multiple ownership

More information

Lecture 6: Communication Complexity of Auctions

Lecture 6: Communication Complexity of Auctions Algorithmic Game Theory October 13, 2008 Lecture 6: Communication Complexity of Auctions Lecturer: Sébastien Lahaie Scribe: Rajat Dixit, Sébastien Lahaie In this lecture we examine the amount of communication

More information

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition Katsushige FUJIMOTO College of Symbiotic Systems Science, Fukushima University, 1 Kanayagawa Fukushima,

More information

Monotonicity and Nash Implementation in Matching Markets with Contracts

Monotonicity and Nash Implementation in Matching Markets with Contracts Monotonicity and Nash Implementation in Matching Markets with Contracts Claus-Jochen Haake Bettina Klaus March 2006 Abstract We consider general two-sided matching markets, so-called matching with contracts

More information

Consistency and Monotonicity in One-Sided Assignment Problems

Consistency and Monotonicity in One-Sided Assignment Problems Consistency and Monotonicity in One-Sided Assignment Problems Bettina Klaus Alexandru Nichifor Working Paper 09-146 Copyright 2009 by Bettina Klaus and Alexandru Nichifor Working papers are in draft form.

More information

Assortative Matching in Two-sided Continuum Economies

Assortative Matching in Two-sided Continuum Economies Assortative Matching in Two-sided Continuum Economies Patrick Legros and Andrew Newman February 2006 (revised March 2007) Abstract We consider two-sided markets with a continuum of agents and a finite

More information

The Pre-nucleolus for Fuzzy Cooperative Games

The Pre-nucleolus for Fuzzy Cooperative Games Journal of Game Theory 207, 6(2): 43-5 DOI: 05923/jjgt207060203 The Pre-nucleolus for Fuzzy Cooperative Games Yeremia Maroutian 39, E98 Str Broolyn, NY 236 Abstract In this paper invented by D Schmeidler

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Game Theory: Spring 2017 Game Theory: Spring 2017 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today Today we are going to review solution concepts for coalitional

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Computing the Nucleolus of Matching, Cover and Clique Games

Computing the Nucleolus of Matching, Cover and Clique Games Proceedings of the Twenty-Sixth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence Computing the Nucleolus of Matching, Cover and Clique Games Ning Chen Division of Mathematical Sciences Nanyang Technological

More information

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games Weighted values and the Core in NTU games Koji Yokote August 4, 2014 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to extend the following result by Monderer et al. (1992): the set of weighted Shapley values includes

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games Toru Hokari Yukihiko Funaki April 25, 2014 Abstract Peleg (1986) and Tadenuma (1992) provide two well-known axiomatic characterizations

More information

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES STUDIA UNIV. BABEŞ BOLYAI, MATHEMATICA, Volume LIV, Number 1, March 2009 ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES TITU ANDREESCU AND ZORAN ŠUNIĆ Abstract. A solution function for convex

More information

Lecture 4 The nucleolus

Lecture 4 The nucleolus Lecture 4 The nucleolus The nucleolus is based on the notion of excess and has been introduced by Schmeidler [3]. The excess measures the amount of complaints of a coalition for a payoff distribution.

More information

Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication)

Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication) Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication) Nikolaus Robalino and Arthur Robson Appendix B: Proof of Theorem 2 This appendix contains the proof of Theorem

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

ONLINE APPENDIX. Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools

ONLINE APPENDIX. Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools ONLINE APPENDIX Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools T. Andrabi, J. Das, A.I. Khwaja, S. Ozyurt, and N. Singh Contents A Theory A.1 Homogeneous Demand.................................

More information

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies Working Papers Institute of Mathematical Economics 430 April 2010 Representation of TU games by coalition production economies Tomoki Inoue IMW Bielefeld University Postfach 100131 33501 Bielefeld Germany

More information

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players Lecture 2 The Core Let us assume that we have a TU game (N, v) and that we want to form the grand coalition. We model cooperation between all the agents in N and we focus on the sharing problem: how to

More information

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE SARA FROEHLICH 1. Introduction Cooperative game theory is fundamentally different from the types of games we have studied so far, which we will now refer to

More information

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014 SANDWICH GAMES EHUD LEHRER AND ROEE TEPER July 9, 204 Abstract. The extension of set functions (or capacities) in a concave fashion, namely a concavification, is an important issue in decision theory and

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

Compromise Stable TU-Games Quant, Marieke; Borm, Peter; Reijnierse, Hans; van Velzen, S.

Compromise Stable TU-Games Quant, Marieke; Borm, Peter; Reijnierse, Hans; van Velzen, S. Tilburg University Compromise Stable TU-Games Quant, Marieke; Borm, Peter; Reijnierse, Hans; van Velzen, S. Publication date: 2003 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Quant, M., Borm,

More information

Best Guaranteed Result Principle and Decision Making in Operations with Stochastic Factors and Uncertainty

Best Guaranteed Result Principle and Decision Making in Operations with Stochastic Factors and Uncertainty Stochastics and uncertainty underlie all the processes of the Universe. N.N.Moiseev Best Guaranteed Result Principle and Decision Making in Operations with Stochastic Factors and Uncertainty by Iouldouz

More information

CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES

CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES RYO MIZUNO Abstract. We consider a situation where coalitions are formed to divide a resource. As in real life, the value of a payoff

More information

Convex Interval Games

Convex Interval Games Convex Interval Games S.Z. Alparslan Gök R. Branzei S. Tijs Abstract In this paper, convex interval games are introduced and characterizations are given. Some economic situations leading to convex interval

More information

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Lukasz Balbus Kevin Reffett Lukasz Woźny April 2014 Abstract Recently Yang and Qi (2013) stated an interesting theorem on existence of complete

More information

Mechanism Design: Bayesian Incentive Compatibility

Mechanism Design: Bayesian Incentive Compatibility May 30, 2013 Setup X : finite set of public alternatives X = {x 1,..., x K } Θ i : the set of possible types for player i, F i is the marginal distribution of θ i. We assume types are independently distributed.

More information

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1

s P = f(ξ n )(x i x i 1 ). i=1 Compactness and total boundedness via nets The aim of this chapter is to define the notion of a net (generalized sequence) and to characterize compactness and total boundedness by this important topological

More information

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (50b) Problem Set 0. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann 4/5/4 This problem set is due on Tuesday, 4//4..

More information

Notes on Measure Theory and Markov Processes

Notes on Measure Theory and Markov Processes Notes on Measure Theory and Markov Processes Diego Daruich March 28, 2014 1 Preliminaries 1.1 Motivation The objective of these notes will be to develop tools from measure theory and probability to allow

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets 2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets NOTE: AS OF 2008, SOME OF THIS STUFF IS A BIT OUT- DATED AND HAS A FEW TYPOS. I WILL REVISE THIS MATE- RIAL SOMETIME. In this lecture we discuss two

More information

Controlling versus enabling Online appendix

Controlling versus enabling Online appendix Controlling versus enabling Online appendix Andrei Hagiu and Julian Wright September, 017 Section 1 shows the sense in which Proposition 1 and in Section 4 of the main paper hold in a much more general

More information

2. What is the fraction of aggregate savings due to the precautionary motive? (These two questions are analyzed in the paper by Ayiagari)

2. What is the fraction of aggregate savings due to the precautionary motive? (These two questions are analyzed in the paper by Ayiagari) University of Minnesota 8107 Macroeconomic Theory, Spring 2012, Mini 1 Fabrizio Perri Stationary equilibria in economies with Idiosyncratic Risk and Incomplete Markets We are now at the point in which

More information

Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining

Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining Björn Segendorff Department of Economics Stockholm School of Economics PO Box 6501 SE-113 83STOCKHOLM SWEDEN SSE/EFI Working Paper Series in Economics and Finance No

More information

A Compact Representation Scheme for Coalitional Games in Open Anonymous Environments

A Compact Representation Scheme for Coalitional Games in Open Anonymous Environments A Compact Representation Scheme for Coalitional Games in Open Anonymous Environments Naoki Ohta, Atsushi Iwasaki, Makoto Yokoo and Kohki Maruono ISEE, Kyushu University 6-10-1, Hakozaki, Higashi-ku, Fukuoka,

More information

Game Theory and Rationality

Game Theory and Rationality April 6, 2015 Notation for Strategic Form Games Definition A strategic form game (or normal form game) is defined by 1 The set of players i = {1,..., N} 2 The (usually finite) set of actions A i for each

More information

An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set

An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set By Parkash Chander * May 2015 Revised: November 2015 Abstract In this paper, we first introduce and characterize a new and general concept of a credible deviation in

More information

Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities

Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities 1 / 45 Mechanism design and allocation algorithms for energy-network markets with piece-wise linear costs and quadratic externalities Alejandro Jofré 1 Center for Mathematical Modeling & DIM Universidad

More information

Existence of Optimal Strategies in Markov Games with Incomplete Information

Existence of Optimal Strategies in Markov Games with Incomplete Information Existence of Optimal Strategies in Markov Games with Incomplete Information Abraham Neyman 1 December 29, 2005 1 Institute of Mathematics and Center for the Study of Rationality, Hebrew University, 91904

More information

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School Lecturer: Bruno Codenotti Lecture 5: The Core of Cooperative Games The core is by far the cooperative solution concept most used in Economic

More information

2 Making the Exponential Mechanism Exactly Truthful Without

2 Making the Exponential Mechanism Exactly Truthful Without CIS 700 Differential Privacy in Game Theory and Mechanism Design January 31, 2014 Lecture 3 Lecturer: Aaron Roth Scribe: Aaron Roth Privacy as a Tool for Mechanism Design for arbitrary objective functions)

More information

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Game Theory: Spring 2017 Game Theory: Spring 2017 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today The coming four lectures are about cooperative game theory, where

More information

M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 6

M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 6 M17 MAT25-21 HOMEWORK 6 DUE 10:00AM WEDNESDAY SEPTEMBER 13TH 1. To Hand In Double Series. The exercises in this section will guide you to complete the proof of the following theorem: Theorem 1: Absolute

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

A simple algorithm for the nucleolus of airport profit games

A simple algorithm for the nucleolus of airport profit games Int J Game Theory 2006 34:259 272 DOI 10.1007/s00182-006-0019-4 ORIGINAL ARTICLE A simple algorithm for the nucleolus of airport profit games Rodica Brânzei Elena Iñarra Stef Tijs José M. Zarzuelo Accepted:

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY H. JEROME KEISLER AND YENENG SUN Abstract. An atomless probability space (Ω, A, P ) is said to have the saturation property for a probability measure µ on

More information

Dynamic Linear Production Games under Uncertainty

Dynamic Linear Production Games under Uncertainty Dynamic Linear Production Games under Uncertainty Alejandro Toriello Stewart School of Industrial and Systems Engineering Georgia Institute of Technology Joint work with N.A. Uhan (USNA) Partially supported

More information

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities NUPRI Working Paper 2016-03 Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities Takuya Iimura, Toshimasa Maruta, and Takahiro Watanabe October, 2016 Nihon University Population Research Institute http://www.nihon-u.ac.jp/research/institute/population/nupri/en/publications.html

More information

On Bankruptcy Game Theoretic Interval Rules

On Bankruptcy Game Theoretic Interval Rules On Bankruptcy Game Theoretic Interval Rules arxiv:1301.3096v1 [q-fin.gn] 7 Jan 2013 Rodica Branzei University Alexandru Ioan Cuza, Iaşi, Romania branzeir@info.uaic.ro Marco Dall Aglio Luiss University,

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information

Chapter 5 Random vectors, Joint distributions. Lectures 18-23

Chapter 5 Random vectors, Joint distributions. Lectures 18-23 Chapter 5 Random vectors, Joint distributions Lectures 18-23 In many real life problems, one often encounter multiple random objects. For example, if one is interested in the future price of two different

More information

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming 1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming Formally, a stochastic dynamic program has the same components as a deterministic one; the only modification is to the state transition equation. When events in the future

More information

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS

MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS Chapter 6 MORE ON CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS AND SETS This chapter can be considered enrichment material containing also several more advanced topics and may be skipped in its entirety. You can proceed directly

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Theorem 2.1 (Caratheodory). A (countably additive) probability measure on a field has an extension. n=1

Theorem 2.1 (Caratheodory). A (countably additive) probability measure on a field has an extension. n=1 Chapter 2 Probability measures 1. Existence Theorem 2.1 (Caratheodory). A (countably additive) probability measure on a field has an extension to the generated σ-field Proof of Theorem 2.1. Let F 0 be

More information

VOL. VOL NO. ISSUE NEAR-FEASIBLE STABLE MATCHINGS WITH COUPLES 19. Online Appendix. Near-Feasible Stable Matching with Couples

VOL. VOL NO. ISSUE NEAR-FEASIBLE STABLE MATCHINGS WITH COUPLES 19. Online Appendix. Near-Feasible Stable Matching with Couples VOL. VOL NO. ISSUE NEAR-FEASIBLE STABLE MATCHINGS WITH COUPLES 19 Online Appendix Near-Feasible Stable Matching with Couples Thành Nguyen and Rakesh Vohra Preferences and Stability A1. Preferences Doctor

More information

Majority bargaining for resource division

Majority bargaining for resource division Auton Agent Multi-Agent Syst (2016) 30:331 363 DOI 10.1007/s10458-015-9290-8 Majority bargaining for resource division Shaheen Fatima Michael Wooldridge Published online: 18 February 2015 TheAuthor(s)2015

More information

Stochastic Convergence, Delta Method & Moment Estimators

Stochastic Convergence, Delta Method & Moment Estimators Stochastic Convergence, Delta Method & Moment Estimators Seminar on Asymptotic Statistics Daniel Hoffmann University of Kaiserslautern Department of Mathematics February 13, 2015 Daniel Hoffmann (TU KL)

More information

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS

WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic Renou No 902 WARWICK ECONOMIC RESEARCH PAPERS DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Implementation in Mixed Nash Equilibrium Claudio Mezzetti & Ludovic

More information

Persuading a Pessimist

Persuading a Pessimist Persuading a Pessimist Afshin Nikzad PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract While in practice most persuasion mechanisms have a simple structure, optimal signals in the Bayesian persuasion framework may not be so.

More information

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers joint work with Frederic Murphy Climate Policy and Long Term Decisions-Investment and R&D, Bocconi University, Milan,

More information

Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems

Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems Converse consistency and the constrained equal benefits rule in airport problems Cheng-Cheng Hu Min-Hung Tsay Chun-Hsien Yeh June 3, 009 Abstract We propose a converse consistency property and study its

More information

Lecture 2. We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales.

Lecture 2. We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales. Lecture 2 1 Martingales We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales. 1.1 Doob s inequality We have the following maximal

More information

DISTRIBUTION OF THE SUPREMUM LOCATION OF STATIONARY PROCESSES. 1. Introduction

DISTRIBUTION OF THE SUPREMUM LOCATION OF STATIONARY PROCESSES. 1. Introduction DISTRIBUTION OF THE SUPREMUM LOCATION OF STATIONARY PROCESSES GENNADY SAMORODNITSKY AND YI SHEN Abstract. The location of the unique supremum of a stationary process on an interval does not need to be

More information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Seungjin Han May 20, 2011 Abstract In common agency problems, competing principals often incentivize a privately-informed agent s action choice

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland.

Measures. 1 Introduction. These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. Measures These preliminary lecture notes are partly based on textbooks by Athreya and Lahiri, Capinski and Kopp, and Folland. 1 Introduction Our motivation for studying measure theory is to lay a foundation

More information

A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation

A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation A Generic Approach to Coalition Formation Krzysztof R. Apt and Andreas Witzel Abstract We propose an abstract approach to coalition formation by focusing on partial preference relations between partitions

More information