Math 131A: Real Analysis

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Math 131A: Real Analysis"

Transcription

1 Math 131A: Real Analysis Michael Andrews UCLA Mathematics Department February 6, 018 Contents 1 Introduction 4 Truth Tables 4.1 NOT(P ) P and Q, P or Q P = Q (read this as P arrow Q, not as P implies Q ) Some familiar sets 6 4 Quantifiers Unspecified variables A well-formed sentence Verifying a sentence involving quantifiers Negating a sentence involving quantifiers Parentheses Negating a sentence with parentheses carefully Math 95 notes Absolute value Definition and basic properties The point of the absolute value A little more about sets 17 7 Sequences and the definition of convergence Sequences Convergence of sequences Divergence of sequences How to spend your time Constructing the proof of theorem

2 7.6 Motivating the definition of convergence Another sequence that converges Constructing the proof of theorem The algebra of limits The game and the computer program, finishing the proof of Another algebra of limits proof, more game/computer program Continuity The definition Motivating the definition of continuity Examples of continuous functions Uniform Continuity The definition and a comparison with the definition of continuity Examples of uniformly continuous and non-uniformly continuous functions What are the real numbers? The completeness axiom What are the real numbers? Boundedness, maximum and minimum elements The completeness axiom Suprema and Infima Contrapositive and contradiction An almost-proof of corollary Some more on sequences (not lectured) Uniqueness of limits Bounded sequences Algebra of limits (continued) Sequences and the completeness of R Cauchy sequences Monotone Sequences Subsequences and the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem Completeness of R Examples More on continuous functions The sequence definition of continuity New continuous functions from old ones (not lectured) The Intermediate Value Theorem and the Extreme Value Theorem A theorem that should be included somewhere Calculus Limits along the domain of a function The derivative Rules for differentiating (not lectured or examined explicitly) Fermat and Rolle s Theorem

3 14.5 The Mean Value Theorem and important results from calculus Series From sequences to series Tests for convergence and divergence Power series More functions: cos, sin, exp, log Definitions cos, sin and π exp, log, exponents De Moivre s theorem (off syllabus) Taylor s theorem Taylor series and Taylor polynomials Taylor series of polynomials A rubbish Taylor series An even more rubbish Taylor series (definitely off syllabus) Taylor s theorem Miscellaneous Denseness of the rationals and irrationals in R Irrationality of Countability Integration Goals for our theory of integration Deficiencies What is integration anyway? The definition of integrability Basic examples Integration: two auxilary theorems Properties of the integral Preliminary examples to the fundamental theorems of calculus The fundamental theorems of calculus One more theorem Picard Iterates

4 1 Introduction Many people find mathematics satisfying because a (well-constructed) statement in math is either true or false. For example, 0 = 0 is true and 0 0 is false. Another example of a true statement is: if f : R R is a differentiable function, then f is continuous. The first two examples are very different from the last example. The first examples are ridiculously easy, whereas the latter is more complicated. The latter is more complicated because of the words which appear. It is unlikely that the word continuous has ever been defined carefully enough for you so that whatever function I give you, you can answer with certainty, either it is continuous or it is not continuous, and you never answer it is and it s not. Even if such a definition was given to you, it is unlikely that you were given the time to master verifying such definitions to the standard of a pure mathematician. The purpose of this class is to give you precise definitions of concepts such as continuity and differentiability, and to teach you how to verify such definitions (or their negation). We will learn how concepts like these relate to one another; the sentence above gives an example of how continuity and differentiability relate to one another. We will learn how to prove such relationships rigorously. Truth Tables Mathematics is concerned with statements which are true or false. We gave two simple examples and a more complicated example in the introduction. Just like when we speak English, mathematics is built up by putting together lots of simpler pieces. In this section, we learn a few simple ways of constructing statements which are true or false from existing statements which are true or false..1 NOT(P ) Suppose P is a statement which is true or false. We normally call such a thing a proposition. We have a new proposition NOT(P ). The truth of NOT(P ) is completely determined by the truth of P. This is demonstrated in the following truth table. P NOT(P ) T F For example, the statement I am your lecturer for math 131A is true, and the statement I am NOT your lecturer for math 131A is false. I am a cat is false; I am NOT a cat is true. You can see that NOT(NOT(P )) always has the same truth value as P by completing the following truth table. F T P NOT(P ) NOT(NOT(P )) I am NOT NOT your lecturer for math 131A is true. T F F T 4

5 . P and Q, P or Q Here is the truth table for (P and Q), and for (P or Q). It is important to note that mathematically or is taken to be inclusive unless we explicitly say otherwise. If you consider such rules for nonmathematical propositions, you might think that this seems like a strange convention, but I hope you will find that in mathematics such a convention makes a lot of sense. The following sentence seems fine to me: every real number is either bigger than or equal to 0, or less than or equal to 0. De Morgan s Laws state the following. P Q P and Q P or Q T T T T T F F T F T F T F F F F 1. NOT(P or Q) has the same truth values as (NOT(P ) and NOT(Q));. NOT(P and Q) has the same truth values as (NOT(P ) or NOT(Q)). If you ve never seen these laws before you should think up examples that convince you they work, and check them with truth tables..3 P = Q (read this as P arrow Q, not as P implies Q ) Here is the truth table for (P = Q). This is the most bizarre truth table. Whenever P is false, (P = Q) is true. This normally upsets people at first. We ll see why this is a sensible convention once we introduce quantifiers. P Q P = Q NOT(P = Q) T T T F T F F T F T T F F F T F 1. You can use a truth table to see that (P = Q) has the same truth values as (NOT(P ) or Q).. De Morgan s Laws tell us that NOT(P = Q) has the same truth values as (P and NOT(Q)). 5

6 3 Some familiar sets To make our discussion of quantifiers easier I need to introduce some concepts and some notation. Definition 3.1. A set is any collection of individuals. The members of a set are often called its elements. Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same elements. We write x X to mean that x is an element of a set X. Notation 3.. Curly brackets (braces) are often used to show sets. The set whose elements are a 1, a, a 3,..., a n is written {a 1, a, a 3,..., a n }. Similarly, the set whose members are those of an infinite sequence a 1, a, a 3,... of objects is denoted {a 1, a, a 3,...}. Definition 3.3. A common way to define a set is as those elements with a certain property. This can be problematic (Russell s paradox), but usually it is okay. We write {x : x has property P } for the set consisting of elements x with a property P, or {x X : x has property P } for the elements of a previously defined set X with a property P. The colons should be read as such that. Definition 3.4. If X and Y are sets then we write X Y and say X union Y for the set {a : a is an element of X or Y }, and we write X Y and say X intersect Y for the set We write X \ Y and say X take away Y for Here x / Y is read x is not an element of Y. {a : a is an element of X and Y }. {x X : x / Y }. Notation 3.5. Here is some notation for familiar sets. 1. the natural numbers N = {1,, 3,...},. the integers Z = {0} { n : n N} N = {0, 1, 1,,, 3, 3,...}, 3. the rationals Q = { m n : m Z, n N}, 4. the reals R (the stars of the show and yet you can t even tell me what they are), 5. the irrationals R \ Q, 6. the complex numbers C = {x + iy : x, y R}. 6

7 4 Quantifiers Quantifiers are the key to making precise, strong definitions. If you do not understand quanitifiers by the end of this class, you will fail the class. They are tricky, and they trip lots of people up, but they are worth investing lots of time into understanding properly. This class is difficult for multiple reasons. My hope is for us to conquer quantifiers early on so that we can focus on other difficult aspects later without quantifiers getting in our way. 4.1 Unspecified variables In section we talked about statements which are true or false, and some ways we can form new such statements from existing ones. Here is a formula. a + b = c Is it true or false? What about the following formula? Is that true or false? x = b ± b 4ac a I just fed you nonsense. I wrote down familiar formulae, and gave you no context for them at all. It is impossible to say whether they are true or false, because the truth of the first depends on what a, b, and c are, and the truth of the second depends on what a, b, c and x are. If you know what these familiar looking formula relate to, you will also know that the significance of a, b, and c in each equation is completely different, even though we have used the same letters. Here s are some even simpler examples of formulae. 1. x = 0. Is it true or false? Again, it depends on what x is. However, there are two observations that I can make. (a) It is not true for all possible choices for x. (If you find this sentence ambiguous, the simplicity of the equation x = 0 should resolve that ambiguity. Quantifiers will remove the ambiguity from more complicated sentences. Maybe you prefer, it is not true for all possible choices for x. ) (b) There is at least one choice of x which makes it true.. (x + 1) = x + x + 1. A priori, the truth of this formula might depend on x, but you have seen this one a million times in your life. You know this is always true. (a) It is true for all possible choices for x. (b) As a consequence, there is at least one choice of x which makes it true. 3. x = x + 1. (a) It is not true for all possible choices for x. (b) In fact, it is never true. There is not at least one choice of x which makes it true. 7

8 4. We now introduce our first quantifier which is read there exists. Oddly enough, giving a precise definition of this symbol in terms of the truth values of propositions is beyond the scope of this class. It is not too difficult, but it is for another time, when you take a class in mathematical logic. We demonstrate how it is used with the examples of the previous section. The following sentence is true. x R : x = 0. This is read there exists an x in R such that x = 0 or there exists a real number x such that x = 0. The following sentence is also true. x R : (x + 1) = x + x + 1. You can see these sentences are true because, in both cases, taking x to be 0 makes the subsequent formula true. The following sentence is false. x R : x = x + 1. It is possible to use more than one. For instance, a R : b R : c R : a + b = c is true because when a, b, and c are equal to 0, the formula is true. Don t dwell on this last example just yet because we will talk about how to deal with multiple quantifiers at a time shortly. 4.3 Our next quantifier is which is read for all. The following sentence is false. x R, x = 0. This is read for all x in R, x = 0 or for all real numbers x, x = 0. It is false because 1 is a real number which is not equal to 0. The following sentence is true. x R, (x + 1) = x + x + 1. That s because you know how to multiply (x + 1) = (x + 1)(x + 1) using distributivity of multiplication. The following sentence is false. x R, x = x + 1. The following sentence is also false. a R, b R, c R, a + b = c That s because taking a = 0, b = 0 and c = 1, makes the formula false. Example I think the following example is useful because it shows why the truth table for (P = Q) is what it is. We ll be coming back to this one. n Z, (n > 10 = n > 10). It expresses the sentence if an integer is bigger than 10, then it is bigger than 10 and so it is a true sentence. It is not crazy to believe that this is what the symbols encode, but I need to give you a way of verifying the truth of quantified sentences for you to really see why this is the case. 8

9 4.4 A well-formed sentence In mathematical logic, the concept of a sentence is defined. To be a well-formed sentence, the variables appearing in the formulae of the sentence must be quantified over. This means that for each variable there must be a corresponding quantifier. This is to guarantee that the sentence has a well-defined truth value. In this class, you should be suspicious if you see a variable that has not been previously declared or quantified over. 4.5 Verifying a sentence involving quantifiers Most sentences we will encounter in this course will be of the form Q 1 Q... Q n ϕ where each individual Q i is either of the form x i X i or x i X i, and ϕ is something constructed from a load of formulae and the operations of and, or, and =. (It can be more complicated than this because ϕ could also involve quanitfiers and look, for example, like ( x X : F 1 ) = F. The second example below is more complicated in a similar way.) A proof of the truth of such a sentence should consist of (n + 1) steps. At the i-th step, to deal with x i X i you should say let x i = BLAH where BLAH needs to be an element of X i written only in terms of variables which have already been specified. You should always check that the element x i that you declare is an element of the set X i. To deal with x i X i you simply say let x i X i. ϕ will be some proposition involving the variables x 1,..., x n. At the (n+1)-st step, you must verify the truth of ϕ based on your previous declared variables. For clarity, you should break this step up in to further substeps (a), (b), (c),... if necessary. Example The following sentence is true. n Z, (n > 10 = n > 10). Proof. We write the proof in the format just described. 1. Let n Z.. We must verify the truth of (n > 10 = n > 10). (a) Case 1: n 10. n > 10 is false, so the truth table for = says (n > 10 = n > 10) is true. (b) Case : n > 10. n > 10 is true. For (n > 10 = n > 10) to be true we must verify that n > 10. This is true because n > 10 > 10. I hope this example illustrates why the truth table for P = Q is what it is. The sentence is supposed to say if an integer is bigger than 10, then it is bigger than 10. Thinking of this statement as one about every integer, we see that we don t really care about integers less than or equal to 10 and we want (n > 10 = n > 10) to be true in this case. 9

10 Example The following sentence is true. ( x R, y R, x y = ( )) z R : x + z = y. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y R. 3. We must verify the truth of x y = ( ) z R : x + z = y. (a) Case 1: x > y. x y is false, so the truth table for = says the relevant sentence is true. (b) Case : x y. x y is true and we must verify the truth of z R : x + z = y. Notice that because the original sentence is not of the nice form I mentioned at the start of the section, we ve hit a point where we have to verify another proposition involving a quantifier. i. Let z = y x. z is a well-defined real number: we are working under the assumption that x y, and so y x 0. ii. We must verify that x + z = y. This is trivial algebra: x + z = x + ( y x) = x + (y x) = y. Example The following sentence is true. Proof. 1. Let x = 0.. Let y R. 3. Let z = y. Notice z R. 4. We see that x + y = 0 + z = z. x R : y R, z R : x + y = z. There s something important to note about this proof: we let z = y. This is fine because we made this declaration in step 3, and y was declared in step. Letting x = y in step 1 would have been an illegal declaration. We CANNOT define a variable in terms of a variable that s declared later. 10

11 4.6 Negating a sentence involving quantifiers Example Let s try to show the following sentence to be true. Our proof would read as follows. 1. Let x = BLAH. Notice x R.. Let y R. 3. Let z R. x R : y R, z R, x + y = z. 4. We need to check the truth of x + y = z. We need to think up what BLAH should be. Suppose we tried x = 0 in step 1. Then, in step 4, we would have to show that y = z. Checking that this is true is impossible since we know absolutely nothing about y and z (other than the fact that they are real numbers). y could be 1, and z could be 0, and in this case the equation is false. Similarly, if we tried x = 1 in step 1, then, in step 4, we would have to show that 1 + y = z. Checking that this is true is impossible too. Hmm, it seems the sentence is false. How do we verify this? First, let s note some things. The reason it is false is not because one choice of x failed us; it is because all choices of x fail us. Saying it another way, for all x R, the following proposition is false. y R, z R, x + y = z. Why is the proposition above false? When x = 0, we argued it was false by thinking about the case when y = 1 and z = 0. In the case when x = 0, this actually gives a proof that is true. y R : z R : x + y z In the end, the reason that the orginal sentence is false is that the following sentence is true. Example The following sentence is true. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y = 1. Notice y R. 3. Let z = 0. Notice z R. x R, y R : z R : x + y z. x R, y R : z R : x + y z. 4. We see that x + y = x > 0 = z. In particular, x + y z. 11

12 Remark In our attempt to verify the original sentence, the declaration let x = z y would be wrong for two reasons. First, y and z are declared after x. Second, z y could be less than zero, and so it is not possible to argue that x R. Remark Note the way that I used in particular in the previous proof. In particular is used in the following way. [Something holding less often]. In particular, [something holding more often]. Some examples in plain English are as follows. Some math examples. I am a man. In particular, I am a human. I am a human. In particular, I am an animal. I love all burgers. In particular, I love In N Out burgers. x = y. In particular, x y. x > y. In particular, x y. n Z is divisible by 4. In particular, n is even. Just for the hell of it, let s note another proof of the previous example. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y = x +. Notice y R. 3. Let z = (x + 1). Notice z R. 4. We see that x + y = x + (x + ) = x + 4x + 4 = (x + 1) + (x + 1) = z. Notice that the sentences x R : y R, z R, x + y = z x R, y R : z R : x + y z are related to each other by replacing with, with, and = with. In general, there is a procedure called negation which is always guaranteed to change a true sentence to a false one, and a false sentence to a true one. 1

13 Definition The negation of a sentence S is NOT(S ); NOT(S ) can be obtained from S via the following rules. Being careful with parentheses when there is a complicated arrangement of clauses; NOT( x X : ϕ) is ( x X, NOT(ϕ)); NOT( x X, ϕ) is ( x X : NOT(ϕ)); NOT(NOT(ϕ)) is ϕ; NOT(ϕ or ψ) is (NOT(ϕ) and NOT(ψ)); NOT(ϕ and ψ) is (NOT(ϕ) or NOT(ψ)); NOT(ϕ = ψ) is (ϕ and NOT(ψ)). I m not a fan of rules. Rules exist because they are true for a reason. Thinking carefully about what your quantified sentences say will prevent you from negating incorrectly, and you should never apply the rules mindlessly. Remark The procedure for checking a sentence is false is now as follows. Negate the sentence. Verify that the negated sentence is true. Example The following sentence is false. Proof. The negation of the sentence is This is true, because we can verify it as follows. 1. Let n = 0. Notice n Z. n Z, (n > 10 = n > 10). n Z : (n > 10 and n 10).. Because 10 < 0 10, we see that (n > 10 and n 10) is true. Remark Notice that (n > 10 = n > 10) is true when n = 0 and when n = 0. However, what matters is that it is not true when n = 0. The quantifier n N ensures that the sentence in the example has one truth value. 13

14 4.7 Parentheses In this section I have used more parentheses than necessary so that you do not get confused. There is a convention that a quantifier automatically opens up parentheses. So x R, y R : x = y = 0 = 1 means x R, ( y R : ( )) x = y = 0 = 1. (This pointless sentence is true; can you prove it?) It does not mean ( ( )) x R, y R : x = y = 0 = 1. (This pointless sentence is false; can you prove it?) Because of this convention, the parentheses in ( ) a R \ {0}, b R, c R, x R : ax + bx + c = 0 = b 4ac 0 are necessary to distinguish it from a R \ {0}, b R, c R, x R : ax + bx + c = 0 = b 4ac 0. If you find yourself confused by some parentheses (or lack of them), ask for clarification. 4.8 Negating a sentence with parentheses carefully Example The negation of the sentence ( ) a R \ {0}, b R, c R, x R : ax + bx + c = 0 = b 4ac 0 is given by a R \ {0} : b R : c R : ( ) x R : ax + bx + c = 0 and b 4ac < 0. Example The negation of the sentence a R \ {0}, b R, c R, b 4ac 0 = ( ) x R : ax + bx + c = 0 is given by a R \ {0} : b R : c R : b 4ac 0 and ( ) x R, ax + bx + c Math 95 notes The first 7 pages of cover the previous material even more thoroughly. 14

15 5 Absolute value 5.1 Definition and basic properties Definition The absolute value function : R R is defined piecewise by { x if x 0 x = x if x < 0. Lemma x R, ( x 0 and x = x ). Proof. Left to you as preparation for the first quiz. Lemma x R, x x. Proof. 1. Let x R.. (a) Case 1: x 0. In this case, x = x. In particular, x x. (b) Case : x < 0. In this case, x < 0 < x = x. Corollary x R, x x x. Proof. 1. Let x R.. The previous lemma says x x. Since x R the previous lemma also says that x x. The first lemma says that x = x, so this gives x x and thus, x x. Remark P Q is shorthand for ((P = Q) and (Q = P )). P Q P = Q Q = P P Q T T T T T T F F T F F T T F F F F T T T Lemma x R, y R, x y y x y. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y R. 15

16 3. From the truth table for P Q, we see that we must show that it is not possible for exactly one of x y, y x y to be true. This time, we will do this by showing that whenever one of them is true, the other is also true. (a) Suppose x y is true. Then y x is true too. By using the previous corollary, we see that y x x x y is true; in particular, y x y is true. (b) Suppose that y x y is true. Then x y and x y are true. i. Case 1: x 0. We see that x = x y is true. ii. Case : x < 0. We see that x = x y is true. The following is the most important inequality in analysis. Theorem (The triangle inequality) x R, y R, x + y x + y. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y R. 3. By the previous lemma we have x x x. By the previous lemma we have y y y. Because of how inequalities work - you should think about such things more than I do since simple inequality mistakes on quizzes and finals make me furious - this gives x y x + y x + y, i.e. ( x + y ) x + y x + y. By the previous lemma we have x + y x + y. Corollary (The triangle inequality s cousin) x R, y R, x y x y. Proof. 1. Let x R.. Let y R. 3. A dirty trick and the triangle inequality show that x = (x y) + y x y + y. Thus, x y x y. Similarly, ( x y ) = y x y x = x y. The last lemma shows that x y x y. The trick used in this proof is very common. Remember it! Remark Inequalities involving the absolute values of expressions should only come from the application of one of the previous results or the following (trivial) result. x R \ {0}, y R \ {0}, x y 1 y 1 x. Anything else will look suspicious and will annoy me even if it happens to be true. 16

17 5. The point of the absolute value When you first learn about absolute values, you are told that they ignore the sign. This is true: for example, 7 = 7 and e = e. But what is the point of an absolute value? In analysis, they appear so frequently because they allow us to measure the distance between two numbers. What s the distance between a and b? Taking the difference of the numbers, a b, is a good start, but we do not care about the sign. Theorem The distance fuction defined by d(a, b) = a b has the following properties. ( ( )) 1. (positivity) a R, b R, d(a, b) 0 and d(a, b) = 0 a = b.. (symmetry) a R, b R, d(a, b) = d(b, a). 3. (triangle) a R, b R, c R, d(a, c) d(a, b) + d(b, c). b a c Proof. You can prove it if you want. We ll never need it explicitly. I just wanted to give you some context. 6 A little more about sets Definition 6.1. The empty set, written, is the set with no elements. Definition 6.. Given two sets X and Y, we say that X is a subset of Y and write X Y iff Remark 6.3. z, z X = z Y 1. In this definition iff stands for if and only if. This means that saying X is a subset of Y is exactly the same as saying the quantified sentence is true. Often, in definitions, mathematicians say if even though the meaning is iff. I normally do this, and I feel a little silly for writing iff, but I decided that it s the least confusing thing I can do. To make this iff feel different from a non-definitional iff I have used bold.. The quantified sentence is a little strange since we don t say where z lives; we just have z. Things become funny once you start talking about sets. Basically everything in math is a set in disguise, so this means for every mathematical thing z. Example 6.4. Suppose X is a set. Then X. 17

18 Proof. Let X be a set. We must check that the following sentence is true. 1. Let x be some mathematical thing. x, x = x X.. We must check the truth of (x = x X). Since has no elements, x is false. The truth table for = tells us that (x = x X) is true. Example 6.5. For any sets X and Y we have the following inclusions. 1. X X Y, Y X Y.. X Y X, X Y Y. 3. X Y X Y. Now we can improve our definition of two sets being equal. Definition 6.6. Suppose X and Y are sets. We say that X = Y iff X Y and Y X, i.e. iff the following sentence is true z, z X z Y. Example {0, 1} = {1, 0}.. {, } = {}. 3. { }. Finally, we record some commonly occuring sets. Definition 6.8 (Real intervals). Let a, b R. The following are called intervals. 1. (a, b) := {x R : a < x < b} [open interval];. [a, b] := {x R : a x b} [closed interval]; 3. (a, b] := {x R : a < x b} [half open interval]; 4. [a, b) := {x R : a x < b} [half open interval]; 5. (a, ) := {x R : a < x}; 6. [a, ) := {x R : a x}; 7. (, b) := {x R : x < b}; 8. (, b] := {x R : x b}; 9. (, ) := R. 18

19 Remark Read the symbol := as is defined to be. It is quite different from =, is equal to, which indicates that two previously defined entities are the same.. If you see any of the first four sets above, you can assume, unless otherwise stated, that a < b; this is because if a b, then these sets are either empty or consist of one element and so it is unlikely we ll want to consider these cases. 3. Although is used for notation in the above sets, it is not something that we will treat as a number. You can not plug it into an equation. will always require careful consideration and there will be careful definitions concerning it. It is often used as a notational device. 7 Sequences and the definition of convergence Black (1) then (1) white are () all I see (3) in my in-fan-cy, (5) red and yel-low then came to be (8)... Tool, Los Angeles, Sequences A sequence is what you think it is. Definition (Informal). A sequence is an infinite list of numbers. Here are some examples: 1,, 3, 4, 5,..., n,... 1, 1, 1 3, 1 4, 1 5,..., 1 n,... 1, 1, 1, 1, 1,..., ( 1) n,..., ( 3 ), ( 4 3 ) 3, ( 5 4 ) 4, ( 6 5) 5,..., ( n) n,... 1, 1,, 3, 5,..., F n = F n 1 + F n, , 1, 3, 5 3, 8 5,..., F n+1 F n,... 19

20 We frequently write s n for the n-th term in a sequence, and so we could express the first four sequences above, concisely, as s n = n, s n = 1 ( n, s n = ( 1) n, s n = 1 + n) 1 n. (Is there a formula for the n-th Fibonacci number which is not iterative? Can you find evidence of the Fibonacci sequence in the Tool song Lateralus, other than that highlighted in the quote at the start of the lecture?) Notation To indicate an abstract sequence we use parentheses: (s n ). Sometimes we may want to emphasize that the list is indexed by natural numbers and we write (s n ) n N. We might also write (s n ) n=1. It is convenient to be able to start a sequence with s m, where m might be greater than 1. In this case we write (s n ) n=m. So, for example, ( 1 n ) n=8 7. Convergence of sequences Here s our first major definition of the class. = 1 8, 1 9, 1 10, 1 11, 1 1,.... Definition Suppose (s n ) n=1 is a sequence. We say that (s n ) converges iff the following sentence is true. L R : ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = s n L < ɛ. Remark 7... The quanitifier ɛ > 0 is shorthand for ɛ (0, ). First, let me show you a sequence which converges and a sequence which does not converge, and proofs of those facts without any explanation of where the proofs come from. Theorem The sequence ( 1 n ) n=1 converges. Proof. By definition, we must verify that the following sentence is true. L R : ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = 1 n L < ɛ. 1. Let L = 0.. Let ɛ > Let N = 1 ɛ + 1. Here denotes the ceiling function. It rounds up to the nearest integer. For example, 5 = 3 = 3. This is useful frequently, so remember it. 4. Let n N. 0

21 5. We must verify the truth of (n N = 1 n L < ɛ). (a) Case 1: n < N. n N is false, so the truth table for = says (n N = 1 n L < ɛ) is true. (b) Case : n N. We must show that 1 n L < ɛ. We have N = 1 ɛ + 1 > 1 ɛ and also 1 n L = 1 n 0 = 1 n 1 N < ɛ. 7.3 Divergence of sequences Definition Suppose (s n ) n=1 is a sequence. We say that (s n ) diverges iff (s n ) does not converge, i.e. iff the following sentence is true. L R, ɛ > 0 : N N, n N : n N and s n L ɛ. Theorem The sequence (( 1) n ) n=1 diverges. Proof. By definition, we must verify that the following sentence is true. 1. Let L R.. Let ɛ = Let N N. L R, ɛ > 0 : N N, n N : n N and ( 1) n L ɛ. 4. (a) Case 1: L 0. Let n = N + 1. (b) Case : L < 0. Let n = N. 5. We must verify that (n N and ( 1) n L ɛ) is true. (a) Case 1: L 0. n = N + 1 = N + (N + 1) N. Also, (b) Case : L < 0. n = N = N + N N. Also, ( 1) n L = ( 1) N+1 L = 1 L = 1 + L 1 = ɛ. ( 1) n L = ( 1) N L = 1 L = 1 L 1 = ɛ. 1

22 7.4 How to spend your time In terms of your learning, your current goals should be as follows. Make sure you are happy with all of the quantifier verifications of the previous sections. Make sure you are happy with the correctness of the last two proofs given, even if you have no clue where the idea for them came from. Look at the previous two proofs. Figure out which parts of the proof are mindless, and will be the same for any sequence. Figure out which bits require thought. Think about these parts and see if you can figure out what thinking I did to come up with them. You should spend a long time on this step before going on to the next one, either until you think that you have figured it out, or until two hours has passed. Try and understand what the definition of convergence is saying. It is a wonderful and clever definition. It encodes everything you could ever want. You should spend a long time on this step before going on to the next one, either until you think that you have figured it out, or until two hours has passed. Read further and understand my description of where the proofs came from, and what the definition of convergence is saying.

23 7.5 Constructing the proof of theorem 7..3 Let s revisit theorem 7..3, the fact that ( 1 n ) n=1 converges. We must verify that the following sentence is true. L R : ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = 1 n L < ɛ. A lot of the proof is fairly mindless and it is likely that writing what follows is a step in the right direction. 1. Let L = BLAH.. Let ɛ > Let N = BLAH. 4. Let n N. 5. We must verify the truth of (n N = 1 n L < ɛ). (a) Case 1: n < N. n N is false, so the truth table for = says (n N = 1 n L < ɛ) is true. (b) Case : n N. We must show that 1 n L < ɛ. We have 1 n L =.... BLAH BLAH BLAH. We have to fill in the BLAHs. First, we must figure out what L is. What s the significance of L? I hope that after thinking about the definition of convergence and the proofs of theorem 7..3 long enough you will have come to the conclusion that L is supposed to be the limit of the sequence. Even if you have not parsed all the quantifiers just yet, you know that the condition s n L < ɛ says s n is within ɛ of L. The limit of a sequence is precisely the real number that the terms in a sequence get close to, so L has got to be the limit, right?! Let s take a minute to make a definition. Definition Suppose (s n ) n=1 is a sequence and L R. We say that (s n ) converges to L iff the following sentence is true. ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = s n L < ɛ. In this case L is said to be the limit of the sequence (s n ) and we will often express this by writing lim n s n = L or, if it is not confusing, lim s n = L. Remark If you look at the quantified sentence in the previous definition, you will see that L has not been quantified over. This is okay because L was declared in the preamble. By the time we state the quantified sentence, L is a constant real number. 3

24 . (a) If (s n ) converges, then there is some L R such that (s n ) converges to L. (b) If (s n ) converges to some L R, then (s n ) converges. These statements are trivial from the definitions, but in this early stage of analysis, you should check that you understand them 100%. 1 I hope that while taking math 31B or a similar class you were told that lim n n now proving this fact. This is the reason that I took L to be 0 in my proof. Now we can improve upon the beginning of the proof written above a little bit. = 0. We are 1. Let L = (b) Case : n N. We must show that 1 n L < ɛ. We have 1 n L = 1 n 0 = 1 n... Now to N. The purpose of N is to specify how far along in the sequence we have to go before terms in the sequence are within ɛ of the limit L. N will almost always depend on ɛ. If ɛ is small, N will almost always be large. Formulae like N = ɛ are stupid. In the case that we re considering we see that beyond N, 1 n is within 1 N of 0, and so we just need 1 N < ɛ, i.e. N > 1 ɛ. I ve decided to go back to my Oxford routes and demand that N be a natural number. The textbook says otherwise. Sorry about this. It ll be an exercise later to show that this choice doesn t matter. 1 ɛ + 1 is the simplest way to write down an explicit natural number bigger than 1 ɛ. We ve now completed the proof. 3. Let N = 1 ɛ (a) Case : n N. We must show that 1 n L < ɛ. We have N = 1 ɛ + 1 > 1 ɛ and also 1 n L = 1 n 0 = 1 n 1 N < ɛ. 4

25 7.6 Motivating the definition of convergence A picture is worth a thousand words. s N 5 s N 4 s N+1 L + ɛ L s N 3 L ɛ N A sequence of real numbers (s n ) converges to a real number L, the limit, if whenever a small positive quantity ɛ is specified by going far enough along in the sequence we ensure that the terms of the sequence differ from the limit by less than the small quantity specified. The first bullet point is said mathematically as ɛ > 0. The last two are said mathematically as follows. N N (there exists a number telling us how far we need to go) : n N, n N = (if we go this far along in the sequence) s n L < ɛ (then the terms of the sequence are within ɛ of L). 5

26 7.7 Another sequence that converges Theorem The sequence ( n 101 ) n=1 converges. n Before writing the proof let s think what it must look like. I hope that you can see that the limit of this sequence will be 0. Thus, our proof is going to look as follows. We must verify that the following sentence is true. L R : ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = n n 101 L < ɛ. 1. Let L = 0.. Let ɛ > Let N = BLAH. 4. Let n N. n 5. We must verify the truth of (n N = L < ɛ). n 101 (a) Case 1: n < N. n N is false, so the truth table for = says (n N = (b) Case : n N. We must show that BLAH BLAH BLAH. n n 101 L < ɛ. We have n n 101 L = n n 101 =.... n n 101 L < ɛ) is true. Now I get to say more about N. The clause N N : n N, n N = n n 101 < ɛ n says that < ɛ is true as long as n is sufficiently large, and N is a natural number quantifying n 101 exactly how large n needs to be. n n When considering the expression my first thought is is positive? The answer n 101 n 101 is, not necessarily, but as long as n is sufficiently large. We can improve on this and say that it is positive as long as n > 101. n N, n > 101 = n n 101 > 0. n n 101 We can now pretty much work under the assumption that positive. But by saying pretty much, I mean that we have to remember the conditions under which it actually holds: n >

27 My next thought is that proof would be n n 101 should behave somewhat like 1 n. A useful inequality towards a n N, n n n but this is UTTER NONSENSE!! In fact, the following sentence is true n N, n > 101 = The inequality goes the wrong way. Instead, we note that n N, n 0 = 0 n n n 101 > 1 n. n n 101 n (7.7.) This is because the condition 0 n 101 n is equivalent to 0 n by basic algebra. The idea I had here was 1 n doesn t give a correct inequality, but maybe n does. In the end, the made all the difference. We finally note that the following sentence is true. n N, n > ɛ = n < ɛ. (7.7.3) Equations (7.7.) and (7.7.3) suggest taking N = max{ 0, ɛ } + 1. Proof of theorem We must verify that the following sentence is true. L R : ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = n n 101 L < ɛ. 1. Let L = 0.. Let ɛ > Let N = max{ 0, ɛ } Let n N. n 5. We must verify the truth of (n N = L < ɛ). n 101 (a) Case 1: n < N. n N is false, so the truth table for = says (n N = n n 101 (b) Case : n N. Since N = max{ 0, ɛ } + 1 > 101, we have n > 101 and n 101 > 0. Since N = max{ 0, ɛ } + 1 > 0, we have n n 0 and n 101 n. Since N = max{ 0, ɛ } + 1 > ɛ, we have n > ɛ. Thus, n n 101 L = n n 101 = n n 101 n < ɛ. L < ɛ) is true. 7

28 7.8 Constructing the proof of theorem 7.3. Let s revisit theorem 7.3., the fact that (( 1) n ) n=1 diverges. We must verify that the following sentence is true. L R, ɛ > 0 : N N, n N : n N and ( 1) n L ɛ. A lot of the proof is fairly mindless and it is likely that writing what follows is a step in the right direction. 1. Let L R.. Let ɛ = BLAH. 3. Let N N. 4. Let n = BLAH. 5. We must verify that (n N and ( 1) n L ɛ) is true. BLAH. This looks tricky because ɛ is allowed to depend on L, and n is allowed to depend on L, ɛ, and N. That s a lot to juggle. It turns out that whenever (s n ) is a sequence, if and only if L R, ɛ > 0 : N N, n N : n N and s n L ɛ is true ɛ > 0 : L R, N N, n N : n N and s n L ɛ is true. This is quite a subtle fact, one which we will only be able to prove later on. For now, this simplifies things a little. It tells you that ɛ does not need to depend on L; that is the point in swapping the first two quantifiers. In the case of (( 1) n ) n=1, my intuition for choosing ɛ = 1 is the following. The clause N N, n N : n N and ( 1) n L ɛ says that however far along in the sequence we go, we can always find a term in the sequence which is ɛ or further away from L. We don t know what L is but we can think about how difficult it would be to prove that the sentence above is true for different Ls. Suppose L is 1. Then the even terms of the sequence are 0 away from L. However, the odd terms are away from L. This suggests taking ɛ =. Suppose L is 1. Then the odd terms of the sequence are 0 away from L. However, the even terms are away from L. This suggests taking ɛ =. Suppose L is 500. Then the odd terms of the sequence are 501 away from L and the even terms are 499 away from L. This continues to suggest that ɛ = would be a fine choice. 8

29 Suppose L is 0. Then all of the terms are 1 away from L. This suggests that ɛ = 1 would be a better choice. For the first three choices of L that we spoke about, we considered the even and odd terms separately. We did not have to do this for the choice L = 0. All of this hinted to me that considering the cases L 0 and L < 0 separately might be useful; there is some symmetry going on. Suppose L 0. Then the odd terms of the sequence are at least 1 away from L and this continues to suggest that ɛ = 1 would be a fine choice. Suppose L < 0. Then the even terms of the sequence are at least 1 away from L and this continues to suggest that ɛ = 1 would be a fine choice. All of the above reasoning suggests taking ɛ = 1. It also suggests that when specifying n we should break up into two cases, when L 0 and when L < 0. Our incomplete proof now becomes. 1. Let L R.. Let ɛ = Let N N. 4. (a) Case 1: L 0. Let n = BLAH. (b) Case : L < 0. Let n = BLAH. 5. We must verify that (n N and ( 1) n L ɛ) is true. (a) Case 1: L 0. BLAH. (b) Case : L < 0. BLAH. Let s consider how to choose n in the case that L 0. When L 0, the odd terms of the sequence are at least 1 away from L. This tells us we should choose n to be an odd number. We also want n to be bigger than or equal to N. N + 1 is an odd number bigger than or equal to N. When L < 0, the even terms of the sequence are at least 1 away from L. This tells us we should choose n to be an even number. We also want n to be bigger than or equal to N. N is an even number bigger than or equal to N. This allows us to fill in. 4. (a) Case 1: L 0. Let n = N + 1. (b) Case : L < 0. Let n = N. We are just left to complete step 5. By this point this is just a matter of writing down everything correctly. However, this step is important and I ll be annoyed when I see nonsense inequalities, or incorrect absolute values, so make sure you get things correct! 9

30 Remark At this point I may as well mention that my order of preference for a quiz or final solution is as follows. A complete and correct solution. An incomplete solution where nothing that is written is incorrect. In addition, separate ideas are given for completing the proof with difficulties highlighted. An incomplete solution where nothing that is written is incorrect. No idea on how to proceed. A solution which uses inequalities that are nonsense in the attempt of making the solution appear complete. This type of solution will be dealt with harshly. 30

31 7.9 The algebra of limits It is a little tedious to verify the definition of a convergent sequence every time we want to show that a sequence converges. In mathematics, we often prove theorems to save ourselves from having to do similar work over and over again. That is the purpose of the algebra of limits. It says things like, the sum of two convergent sequences is a convergent sequence. The first result in the algebra of limits which we will prove is the following. Theorem Suppose (s n ) n=1 is a sequence and s, c R. If (s n) converges to s, then (cs n ) n=1 converges to cs. We could also state this theorem by saying that the following sentence is true. Proof attempt. sequences (s n ) n=1, s R, c R, 1. Let (s n ) be a sequence.. Let s R. 3. Let c R. lim s n = s = n 4. We must verify the truth of (lim n s n = s = lim n cs n = cs). (a) Case 1: lim n s n = s is false. Trivial. lim cs n = cs. n (b) Case : lim n s n = s is true. We must show that lim n cs n = cs is true. Both of these expressions have a definition associated with them. So we can expand on this and say the following. The following sentence is true. ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = s n s < ɛ. (The use of ɛ and N will become clear in the next subsection.) We must show that the following sentence is true. ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = cs n cs < ɛ. We verify the truth of the last statement. i. Let ɛ > 0 ii. Let N = BLAH. iii. Let n N. iv. We must verify the truth of (n N = cs n cs < ɛ). A. Case 1: n < N. Trivial. B. Case : n N. In this case cs n cs = c s n s... BLAH. We have to fill in the BLAHs. How can we possibly write down an N if we have no idea what (cs n ) looks like? 31

32 7.10 The game and the computer program, finishing the proof of In earlier subsections we verified that some sequences converge. After figuring out the limit L of a sequence, this verification comes down to playing an ɛ-n game. The goal of the ɛ-n game is to figure out N in terms of ɛ, and it must be an N N making the relevant statement n N, n N = s n s < ɛ (7.10.1) true. When we wrote our proofs, we wrote them in the style of a computer program. The information that a sequence converges to a limit can be viewed as giving us such a computer program. If we give the computer program a postive real number ɛ, it will return a natural number N making the relevant statement (7.10.1) true. The key to completing the proof of theorem is to use such a computer program to specify an N. Completing the proof of theorem (b) i. Let ɛ > 0. ii. This is where the bulk of the argument happens. A. Let ɛ = ɛ 1+ c. Then ɛ > 0. B. Since ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = s n s < ɛ is true, we obtain an N N such that the following sentence is true. n N, n N = s n s < ɛ. C. Let N = N. iii. Let n N. iv. We must verify the truth of (n N = cs n cs < ɛ). A. Case 1: n < N. Trivial. B. Case : n N. Since N = N, we have n N, and so s n s < ɛ. Thus, cs n cs = c s n s c ɛ ɛ = c 1 + c < ɛ. Notice how algorithmically this proof is written. We say what ɛ is in terms of c and ɛ which were already declared in. and 4.(b)i., respectively. We obtain N from the computer program and ɛ which were already declared in 4.(b) and 4.(b)ii.A., respectively. We say what N is in terms of N which was declared in the step before. Finally, we check that everything works as it is supposed to. 3

33 7.11 Another algebra of limits proof, more game/computer program Let s see another similar example. Theorem Suppose (s n ) n=1 and (t n) n=1 are sequences, and that s, t R. If (s n) converges to s and (t n ) converges to t, then (s n + t n ) n=1 converges to s + t. We could also state this theorem by saying that the following sentence is true. Proof. 1. Let (s n ) be a sequence.. Let (t n ) be a sequence. 3. Let s R. 4. Let t R. sequences (s n ) n=1, sequences (t n ) n=1, s R, t R, ( ) lim s n = s and n lim t n = t n = lim n (s n + t n ) = s + t. 5. We must verify the truth of ( lim n s n = s and ) lim t n = t n = lim n (s n + t n ) = s + t. (a) Case 1: (lim n s n = s and lim n t n = t) is false. Trivial. (b) Case : (lim n s n = s and lim n t n = t) is true. We must show that lim n (s n + t n ) = s + t is true. Since all of these expressions have a definition associated with them, we can expand on this and say the following. The following sentence is true. ɛ 1 > 0, N 1 N : n N, n N 1 = s n s < ɛ 1. The following sentence is true. ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = t n t < ɛ. We must show that the following sentence is true. ɛ > 0, N N : n N, n N = (s n + t n ) (s + t) < ɛ. We verify the truth of the last statement. i. Let ɛ > 0. ii. This is where the bulk of the argument happens. A. Let ɛ 1 = ɛ. Then ɛ 1 > 0. B. Let ɛ = ɛ. Then ɛ > 0. 33

Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics, Part II

Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics, Part II Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics, Part II Michael Andrews UCLA Mathematics Department September 13, 2018 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Office hours / lecture?...................................

More information

Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics

Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics Math 95: Transition to Upper Division Mathematics Michael Andrews UCLA Mathematics Department September 6, 2017 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Class description...................................... 3 1.2

More information

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 1 Real Numbers In these lectures, we are going to study a branch of mathematics called

More information

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents Contents 1 1 Introduction 1 What is proof? 1 Statements, Definitions and Euler Diagrams 1 Statements 1 Definitions Our first proof Euler diagrams 4 3 Logical Connectives 5 Negation 6 Conjunction 7 Disjunction

More information

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide Algebra Exam Solutions and Grading Guide You should use this grading guide to carefully grade your own exam, trying to be as objective as possible about what score the TAs would give your responses. Full

More information

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271) Chapter 2 Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271) 2.1 Overview This chapter reviews proof techniques that were probably introduced in Math 271 and that may also have been used in a different way in Phil

More information

5.4 Continuity: Preliminary Notions

5.4 Continuity: Preliminary Notions 5.4. CONTINUITY: PRELIMINARY NOTIONS 181 5.4 Continuity: Preliminary Notions 5.4.1 Definitions The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language defines continuity as an uninterrupted succession,

More information

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras

CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, Boolean algebras CM10196 Topic 2: Sets, Predicates, oolean algebras Guy McCusker 1W2.1 Sets Most of the things mathematicians talk about are built out of sets. The idea of a set is a simple one: a set is just a collection

More information

3 The language of proof

3 The language of proof 3 The language of proof After working through this section, you should be able to: (a) understand what is asserted by various types of mathematical statements, in particular implications and equivalences;

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. IAN KIMING 1. Motivation. It will not come as a big surprise to anyone when I say that we need the real numbers in mathematics. More to the point, we need to be able to

More information

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S.

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S. 1 Notation For those unfamiliar, we have := means equal by definition, N := {0, 1,... } or {1, 2,... } depending on context. (i.e. N is the set or collection of counting numbers.) In addition, means for

More information

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Week 5 UCSB 204 The Integers Normally, using the natural numbers, you can easily define

More information

Math 115A: Linear Algebra

Math 115A: Linear Algebra Math 115A: Linear Algebra Michael Andrews UCLA Mathematics Department February 9, 218 Contents 1 January 8: a little about sets 4 2 January 9 (discussion) 5 2.1 Some definitions: union, intersection, set

More information

Quadratic Equations Part I

Quadratic Equations Part I Quadratic Equations Part I Before proceeding with this section we should note that the topic of solving quadratic equations will be covered in two sections. This is done for the benefit of those viewing

More information

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On Basics of Proofs The Putnam is a proof based exam and will expect you to write proofs in your solutions Similarly, Math 96 will also require you to write proofs in your homework solutions If you ve seen

More information

What is proof? Lesson 1

What is proof? Lesson 1 What is proof? Lesson The topic for this Math Explorer Club is mathematical proof. In this post we will go over what was covered in the first session. The word proof is a normal English word that you might

More information

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Written by Santiago Cañez These are notes which provide a basic summary of each lecture for Math 300, Foundations of Higher

More information

Math Lecture 3 Notes

Math Lecture 3 Notes Math 1010 - Lecture 3 Notes Dylan Zwick Fall 2009 1 Operations with Real Numbers In our last lecture we covered some basic operations with real numbers like addition, subtraction and multiplication. This

More information

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability

Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability Sequence convergence, the weak T-axioms, and first countability 1 Motivation Up to now we have been mentioning the notion of sequence convergence without actually defining it. So in this section we will

More information

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models Contents Mathematical Reasoning 3.1 Mathematical Models........................... 3. Mathematical Proof............................ 4..1 Structure of Proofs........................ 4.. Direct Method..........................

More information

2.2 Graphs of Functions

2.2 Graphs of Functions 2.2 Graphs of Functions Introduction DEFINITION domain of f, D(f) Associated with every function is a set called the domain of the function. This set influences what the graph of the function looks like.

More information

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH ) Contents 1 Sets 1 2 The Real Numbers 9 3 Sequences 29 4 Series 59 5 Functions 81 6 Power Series 105 7 The elementary functions 111 Chapter 1 Sets It is very convenient to introduce some notation and terminology

More information

Guide to Proofs on Sets

Guide to Proofs on Sets CS103 Winter 2019 Guide to Proofs on Sets Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz I would argue that if you have a single guiding principle for how to mathematically reason about sets, it would be this one: All sets

More information

Algebra. Here are a couple of warnings to my students who may be here to get a copy of what happened on a day that you missed.

Algebra. Here are a couple of warnings to my students who may be here to get a copy of what happened on a day that you missed. This document was written and copyrighted by Paul Dawkins. Use of this document and its online version is governed by the Terms and Conditions of Use located at. The online version of this document is

More information

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero

We are going to discuss what it means for a sequence to converge in three stages: First, we define what it means for a sequence to converge to zero Chapter Limits of Sequences Calculus Student: lim s n = 0 means the s n are getting closer and closer to zero but never gets there. Instructor: ARGHHHHH! Exercise. Think of a better response for the instructor.

More information

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities

Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Chapter 1 Review of Equations and Inequalities Part I Review of Basic Equations Recall that an equation is an expression with an equal sign in the middle. Also recall that, if a question asks you to solve

More information

Algebra & Trig Review

Algebra & Trig Review Algebra & Trig Review 1 Algebra & Trig Review This review was originally written for my Calculus I class, but it should be accessible to anyone needing a review in some basic algebra and trig topics. The

More information

Induction 1 = 1(1+1) = 2(2+1) = 3(3+1) 2

Induction 1 = 1(1+1) = 2(2+1) = 3(3+1) 2 Induction 0-8-08 Induction is used to prove a sequence of statements P(), P(), P(3),... There may be finitely many statements, but often there are infinitely many. For example, consider the statement ++3+

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Sequences and infinite series

Sequences and infinite series Sequences and infinite series D. DeTurck University of Pennsylvania March 29, 208 D. DeTurck Math 04 002 208A: Sequence and series / 54 Sequences The lists of numbers you generate using a numerical method

More information

Metric spaces and metrizability

Metric spaces and metrizability 1 Motivation Metric spaces and metrizability By this point in the course, this section should not need much in the way of motivation. From the very beginning, we have talked about R n usual and how relatively

More information

We have seen that the symbols,,, and can guide the logical

We have seen that the symbols,,, and can guide the logical CHAPTER 7 Quantified Statements We have seen that the symbols,,, and can guide the logical flow of algorithms. We have learned how to use them to deconstruct many English sentences into a symbolic form.

More information

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions Please read this pdf in place of Section 6.5 in the text. The text uses the term inverse of a function and the notation f 1

More information

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating HOW TO CREATE A PROOF ALLAN YASHINSKI Abstract We discuss how to structure a proof based on the statement being proved Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

More information

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018 CS 124 Math Review Section CS 124 is more math intensive than most of the introductory courses in the department. You re going to need to be able to do two things: 1. Perform some clever calculations to

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

1.4 Mathematical Equivalence

1.4 Mathematical Equivalence 1.4 Mathematical Equivalence Introduction a motivating example sentences that always have the same truth values can be used interchangeably the implied domain of a sentence In this section, the idea of

More information

Mathematical Statements

Mathematical Statements Mathematical Statements Joseph R. Mileti January 26, 2015 1 Mathematical Statements and Mathematical Truth Unfortunately, many people view mathematics only as complicated equations and elaborate computational

More information

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1)

Theorem. For every positive integer n, the sum of the positive integers from 1 to n is n(n+1) Week 1: Logic Lecture 1, 8/1 (Sections 1.1 and 1.3) Examples of theorems and proofs Theorem (Pythagoras). Let ABC be a right triangle, with legs of lengths a and b, and hypotenuse of length c. Then a +

More information

2.1 Convergence of Sequences

2.1 Convergence of Sequences Chapter 2 Sequences 2. Convergence of Sequences A sequence is a function f : N R. We write f) = a, f2) = a 2, and in general fn) = a n. We usually identify the sequence with the range of f, which is written

More information

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem Cosets and Lagrange s theorem These are notes on cosets and Lagrange s theorem some of which may already have been lecturer. There are some questions for you included in the text. You should write the

More information

Glossary of Logical Terms

Glossary of Logical Terms Math 304 Spring 2007 Glossary of Logical Terms The following glossary briefly describes some of the major technical logical terms used in this course. The glossary should be read through at the beginning

More information

Introduction to Algebra: The First Week

Introduction to Algebra: The First Week Introduction to Algebra: The First Week Background: According to the thermostat on the wall, the temperature in the classroom right now is 72 degrees Fahrenheit. I want to write to my friend in Europe,

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 013 Vazirani Note 1 Induction Induction is a basic, powerful and widely used proof technique. It is one of the most common techniques for analyzing

More information

The Basics COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. chapter. Algebra is a very logical way to solve

The Basics COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. chapter. Algebra is a very logical way to solve chapter 1 The Basics Algebra is a very logical way to solve problems both theoretically and practically. You need to know a number of things. You already know arithmetic of whole numbers. You will review

More information

Conceptual Explanations: Simultaneous Equations Distance, rate, and time

Conceptual Explanations: Simultaneous Equations Distance, rate, and time Conceptual Explanations: Simultaneous Equations Distance, rate, and time If you travel 30 miles per hour for 4 hours, how far do you go? A little common sense will tell you that the answer is 120 miles.

More information

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory 1 Introduction In mathematics, we seek absolute rigor in our arguments, and a solid foundation for all of the structures we consider. Here, we will see some

More information

Sequences of Real Numbers

Sequences of Real Numbers Chapter 8 Sequences of Real Numbers In this chapter, we assume the existence of the ordered field of real numbers, though we do not yet discuss or use the completeness of the real numbers. In the next

More information

Ordinary Differential Equations Prof. A. K. Nandakumaran Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Science Bangalore

Ordinary Differential Equations Prof. A. K. Nandakumaran Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Science Bangalore Ordinary Differential Equations Prof. A. K. Nandakumaran Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Science Bangalore Module - 3 Lecture - 10 First Order Linear Equations (Refer Slide Time: 00:33) Welcome

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF sequence of rational approximations to sets of rational approximating sequences, all with the same tail behaviour Definition 1.

CONSTRUCTION OF sequence of rational approximations to sets of rational approximating sequences, all with the same tail behaviour Definition 1. CONSTRUCTION OF R 1. MOTIVATION We are used to thinking of real numbers as successive approximations. For example, we write π = 3.14159... to mean that π is a real number which, accurate to 5 decimal places,

More information

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition

Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Supplementary Material for MTH 299 Online Edition Abstract This document contains supplementary material, such as definitions, explanations, examples, etc., to complement that of the text, How to Think

More information

MATH 131A: REAL ANALYSIS

MATH 131A: REAL ANALYSIS MATH 131A: REAL ANALYSIS NICKOLAS ANDERSEN The textbook for the course is Ross, Elementary Analysis [2], but in these notes I have also borrowed from Tao, Analysis I [3], and Abbott, Understanding Analysis

More information

For all For every For each For any There exists at least one There exists There is Some

For all For every For each For any There exists at least one There exists There is Some Section 1.3 Predicates and Quantifiers Assume universe of discourse is all the people who are participating in this course. Also let us assume that we know each person in the course. Consider the following

More information

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem These are notes on cosets and Lagrange s theorem; they go over some material from the lectures again, and they have some new material it is all examinable,

More information

The Inductive Proof Template

The Inductive Proof Template CS103 Handout 24 Winter 2016 February 5, 2016 Guide to Inductive Proofs Induction gives a new way to prove results about natural numbers and discrete structures like games, puzzles, and graphs. All of

More information

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ).

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ). Lecture 9: Conditional probability II: breaking complex events into smaller events, methods to solve probability problems, Bayes rule, law of total probability, Bayes theorem Discrete Structures II (Summer

More information

6 Cosets & Factor Groups

6 Cosets & Factor Groups 6 Cosets & Factor Groups The course becomes markedly more abstract at this point. Our primary goal is to break apart a group into subsets such that the set of subsets inherits a natural group structure.

More information

Writing Mathematical Proofs

Writing Mathematical Proofs Writing Mathematical Proofs Dr. Steffi Zegowitz The main resources for this course are the two following books: Mathematical Proofs by Chartrand, Polimeni, and Zhang How to Think Like a Mathematician by

More information

Study skills for mathematicians

Study skills for mathematicians PART I Study skills for mathematicians CHAPTER 1 Sets and functions Everything starts somewhere, although many physicists disagree. Terry Pratchett, Hogfather, 1996 To think like a mathematician requires

More information

An analogy from Calculus: limits

An analogy from Calculus: limits COMP 250 Fall 2018 35 - big O Nov. 30, 2018 We have seen several algorithms in the course, and we have loosely characterized their runtimes in terms of the size n of the input. We say that the algorithm

More information

Topic 1: Propositional logic

Topic 1: Propositional logic Topic 1: Propositional logic Guy McCusker 1 1 University of Bath Logic! This lecture is about the simplest kind of mathematical logic: propositional calculus. We discuss propositions, which are statements

More information

Solution to Proof Questions from September 1st

Solution to Proof Questions from September 1st Solution to Proof Questions from September 1st Olena Bormashenko September 4, 2011 What is a proof? A proof is an airtight logical argument that proves a certain statement in general. In a sense, it s

More information

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity Week 2 UCSB 204 Sizes of Infinity On one hand, we know that the real numbers contain more elements than the rational

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

Some Review Problems for Exam 1: Solutions

Some Review Problems for Exam 1: Solutions Math 3355 Fall 2018 Some Review Problems for Exam 1: Solutions Here is my quick review of proof techniques. I will focus exclusively on propositions of the form p q, or more properly, x P (x) Q(x) or x

More information

DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS

DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS Basic Concepts Paul Dawkins Table of Contents Preface... Basic Concepts... 1 Introduction... 1 Definitions... Direction Fields... 8 Final Thoughts...19 007 Paul Dawkins i http://tutorial.math.lamar.edu/terms.aspx

More information

Please bring the task to your first physics lesson and hand it to the teacher.

Please bring the task to your first physics lesson and hand it to the teacher. Pre-enrolment task for 2014 entry Physics Why do I need to complete a pre-enrolment task? This bridging pack serves a number of purposes. It gives you practice in some of the important skills you will

More information

In this initial chapter, you will be introduced to, or more than likely be reminded of, a

In this initial chapter, you will be introduced to, or more than likely be reminded of, a 1 Sets In this initial chapter, you will be introduced to, or more than likely be reminded of, a fundamental idea that occurs throughout mathematics: sets. Indeed, a set is an object from which every mathematical

More information

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ.

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ. 2008 Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ. All rights reserved. APPENDIX: Mathematical Proof There are many mathematical statements whose truth is not obvious. For example, the French mathematician

More information

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Goal Importance of proof Building up logic thinking and reasoning reading/using definition interpreting :

More information

Main topics for the First Midterm Exam

Main topics for the First Midterm Exam Main topics for the First Midterm Exam The final will cover Sections.-.0, 2.-2.5, and 4.. This is roughly the material from first three homeworks and three quizzes, in addition to the lecture on Monday,

More information

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT

27. THESE SENTENCES CERTAINLY LOOK DIFFERENT 27 HESE SENENCES CERAINLY LOOK DIEREN comparing expressions versus comparing sentences a motivating example: sentences that LOOK different; but, in a very important way, are the same Whereas the = sign

More information

In Which We Conclude Calculus by Using Taylor Series to Prove Euler s Identity Calculus 12, Veritas Prep.

In Which We Conclude Calculus by Using Taylor Series to Prove Euler s Identity Calculus 12, Veritas Prep. In Which We Conclude Calculus by Using Taylor Series to Prove Euler s Identity Calculus 12, Veritas Prep. 23 February 2011 Name: Directions: Feel free to use scrap paper if you need it. Show all your work

More information

Math Lecture 4 Limit Laws

Math Lecture 4 Limit Laws Math 1060 Lecture 4 Limit Laws Outline Summary of last lecture Limit laws Motivation Limits of constants and the identity function Limits of sums and differences Limits of products Limits of polynomials

More information

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring

Math Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring Math 135 - Precalculus I University of Hawai i at Mānoa Spring - 2013 Created for Math 135, Spring 2008 by Lukasz Grabarek and Michael Joyce Send comments and corrections to lukasz@math.hawaii.edu Contents

More information

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Goal Importance of proof Building up logic thinking and reasoning reading/using definition interpreting statement:

More information

Seunghee Ye Ma 8: Week 2 Oct 6

Seunghee Ye Ma 8: Week 2 Oct 6 Week 2 Summary This week, we will learn about sequences and real numbers. We first define what we mean by a sequence and discuss several properties of sequences. Then, we will talk about what it means

More information

Sets and Logic Linear Algebra, Spring 2012

Sets and Logic Linear Algebra, Spring 2012 Sets and Logic Linear Algebra, Spring 2012 There is a certain vocabulary and grammar that underlies all of mathematics, and mathematical proof in particular. Mathematics consists of constructing airtight

More information

irst we need to know that there are many ways to indicate multiplication; for example the product of 5 and 7 can be written in a variety of ways:

irst we need to know that there are many ways to indicate multiplication; for example the product of 5 and 7 can be written in a variety of ways: CH 2 VARIABLES INTRODUCTION F irst we need to know that there are many ways to indicate multiplication; for example the product of 5 and 7 can be written in a variety of ways: 5 7 5 7 5(7) (5)7 (5)(7)

More information

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works.

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works. Analysis I We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works. Copier s Message These notes may contain errors. In fact, they almost

More information

A Brief Introduction to Proofs

A Brief Introduction to Proofs A Brief Introduction to Proofs William J. Turner October, 010 1 Introduction Proofs are perhaps the very heart of mathematics. Unlike the other sciences, mathematics adds a final step to the familiar scientific

More information

CIS 2033 Lecture 5, Fall

CIS 2033 Lecture 5, Fall CIS 2033 Lecture 5, Fall 2016 1 Instructor: David Dobor September 13, 2016 1 Supplemental reading from Dekking s textbook: Chapter2, 3. We mentioned at the beginning of this class that calculus was a prerequisite

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Finite Mathematics : A Business Approach

Finite Mathematics : A Business Approach Finite Mathematics : A Business Approach Dr. Brian Travers and Prof. James Lampes Second Edition Cover Art by Stephanie Oxenford Additional Editing by John Gambino Contents What You Should Already Know

More information

( )( b + c) = ab + ac, but it can also be ( )( a) = ba + ca. Let s use the distributive property on a couple of

( )( b + c) = ab + ac, but it can also be ( )( a) = ba + ca. Let s use the distributive property on a couple of Factoring Review for Algebra II The saddest thing about not doing well in Algebra II is that almost any math teacher can tell you going into it what s going to trip you up. One of the first things they

More information

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers

Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers Predicates, Quantifiers and Nested Quantifiers Predicates Recall the example of a non-proposition in our first presentation: 2x=1. Let us call this expression P(x). P(x) is not a proposition because x

More information

chapter 12 MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA 12.1 Systems of Linear Equations GOALS

chapter 12 MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA 12.1 Systems of Linear Equations GOALS chapter MORE MATRIX ALGEBRA GOALS In Chapter we studied matrix operations and the algebra of sets and logic. We also made note of the strong resemblance of matrix algebra to elementary algebra. The reader

More information

CHAPTER 1: Functions

CHAPTER 1: Functions CHAPTER 1: Functions 1.1: Functions 1.2: Graphs of Functions 1.3: Basic Graphs and Symmetry 1.4: Transformations 1.5: Piecewise-Defined Functions; Limits and Continuity in Calculus 1.6: Combining Functions

More information

6: Polynomials and Polynomial Functions

6: Polynomials and Polynomial Functions 6: Polynomials and Polynomial Functions 6-1: Polynomial Functions Okay you know what a variable is A term is a product of constants and powers of variables (for example: x ; 5xy ) For now, let's restrict

More information

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009 1 Propositional Logic Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009 1.1 More efficient truth table methods The method of using truth tables to prove facts about propositional formulas can be a very tedious

More information

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston

HOW TO WRITE PROOFS. Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston HOW TO WRITE PROOFS Dr. Min Ru, University of Houston One of the most difficult things you will attempt in this course is to write proofs. A proof is to give a legal (logical) argument or justification

More information

Inference and Proofs (1.6 & 1.7)

Inference and Proofs (1.6 & 1.7) EECS 203 Spring 2016 Lecture 4 Page 1 of 9 Introductory problem: Inference and Proofs (1.6 & 1.7) As is commonly the case in mathematics, it is often best to start with some definitions. An argument for

More information

COLLEGE ALGEBRA. Paul Dawkins

COLLEGE ALGEBRA. Paul Dawkins COLLEGE ALGEBRA Paul Dawkins Table of Contents Preface... iii Outline... iv Preliminaries... 7 Introduction... 7 Integer Exponents... 8 Rational Exponents...5 Radicals... Polynomials...30 Factoring Polynomials...36

More information

Essentials of Intermediate Algebra

Essentials of Intermediate Algebra Essentials of Intermediate Algebra BY Tom K. Kim, Ph.D. Peninsula College, WA Randy Anderson, M.S. Peninsula College, WA 9/24/2012 Contents 1 Review 1 2 Rules of Exponents 2 2.1 Multiplying Two Exponentials

More information

Chapter III. Basic Proof Techniques. Proving the obvious has never been easy. Marty Rubin

Chapter III. Basic Proof Techniques. Proving the obvious has never been easy. Marty Rubin Chapter III Basic Proof Techniques Proving the obvious has never been easy. Marty Rubin The last two chapters were an introduction to the language of mathematics. Knowing the definitions and concepts of

More information

Lecture 6: Finite Fields

Lecture 6: Finite Fields CCS Discrete Math I Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 6: Finite Fields Week 6 UCSB 2014 It ain t what they call you, it s what you answer to. W. C. Fields 1 Fields In the next two weeks, we re going

More information

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist CS103 Winter 2019 Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz Now that we re transitioning to writing proofs about discrete structures like binary relations, functions, and graphs,

More information

Extensions to the Logic of All x are y: Verbs, Relative Clauses, and Only

Extensions to the Logic of All x are y: Verbs, Relative Clauses, and Only 1/53 Extensions to the Logic of All x are y: Verbs, Relative Clauses, and Only Larry Moss Indiana University Nordic Logic School August 7-11, 2017 2/53 An example that we ll see a few times Consider the

More information

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1.

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1. Chapter 3 Sequences Both the main elements of calculus (differentiation and integration) require the notion of a limit. Sequences will play a central role when we work with limits. Definition 3.. A Sequence

More information

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases September 22, 2018 Recall from last week that the purpose of a proof

More information