Borda count versus approval voting: A fuzzy approach

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Borda count versus approval voting: A fuzzy approach"

Transcription

1 Public Choice 112: , Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 167 Borda count versus approval voting: A fuzzy approach JOSÉ LUIS GARCÍA-LAPRESTA & MIGUEL MARTÍNEZ-PANERO Departamento de Economía Aplicada, Universidad de Valladolid, Valladolid, Spain; lapresta@cpd.uva.es Accepted 6 March 2001 Abstract. In this paper we consider a fuzzy variant of the Borda count taking into account agents intensities of preference. This fuzzy Borda count is obtained by means of score gradation and normalization processes from its original pattern. The advantages of the Borda count hold, and are even improved, providing an appropriate scheme in collective decision making. In addition, both classic and fuzzy Borda counts are related to approval voting, establishing a unified framework from distinct points of view. 1. Introduction Among the great variety of methods in collective decision making, in this paper we shall focus our attention on a variant of the Borda count, the vote-counting scheme introduced in 1770 by Jean Charles de Borda. 1 This engineer and navy officer denounced in a Memory read in the French Academy of Sciences that the usual collective decision procedures (such as plurality rule) only considered the most preferred alternative for each agent, ignoring the rest. Taking into account this partial information, the final output could not faithfully reflect the agents preferences. Borda showed examples with this fault, and then advocated the following method: each agent ranks all the alternatives, and gives integer marks to each of them: the highest score, which coincides with the number of alternatives, to the most preferred; one point less to the next alternative; and so on, in a descent manner, till the least preferred is reached, which is given only one point. This Borda count was chosen by the French Academy of Sciences to select its members and, from that time on, it has been both criticized and praised. Some advantages and drawbacks of the method can be shown according to procedural and epistemic arguments. This paper has been partially supported by the Consejería de Educación y Cultura de la Junta de Castilla y León (project VA09/98). The authors want to acknowledge the valuable comments of an anonymous referee.

2 168 Procedural arguments. The Spanish enlightened mathematician Morales (1797) already considered the Borda count as an straightforward and representative procedure, taking into account the information from the entire preference rankings of all the voters. 2 However, it was said that the Borda count did not respect the agents freedom of scoring and did not reflect the candidates merit with accuracy. This drawback was partially refuted in Morales (1805: 18 30), showing that, if the scale of values 0,1,2..., is used instead of 1,2,3..., to score the alternatives from the least to the most preferred, then the total score of a fixed alternative is the number of alternatives evaluated worse than it. This fact had already been pointed out by Borda and commented by Condorcet to ensure that the range of values used by the Borda count was not arbitrary (see McLean and Urken (1995: 81 89)). On the other hand, Condorcet censured the manipulability of this method 3 and was aware of the following fact: an alternative which defeats all others by simple majority in pairwise comparisons 4 might not be selected if the Borda count is used (see Black (1958: 156)). More recently, the non-fulfillment of the independence of irrelevant alternatives principle considered by Arrow (1963) has been added to the above-mentioned drawbacks. 5 Epistemic arguments. Dummett (1998: 290) has argued that the Borda count is the best tool for reaching the decision most likely to be correct when the object is to reconcile different judgements about effective means to a common aim, and the most equitable method of determining a resultant of divergent desires. 6 However, following the maximum likelihood estimation approach of Condorcet (1785), Young (1988) has shown that the voters competence level influences who the most probable winner in pairwise comparisons is. Assuming that the best candidate exists and that each voter will choose it with probability p, the candidate with the highest probability of being the best is the Borda winner only when p is sufficiently near 0.5. From a theoretical point of view, several characterizations of the Borda count have been obtained by Young (1974), Hansson and Sahlquist (1976), Nitzan and Rubinstein (1981), and Debord (1992), among others. Although Nitzan and Rubinstein (1981) consider non-transitive preferences over the alternatives, in this paper transitivity will be a coherence assumption needed to ensure reasonable Borda scores, as we shall show. The Borda rule has been re-examined many times, inspiring other collective decision making procedures. In 1882, Nanson (see McLean and Urken (1995: )) introduced a sort of Borda count with eliminations. Copeland (1951) considered Borda-type scores for each alternative, which were the

3 169 number of alternatives better than that marked minus the number of alternatives worse than it (see Saari and Merlin (1996)). Black (1958: 66) proposed a hybrid procedure consisting in the choice of the Condorcet winner, if it exists. Otherwise, Borda count should be used. Kemeny (1959) formuled a rule defined with arguments similar to those of the Borda rule (see Young, 1995: 61). Later on, Sen (1977) considered the so-called narrow and broad Borda count in connection with the independence of irrelevant alternatives principle. In addition, Dummett (1998) introduced the revised and adjusted Borda count to penalize the manipulability of the classic Borda count. In this paper the classic Borda count is considered and extended in a natural way to non-strict orderings, where the agents can declare indifference among distinct alternatives. This method will even be generalized by considering fuzzy preferences for the agents and not necessarily integer 7 scores over the alternatives. We note that Marchant (1996a, 1996b, 2000) has used this idea to design a fuzzy variant of the Borda count. However, this author deals with this procedure especially in connection with the PROMETHEE method in multi-criteria decision making. In the present paper, we have essentially come to a similar fuzzy Borda count, but in a collective decision making framework. On the other hand, our approach focuses on the underlying coherence hypotheses to ensure individual pairwise comparisons consistent with the marks given to the alternatives. In addition, the Borda count will be related to another collective decision making procedure with less tradition, but widely studied in recent years: approval voting. 8 This expression was first considered by Weber (1977) for a method whose fundamental impulse is due to Brams and Fishburn. With this procedure, agents can approve of as many alternatives as they wish; that is, as coined by the last mentioned authors: one man, n votes. Brams and Fishburn (1978, 1983) have also pointed out the main advantages of approval voting: more flexibility than other single vote methods, inhibition of abstention, legitimacy to the outcome, eminent practicability, etc. Other studies by the same authors show the difficulty to manipulate approval voting. There are some drawbacks of approval voting pointed out again by Brams and Fishburn (1983): loss of preference gradations allowed by several methods (such as Borda does); agents ambivalence; possibility of inequity among agents, depending on the number of approved alternatives, etc. On the other hand, Saari (1995: 181) has noted that approval voting shares undesirable properties as plurality voting (where agents choose only one alternative) and antiplurality voting (where agents choose necessarily all the alternatives except one of them). From a theoretical point of view, characterizations of approval voting have been given by Fishburn (1978), Sertel (1988) and Baigent and Xu (1991). And

4 170 different versions of approval voting have been proposed by Brams (1990), who consider a coinstrained approval voting by means of determining the number of approved alternatives from different categories of agents, and Ylmaz (1999) who considers an alternative voting method with three categories rather than two. On the other hand, Weber (1995) has revisited the subject of approval voting in connection with other procedures, the Borda count among others. As the title of this paper suggests, we shall also consider the Borda count in connection with approval voting, and a variant of the last method based on the gradual acceptance of the alternatives by the agents is also presented. The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we formalize the classic (discrete) Borda count. In Section 3 a fuzzy Borda count is defined. These Borda counts are connected with approval voting in Section 4. Finally, in Section 5, the results obtained are commented and a utilitarian view to the scores used is exposed. 2. The discrete Borda count At first, the Borda count was designed to score the alternatives sequentially, assuming the agents preferences to be strict orderings. This can be formalized and generalized in a natural way as follows. Let P 1,P 2,..., P m be the preference relations (binary asymmetric relations 9 ) of m agents over n alternatives x 1,x 2,...,x n. Each agent gives a mark to each alternative, according to the number of alternatives worse than it: r k (x i ) = #{x j x i P k x j } is the score given by agent k to the alternative x i. The same result is obtained by considering, for each agent k, its preference matrix: r k 11 rk rk 1n r k 21 rk rk 2n , r k n1 rk n2... rk nn where r k ij = { 1, if xi P k x j, 0, otherwise. In this way, the agent k gives the alternative x i the score:

5 171 r k (x i ) = n j = 1 x i P k x j r k ij We note that the possible score range is contained in the set of values {0, 1,...,,n 1}. Some of the upper values might not be reached if there is indifference (absence of preference) among distinct alternatives. However, if the orderings were strict, the above-mentioned set would exactly be ranged. With these individual counts a collective one is obtained: m r(x i ) = r k (x i ). k=1 So, the collective preference relation P B is defined by: x i P B x j r(x i )> r(x j ), which is negatively transitive. 10 Thus, the highest scored alternatives (maximals for P B ) will be chosen. Nevertheless, it is reasonable for the Borda count to require the fulfillment of the following property of monotonicity: when two alternatives are compared by an agent, the highest scored must be the preferred one. Definition 1. The count r k is monotonic if and only if for all pair of alternatives x i, x j X. x i P k x j r k (x i )>r k (x j ), Remark 1. It is easily seen that if the preference relation P k is transitive, then the count r k is monotonic. However, if P k is not transitive, then the count r k is not necessarily monotonic, as it is showed in the following example. Suppose a preference relation P k over 4 alternatives, explicitly given by: x 1 P k x 2, x 2 P k x 3, x 3 P k x 4, x 2 P k x 4.Thenr k (x 1 ) = 1 < r k (x 2 ) = 2, although, as pointed out, x 1 P k x A fuzzy Borda count In the classic Borda count the agents only consider which alternatives are preferred to the others. In this Section we present a natural extension of the classic Borda count by allowing the agents to show numerically how much some alternatives are preferred to the others, 11 evaluating their preference

6 172 intensities from 0 to 1. This is possible by considering fuzzy binary relations instead of ordinary binary relations. The following pre-requisites are introduced to formalize the fuzzy Borda counts. A fuzzy subset A of X is defined through its membership function, µ A : X [0, 1], whereµ A (x) is the membership grade of x to A. If µ A (x) = 1, then x belongs absolutely to A; if µ A (x) = 0, then x does not belong to A; and if 0 <µ A (x) <1, then x partly belongs to A (the closer µ A (x) is to 1, the more x belongs to A). Thus, the notion of fuzzy subset generalizes the concept of ordinary subset: a fuzzy subset A of X is ordinary if µ A (X) {0, 1}. According to the notion of fuzzy subset, a fuzzy binary relation on X is a fuzzy subset of X X. We shall consider a finite set of alternatives, X ={x 1,...,x n }, over each one of the m agents show their preferences by means of fuzzy binary relations R 1,...,R m.letµ R k : X X [0, 1] the membership function of R k, k = 1,...,m. The number r k ij = µ R k(x i, x j ) [0, 1] has been interpreted in the literature in two main ways (see García-Lapresta and Llamazares (2000: 675) for references). For some authors r k ij is understood as the degree of certainty or confidence with which agent k prefers (strictly or weakly) x i to x j. For other authors, r k ij denotes the intensity with which agent k prefers x i to x j. Our paper is based on this second viewpoint. Because of normalization reasons, for each agent, the total capacity to prefer between pairs of alternatives is considered to be unitary. It is also plausible to admit that however greater the intensity r ij with which x i is preferred to x j, the lower intensity r ji with which x j is preferred to x i will be. These considerations are contemplated in the following axiom of reciprocity, which will be assumed in our arguments. 12 Definition 2. A fuzzy binary relation R over X is reciprocal if and only if it is verified r ij + r ji = 1foralli, j {1,...,n}. Given the reciprocal fuzzy binary relation R k of the agent k, for each α [0, 1) an ordinary binary relation over X can be defined by x i k x j r k ij > α. However, k is an ordinary preference relation (i.e., asymmetric) only if α 0.5. In this case, the indifference relation associated with k is defined by x i k x j neither x i k x j nor x j k x i, i.e., r k ij α and r k ji α. By reciprocity, both conditions are equivalent to 1 α r k ij α. Then, for every pair of alternatives x i, x j, X one and only one of the following statements holds: x i k x j (r k ij >α),x i k x j (1 α r k ij α),x j k x i (r k ji >α, i.e., r k ij < 1 α). Among all possible thresholds α [0.5, 1) which ensure k to be an ordinary preference relation, in what follows we shall consider only the smaller threshold, α = 0.5. This election is supported by two considerations:

7 173 simplicity and the fact that, by reciprocity of R k, r k ij > r k ji is equivalent to r k ij > 0.5. Thus, choosing α = 0.5 todefine k, this ordinary binary relation show those alternatives somehow preferred by the agent k. Definition 3. For each agent k {1,...,m}, the reciprocal fuzzy binary relation R k induces an ordinary preference relation over X defined by x i k x j r k ij > 0.5, for all pair of alternatives x i, x j X. We note that for every pair of alternatives x i, x j X, one and only one of the following statements holds: x i k x j (r k ij > 0.5), x i k x j (r k ij = 0.5), x j k x i (r k ij < 0.5). Given R k, the reciprocal fuzzy preference relation of the agent k over X, we can consider the matrix of preference intensities: r k 11 rk rk 1n r k 21 rk rk 2n , r k n1 rk n2... rk nn where the symmetric entries respect the main diagonal add up to 1. For each agent k {1,...,m}, we shall define a new count to evaluate each alternative according to its preference intensities. In the discrete case, the value assigned by the individual count is the number of alternatives considered worse than it for an ordinary preference relation P k.now, analogously, this role will be played by the ordinary preference relation k induced by the reciprocal fuzzy binary relation R k. So, the introduced individual count will add up the preference intensities among the alternative and those considered worse according to k. Taking into account Definition 3, agent k gives the alternative x i the value n n r k (x i ) = r k ij = r k ij, j = 1 j = 1 x i k x j r k ij > 0.5 which coincides with the sum of the entries greater than 0.5 in the row i in the above matrix. Again, with these individual counts a collective one is obtained: m r(x i ) = r k (x i ). k=1

8 174 Now, the collective preference relation P FB is defined by x i P FB x j r(x i )> r(x j ), which is negatively transitive. Thus, the highest scored alternatives (maximals for P FB ) will be chosen. As we mentioned above, it could be possible to consider other Borda counts by choosing α>0.5 in the definition of k : r k (x i ) = n j = 1 x i k x j r k ij = n j = 1 r k ij >α r k ij. This voting procedure would require a greater support on the alternatives by the agents than the Borda count associated to α = 0.5 (only intensities greater than α would be taken into account). We note that if α>0.5, r k ij > r k ji and x i k x j would be possible simultaneously. We have to point out that the discrete Borda count gives individual scores belonging to the set {0, 1,...,n 1}, while the fuzzy Borda count takes its values in the interval [0, n 1], all intermediate values being possible. In this fuzzy framework we also consider a monotoniciy property, as in the discrete case: when two alternatives are compared by an agent, the highest score must be given to the preferred alternative according to k. Definition 4. The count r k is monotonic if and only if x i k x j r k (x i )>r k (x j ), for all pair of alternatives x i, x j X. According to the discrete case, one can believe that the count r k is monotonic if the ordinary preference relation k is transitive. However, as we shall show, this assumption is not sufficient. All the hypotheses of fuzzy coherence related below ensure the transitivity of k, but only the so-called weak max-max transitivity in the agents individual preferences implies the monotonicity of the count r k. Definition 5. Let properties: be a binary operation in [0, 1] with the following Commutativity: a b = b aforalla, b [0, 1]. Non-decreasing in each component: (a a and b b ) a b a b, for all a, a, b, b [0, 1]. Super-idempotency: a a aforalla [0, 1].

9 175 A reciprocal fuzzy binary relation R k over X is weak 13 max- transitive if and only if it is verified: (x i k x j and x j k x l ) r k il rk ij rk jl, for all x i, x j, x 1 X. Among the operations used in the literature to modelize the agents rationality, the following ones, proposed by Zadeh (1971) and Bezdek and Harris (1978), among others, are considered: a 1 b = min{a, b}, a 2 b = a + b 2, a 3 b = max{a, b}. Definition 6. T i (X) denotes the set of reciprocal fuzzy binary relations verifying weak max- i transitivity, for i = 1, 2, 3. Remark 2. Taking into account that for all a, b [0, 1]] it is verified min{a, b} a + b 2 then max{a, b} and (a > 0.5, b > 0.5) min{a, b} > 0.5, R k T 3 (X) R k T 2 (X) R k T 1 (X) k transitive. In the following result we show that, under the coherence assumption related to T 3 (X), the agents will assign scores to the alternatives in a monotonic way. We note that when a fuzzy relation R k belongs to T 3 (X), drops in the levels of preference are not allowed if agent k compares linked alternatives x i, x j, x l, each one subject to being strictly preferred to the next (according to k ). More specifically, we mean that r k il, the intensity with which k prefers x i to x l, ought to be greater than or equal to both r k ij and r k jl, the preference intensities of k for x i over x j,andforx i over x l, respectively (if these last two values are supposed to be greater than 0.5). Proposition. If R k T 3 (X), then the count r k is monotonic. Proof. For each i {1,...,n} consider the set P(i) = {l r k il > 0.5} {1,...,n}. Thus r k (x i ) = r k il and r k (x j ) = r k jl. Suppose x i k x j, l P(i) l P(j) i.e., r k ij > 0.5. Then P(j) P(i) is verified: if l P(j), thenr k jl > 0.5 By hypothesis, r k ij > 0.5; consequently r k il max{r k ij, rk jl } > 0.5 andsol P(i). What is more, this inclusion is strict, because r k ij > 0.5 implies j P(i),

10 176 while j / P(j) since by reciprocity r k jj = 0.5. Now, if l P(j) P(i), then r k il max {rk ij, rk jl } rk jl and, consequently, r k(x i )>r k (x j ). Remark 3. If R k T 1 (X) or R k T 2 (X), thenr k is not necessarily monotonic, as is shown in the following example. Let R k be the reciprocal fuzzy binary relation over X ={x 1, x 2, x 3, x 4, x 5 } whose matrix is: It is easy to verify R k T 2 (X) and, taking into account Remark 3, also R k T 1 (X). Note that x 1 k x 2, because r k 12 = 0.52 > 0.5. Nevertheless, r k (x 1 ) = = 2.95 < = 3 = r k (x 2 ). A notable advantage of the fuzzy Borda count with respect to the classic Borda count is the agents possibility to show their preferences more faithfully. So, if an agent prefers x i to x j with a weak level of intensity, for instance 0.6, in the classic Borda count that agent must declare the extreme level of intensity 1, the same value as if the agent preferred x i to x j absolutely. No kind of intermediate intensity can be shown, only 0 or 1. However, in the fuzzy Borda count every agent can declare the real intensity of preference between each pair of alternatives. These aspects appear in the following example. Example. Suppose two agents whose preference intensities over a set of two alternatives X ={x 1, x 2 } are given by the matrices associated to R 1 and R , , respectively. We note that R 1, R 2 T 3 (X). If these agents had to show their preferences in a crisp manner in order to give classic Borda scores, they would only take into account those alternatives somehow preferred to the others, i.e., with a intensity of preference greater than 0.5 in pairwise comparisons. That is, they switch from their fuzzy preference relations R k to the ordinary associated preference relations k, k = 1, 2. Thus, each level of intensity greater than 0.5 becomes 1, and each value less than or equal to 0.5 becomes 0, and the matrices above would change to

11 , We note that with the classic Borda count we obtain r(x 1 ) = 2, r(x 2 ) = 3, r(x 3 ) = 1, and the second alternative would be the winner. However, with the matrices of preference intensities the fuzzy Borda count gives r(x 1 ) = 1.9, r(x 2 ) = 1.8, r(x 3 ) = 0.6, and the first alternative will be the winner. There is no paradox in the discordance: the second way takes into account more accurate information and the result may differ with respect to the binary data provided by the classic Borda count. As commented in Section 1, the use of integers to score the alternatives by means of the Borda count was already criticized in the XVIII th century. Since then, such marks have been partially justified in several ways, but it seems to us that the main adverse argument remains: the lack of freedom to score the alternatives according to the real agents preference intensities. Thus, with the fuzzy Borda method, the principal advance would be the gradation allowed the agents in their scores, and hence, a more faithful adherence to their true estimations. There is one more step in terms of representation: not only are all the alternatives considered in agents preferences (this already occurs with the Borda count with respect to plurality rule); now, while maintaining this equitable quality, the alternatives are taken into account in a more accurate way than in the classic Borda method. We note that the fuzzy Borda count shares the same drawbacks as the discrete one: non-fulfillment of the independence of irrelevant alternatives principle and manipulability. In this last aspect, the above arguments about gradation of the scores have a clear incidence in more extensive way than the one pointed out by Morales (1797: 42) (see McLean and Urken (1995: )). Thus, when agents hide their true preferences in order to favor one alternative against other, in the majority rules they do not vote for this alternative (in score terms, they switch from 1 to 0); in the classic Borda count they can reduce their individual scores (for example from m to m 1 or m 2, etc.) in a descent integer manner. However, in the fuzzy Borda count they are not constrained in their assessments (true or false) by the modality of the scores.

12 Approval voting: From binary to gradual assessments Up to now the agents scores given by means of Borda counts are a consequence of their pairwise preferences (crisp or fuzzy) over the alternatives. Another way in collective decision making is that suggested by the approval voting procedure. In this method, we consider that the agents assess at the alternatives one by one, using what we call approval counts, inacrispor fuzzy manner. In the first one, each alternative is approved or disapproved absolutely by each agent. In the second manner, the individual decision is more precise, estimating the agent s level of resolution. In both cases the individual agent s results are added up together in order to obtain the final decision. These fuzzy approval counts are formalized below. Again, it is considered a finite set of alternatives X ={x 1,...,x n } to be evaluated by each of the m agents. With the discrete approval count, each agent accepts each alternative or not, as many as wanted. This can be formalized by defining the binary index: { r k 1, if the alternative xi is approved by the agent k, i = 0, if the alternative x i is disapproved by the agent k. r 1 r r m 1 Thus, the matrix r 1 2 r r m is defined, and each alternative is given r 1 n r 2 n... r m n the sum of individual scores: r(x i ) = m r k i is the total score obtained by the k=1 alternative x i, which coincides with the sum of the entries of the i-th row. As in the Borda count, this scoring defines a collective preference relation x i P A x j r(x i )>r(x j ), which is negatively transitive. The highest scored alternatives (maximals for P A ) will be chosen. The fuzzy approval count is defined in a parallel manner. Each agent estimates the level of acceptance over each alternative as follows. Let r k i [0, 1] be the approval estimation given by the agent k to the alternative x i,and dispose these indices as entries in the scoring matrix r 1 1 r r m 1 r 1 2 r r m r 1 n r 2 n... r m n. Again, we can define, for each alternative x i, the sum of individual scores: r(x i ) = m is the total score obtained by x i, which coincides with the r k i k=1

13 179 sum of the values of the i-th row. Thus, a collective preference relation can be defined by x i P FA x j r(x i )>r(x j ), which is once more negatively transitive. The highest scored alternatives (maximals for P FA ) will be chosen. In order to compare fuzzy Borda count and fuzzy approval voting, we can associate each agent k with a fuzzy binary relation and a fuzzy subset, respectively: In the fuzzy Borda count, µ R k : X X [0, 1], the membership function of the fuzzy binary relation R k of agent k, assigns each pair of alternatives (x i, x j ) the index r k ij = µ R k(x i, x j ), the degree of preference with which the agent k prefers x i to x j. In the fuzzy approval voting, µ Ak : X [0, 1], the membership function of the fuzzy subset A k of approved alternatives in X for agent k, assigns each alternative x i the index r k i = µ Ak (x i ), the degree of acceptance of x i for the agent k. We have to point out the following fact about the ranges of the marks used. While the discrete approval count gives total scores belonging to the set {0, 1,...,m}, the fuzzy approval count does so in the interval [0, m], all the intermediate values being reachable. And then, the last mentioned decision making procedure also provides more flexibility to the agents. As a result, the existence of ties is less likely in the maximum total scores (which are maximals according to the collective preference relation defined in each case) if fuzzy counts are used instead of the discrete ones. Nevertheless, if it happens, procedures to break the ties must be established. The mentioned comment is also applicable to the fuzzy Borda count with respect to the discrete Borda count. 5. Concluding remarks The two voting procedures introduced in the paper, fuzzy Borda count and fuzzy approval voting, use more complex information than classic Borda count and approval voting. While in the classic procedures only 0 s and 1 s should be added as individual marks in pairwise comparisons or individual assessments, in the fuzzy procedures any number from 0 to 1 could appear. In the fuzzy approval voting each voter assigns a value from 0 to 1 to each alternative. Adding up the values that voters give to the alternatives, we obtain the winner(s). Consequently, no essential differences between putting in practice original and fuzzy approval voting appear. In the fuzzy Borda count each voter has to show the intensities of preference between all the pairs of alternatives by means of values from 0 to 1. In practice, every agent must first compare each pair of alternatives showing

14 180 Table 1. Possible marks for n alternatives, m agents Count Borda Approval Discrete Individual {0,...,n 1} Individual {0, 1} step = 1 step = 1 Total {0,...,m(n 1)} Total {0,...,m} step = 1 step = 1 Fuzzy Individual [0, n 1] Individual [0, 1] no step no step Total [0, m(n 1)] Total [0, m] no step no step preference for one over the other; otherwise, the agent is indifferent to both alternatives (in this case, the agent gives 0.5 points to each alternative). If the agent prefers one alternative to the other, then the agent must show the intensity of preference (a number greater than 0.5 and less than or equal to 1). When all the information provided by the agents is collected in the corresponding matrices, then the total score of an alternative is obtained adding up the values greater than 0.5 in the entries of the corresponding row of the agents matrices. The alternative(s) with the highest score will be the winner(s). All this process can be implemented with computer assistance. This is the case of MACBETH, a decision procedure developed in a similar framework to the fuzzy Borda count (see Bana e Costa and Vansnick (1997)). We note that MACBETH and its software consider linguistic labels instead of numbers in the assessments of pairwise comparisons. In Table 1 possible ranges of values appear, individual as well as total, of the considered counts. It is possible to unify the amplitude of the individual scores in Borda and approval counts by dividing these individual scores by n 1. So, the scale changes, but not the ordering, and then the scores range from 0 to 1 with step 1 n 1 in the discrete case, and continuously in the interval [0, 1] in the fuzzy one. When these normalized individual scores are added up, total possible values are obtained from 0 to m with the same step as in the discrete case, and again continuously in the interval [0, m] in the fuzzy one. It is also feasible to unify the variation amplitude of the individual and total scores, so that both of them will vary from 0 to 1. To do this, we normalize again by dividing the total scores by the number of agents, m. That is

15 181 to say, individual scores are aggregated in a collective one as an arithmetic mean. 14 In this way, Table 2 is obtained. Table 2. Possible marks for n alternatives, m agents Count Normalized Normalized Borda approval Discrete Individual {0,...,1} Individual {0, 1} step = m 1 1 step = 1 Total {0,...,1} Total {0,...,1} step = 1 m(n 1) step = m 1 Fuzzy Individual [0, 1] Individual [0, 1] no step no step Total [0, 1] Total [0, 1] no step no step One can observe by examining Table 2 that discrete counts are particular cases of the fuzzy ones, where marks are scaled in the unit interval. As for the fuzzy Borda and approval counts, the marks obtained are the same, although corresponding to distinct conceptions in each case, as pointed out earlier. The marks used in the counts appearing in this paper admit a utilitariancardinal perspective, as pointed out by Black (1976), Sugden (1981) and recently by Marchant (2000). The total score obtained by the alternatives can be understood as defined by a collective utility function U : X [0, 1], such that U(x i ) = u 1(x 1 ) + u 2 (x i ) + +u m (x i ), m where u j (x i ) [0, 1] are the normalized scores which are aggregated through the arithmetic mean, as indicated. Notes 1. Historical background can be found in Black (1958: ) and McLean and Urken (1995: 94 97). These last two authors have also indicated that Nicolaus Cusanus (XV th c.) foresaw the idea of the Borda count (see McLean and Urken (1995: 19 23)). 2. Black (1958, 1976), Mueller (1979) and Straffin Jr. (1980), among others, have noted that the Borda count chooses the alternative which stands highest on average in the agents preference orderings.

16 About this great weakness of voting procedures in connection with the Borda count, see Black (1976), Ludwin (1978), Sen (1984) and Dummet (1998), among others. 4. This alternative, if it exists, is called the Condorcet winner. 5. Again, Condorcet anticipated Arrow s independence of irrelevant alternatives principle. See McLean (1995) and McLean and Urken (1995: 32 34). 6. This viewpoint of Dummet can be supported by the distance-based consensus ideas of disagreement minimization appearing in Cook and Seiford (1982). On the other hand, Biswas (1994) considers efficiency and consistency reasons related to the Borda count. 7. We have just pointed out the arguments of Morales and Borda to justify integer value scale of the Borda count as the number of times each alternative is preferred pairwise to each other. Laplace, on his own, obtained this spectrum of scores by means of probabilistictype arguments based on the agents latent estimates, recently re-formulated by Tanguiane (1991: 80 and ff.) and Tangian (2000), who already suggest the fuzzy counts introduced in this paper. Laplace s arguments also appear in Basset Jr. and Perski (1999). 8. The system used to elect the Venetian Dux anticipates approval voting. See Lines (1986) and McLean and Urken (1995: 22). 9. A binary relation P is asymmetric if x i Px j implies not x j Px i. 10. An ordinary preference relation P is negatively transitive if, not being verified x i Px j nor x j Px k, then does not satisfy x i Px k. This definition, widely used in the literature of preference modeling, is equivalent to other more intuitive statements. So, an asymmetric binary relation P is negatively transitive if and only if R, the weak preference relation associated with P (x i Rx j if not x j Px i ) is transitive. And both statements are equivalent to the transitivity of P and I, the indifference relation associated with P and R (x i Ix j can be defined by no x i Px j nor x j Px i, or equivalently by x i Rx j and x j Rx i ). 11. This idea appears implicitly in Morales (1797, 1805) and in Condorcet s comments to the Memory of Borda (see McLean and Urken (1995: 81 89)). 12. To justify the axiom of reciprocity see, among others, Bezdek, Spillman and Spillman (1978), Nurmi (1981) and García-Lapresta and Llamazares (2000). 13. Max- transitivity for R k is initially defined by demanding r k il r k ij rk jl. Weak (or restricted ) conditions are considered by Tanino (1984) and Dasgupta and Deb (1996), among others, when certain additional hypotheses are required. In our case, these are to consider preference intensities in Definition 5 greater than About the arithmetic mean as an aggregation procedure, see Chichilnisky and Heal (1983), Le Breton and Uriarte (1990), Candeal, Induráin and Uriarte (1992), Candeal and Induráin (1995), Quesada (2000) and García-Lapresta and Llamazares (2000). References Arrow, K.J. (1963). Social choice and individual values. 2nd edition. New York: Wiley. Baigent, N. and Xu, Y. (1991). Independent necessary and sufficient conditions for approval voting. Mathematical Social Sciences 21: Bana e Costa A. and Vansnick J.C. (1997). The MACBETH approach: Basic ideas, software, and an application. In N. Meskens and M. Roubens (Eds.), Advances in decision analysis, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Basset Jr., G.W. and Perski, J. (1999). Robust voting. Public Choice 99: Bezdek, J.C. and Harris, J.D. (1978). Fuzzy partitions and relations: An axiomatic basis for clustering. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 1:

17 183 Bezdek, J.C., Spillman, B. and Spillman, R. (1978). A fuzzy relation space for group decision theory. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 1: Biswas, T. (1994). Efficiency and consistency in group decisions. Public Choice 80: Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. London: Cambridge University Press. Black, D. (1976). Partial justification of the Borda count. Public Choice 28: Brams, S.J. (1990). Constrained approval voting: A voting system to elect a governing board. New York: New York Economic Research Reports. Brams, S.J. and Fishburn, P.C. (1978). Approval voting. American Political Science Review 72: Brams, S.J. and Fishburn, P.C. (1983). Approval voting. Boston: Birkhäuser. Candeal, J.C. and Induráin, E. (1995). Aggregation of preferences from algebraic models on groups. Social Choice and Welfare 12: Candeal, J.C., Induráin, E. and Uriarte, J.R. (1992). Some issues related to the topological aggregation of preferences. Social Choice and Welfare 9: Chichilnisky, G. and Heal, G. (1983). Necessary and sufficient conditions for a resolution of the social choice paradox. Journal of Economic Theory 31: Cook, W.D. and Seiford, L.M. (1982). On the Borda-Kendall consensus method for priority ranking problems. Management Science 28: Copeland, A.H. (1951). A reasonable social welfare function. Mimeo. Notes from a seminar on applications of mathematics to the social sciences, University of Michigan. Dasgupta, M. and Deb, R. (1996). Transitivity and fuzzy preferences. Social Choice and Welfare 13: Debord, B. (1992). An axiomatic characterization of Borda s k-choice function. Social Choice and Welfare 9: Dummett, M. (1998). The Borda count and agenda manipulation. Social Choice and Welfare 15: Fishburn, P.C. (1978). Axioms for approval voting: direct proof. Journal of Economic Theory 19: Corrigendum (1988) 45: 212. García-Lapresta, J.L. and Llamazares, B. (2000). Aggregation of fuzzy preferences: Some rules of the mean. Social Choice and Welfare 17: Hansson, B. and Sahlquist, H. (1976). A proof technique for social choice with variable electorate. Journal of Economic Theory 13: Kemeny, J. (1959). Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88: Le Breton, M. and Uriarte, J.R. (1990). On the robustness of the impossibility result in the topological approach to Social Choice. Social Choice and Welfare 7: Lines, M. (1986). Approval voting and strategic analysis: A venetian example. Theory and Decision 20: Ludwin, W.G. (1978). Strategic voting and the Borda method. Public Choice 33: Marchant, T. (1996a). Agrégation de relations valuées par la méthode de Borda en vue d un rangement. Considérations axiomatiques. Ph.D. Thesis, Université Libre de Bruxelles. Marchant, T. (1996b). Valued relations aggregation with the Borda method. Journal of Multi- Criteria Decision Analysis 5: Marchant, T. (2000). Does the Borda Rule provide more than a ranking? Social Choice and Welfare 17: McLean, I. (1995). Independence of irrelevant alternatives before Arrow. Mathematical Social Sciences 30: McLean, I. and Urken, A.B. (eds.) (1995). Classics of Social Choice. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

18 184 Morales, J.I. (1797). Memoria Matemática sobre el Cálculo de la Opinion en las Elecciones. Madrid: Imprenta Real. English version in McLean and Urken (1995: ). Morales, J.I. (1805). Apéndice á la Memoria Matemática sobre el Cálculo de la Opinion en las Elecciones. Madrid: Imprenta de Sancha. Mueller, D.C. (1979). Public choice. London: Cambridge University Press. Nitzan, S. and Rubinstein, A. (1981). A further characterization of Borda ranking method. Public Choice 36: Nurmi, H. (1981). Approaches to collective decision making with fuzzy preference relations. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 6: Quesada, A. (2000). Manipulability, anonimity and merging functions. Social Choice and Welfare 17: Saari, D.G. (1995). Basic geometry of voting. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Saari, D.G. and Merlin, V.R. (1996). The Copeland method I: Relationships and the dictionary. Economic Theory 8: Sen, A.K. (1977). Social choice theory: A re-examination. Econometrica 45: Sen. A.K. (1984). Strategy-proofness of a class of Borda rules. Public Choice 43: Sertel, M.R. (1988). Characterizing approval voting. Journal of Economic Theory 45: Straffin Jr., P.D. (1980). Topics in the theory of voting. Boston: Birkhäuser. Sugden, R. (1981). The political economy of public choice: An introduction to welfare economics. Oxford: Martin Robertson. Tangian, A.S. (2000). Unlikelihood of Condorcet s paradox in a large society. Social Choice and Welfare 17: Tanguiane, A.S. (1991). Aggregation and representation of preferences. Introduction to mathematical theory of democracy. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Tanino, T. (1984). Fuzzy preference orderings in group decision making. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 12: Weber, R.J. (1977). Comparison of voting systems. Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No Cowles Foundation, Yale University. Weber, R.J. (1995). Approval voting. Journal of Economic Perspectives 9: Ylmaz, M.R. (1999). Can we improve upon approval voting? European Journal of Political Economy 15: Young, H.P. (1974). An axiomatization of Borda s rule. Journal of Economic Theory 9: Young, H.P. (1988). Condorcet s theory of voting. American Political Science Review 82: Young, H.P. (1995). Optimal voting rules. Journal of Economic Perspectives 9: Zadeh, L.A. (1971). Similarity relations and fuzzy orderings. Information Sciences 22:

A general class of simple majority decision rules based on linguistic opinions

A general class of simple majority decision rules based on linguistic opinions A general class of simple majority decision rules based on linguistic opinions José Luis García-Lapresta Dept. de Economía Aplicada (Matemáticas), Universidad de Valladolid Avda. Valle de Esgueva 6, 47011

More information

Collective transitivity in majorities based on difference in support

Collective transitivity in majorities based on difference in support Collective transitivity in majorities based on difference in support Bonifacio Llamazares a,, Patrizia Pérez-Asurmendi b, José Luis García-Lapresta a a PRESAD Research Group, IMUVA, Dep. of Applied Economics,

More information

A DISTANCE-BASED EXTENSION OF THE MAJORITY JUDGEMENT VOTING SYSTEM

A DISTANCE-BASED EXTENSION OF THE MAJORITY JUDGEMENT VOTING SYSTEM A DISTANCE-BASED EXTENSION OF THE MAJORITY JUDGEMENT VOTING SYSTEM EDURNE FALCÓ AND JOSÉ LUIS GARCÍA-LAPRESTA Abstract. It is common knowledge that the political voting systems suffer inconsistencies and

More information

Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making

Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making Paper: jc*-**-**-**** Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making José Luis García-Lapresta PRESAD Research

More information

Triple-acyclicity in majorities based on difference in support

Triple-acyclicity in majorities based on difference in support MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Triple-acyclicity in majorities based on difference in support Bonifacio Llamazares and Patrizia Pérez-Asurmendi University of Valladolid 01 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/518/

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Volume 31, Issue 1 Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Abstract In an election contest, a losing candidate a can manipulate

More information

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice *

The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * The Beach Party Problem: An informal introduction to continuity problems in group choice * by Nick Baigent Institute of Public Economics, Graz University nicholas.baigent@kfunigraz.ac.at Fax: +44 316 3809530

More information

Preference aggregation and DEA: An analysis of the methods proposed to discriminate efficient candidates

Preference aggregation and DEA: An analysis of the methods proposed to discriminate efficient candidates Preference aggregation and DEA: An analysis of the methods proposed to discriminate efficient candidates Bonifacio Llamazares, Teresa Peña Dep. de Economía Aplicada, PRESAD Research Group, Universidad

More information

Inequality of Representation

Inequality of Representation Inequality of Representation Hannu Nurmi Public Choice Research Centre University of Turku Institutions in Context: Inequality (HN/PCRC) Inequality of Representation June 3 9, 2013 1 / 31 The main points

More information

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes Stanford University ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit/lmh Fall, 2008 :, 1 The Voting Problem Given a (finite) set X of candidates and a (finite) set A of voters each of

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

Antipodality in committee selection. Abstract

Antipodality in committee selection. Abstract Antipodality in committee selection Daniel Eckert University of Graz Christian Klamler University of Graz Abstract In this paper we compare a minisum and a minimax procedure as suggested by Brams et al.

More information

A model of elitist qualification

A model of elitist qualification Group Decision and Negotiation manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) A model of elitist qualification Miguel A. Ballester 1, José Luis García-Lapresta 2 1 Dep. d Economia i d Història Econòmica,

More information

Condorcet Efficiency: A Preference for Indifference

Condorcet Efficiency: A Preference for Indifference Condorcet Efficiency: A Preference for Indifference William V. Gehrlein Department of Business Administration University of Delaware Newark, DE 976 USA Fabrice Valognes GREBE Department of Economics The

More information

GROUP DECISION MAKING

GROUP DECISION MAKING 1 GROUP DECISION MAKING How to join the preferences of individuals into the choice of the whole society Main subject of interest: elections = pillar of democracy Examples of voting methods Consider n alternatives,

More information

An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert and Christian Klamler

An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert and Christian Klamler An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert and Christian Klamler An equity-efficiency trade-off in a geometric approach to committee selection Daniel Eckert

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context

Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context Computing Spanning Trees in a Social Choice Context Andreas Darmann, Christian Klamler and Ulrich Pferschy Abstract This paper combines social choice theory with discrete optimization. We assume that individuals

More information

Valued relations aggregation with the Borda method.

Valued relations aggregation with the Borda method. Valued relations aggregation with the Borda method. Thierry Marchant* Service de mathématiques de la gestion, Université Libre de Bruxelles, Boulevard du Triomphe CP210-01, 1050 Bruxelles, Belgium. Tél

More information

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain College of William and Mary W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2008 Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain Lauren Nicole Merrill College of William

More information

Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations

Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations Olfa Meddeb, Fouad Ben Abdelaziz, José Rui Figueira September 27, 2007 LARODEC, Institut Supérieur de Gestion, 41, Rue de

More information

Group Decision-Making with Incomplete Fuzzy Linguistic Preference Relations

Group Decision-Making with Incomplete Fuzzy Linguistic Preference Relations Group Decision-Making with Incomplete Fuzzy Linguistic Preference Relations S. Alonso Department of Software Engineering University of Granada, 18071, Granada, Spain; salonso@decsai.ugr.es, F.J. Cabrerizo

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function Claude Lamboray Abstract In this paper, we are interested in a preference function that associates to a profile of linear orders the

More information

Additive Consistency of Fuzzy Preference Relations: Characterization and Construction. Extended Abstract

Additive Consistency of Fuzzy Preference Relations: Characterization and Construction. Extended Abstract Additive Consistency of Fuzzy Preference Relations: Characterization and Construction F. Herrera a, E. Herrera-Viedma a, F. Chiclana b Dept. of Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence a University

More information

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester May 17, 2004 Abstract Suppose a strict

More information

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives

Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives Economic Theory 26, 607 617 (2005) DOI: 10.1007/s00199-004-059-8 Winning probabilities in a pairwise lottery system with three alternatives Frederick H. Chen and Jac C. Heckelman Department of Economics,

More information

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches Peter Fishburn Aleksandar Pekeč WORKING DRAFT PLEASE DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION Abstract When electing a committee from the pool of individual candidates,

More information

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting Probabilistic Aspects of Voting UUGANBAATAR NINJBAT DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS THE NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF MONGOLIA SAAM 2015 Outline 1. Introduction to voting theory 2. Probability and voting 2.1. Aggregating

More information

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Social Choice Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Summer term 2017 Version: March 15, 2018 CONTENTS Remarks 1 0 Introduction 2 1 The Case of 2 Alternatives 3 1.1 Examples for social choice rules............................

More information

CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES

CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES DONALD G SAARI AND TOMAS J MCINTEE INSTITUTE FOR MATHEMATICAL BEHAVIORAL SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE, CA 9697-5100 Abstract General conclusions

More information

Using quasiarithmetic means in a sequential decision procedure

Using quasiarithmetic means in a sequential decision procedure Using quasiarithmetic means in a sequential decision procedure Miguel Ángel Ballester Dep. d Economia i d Història Econòmica Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, Spain mballester@pareto.uab.es José Luis

More information

Instituto de Engenharia de Sistemas e Computadores de Coimbra Institute of Systems Engineering and Computers INESC - Coimbra

Instituto de Engenharia de Sistemas e Computadores de Coimbra Institute of Systems Engineering and Computers INESC - Coimbra Instituto de Engenharia de Sistemas e Computadores de Coimbra Institute of Systems Engineering and Computers INESC - Coimbra Claude Lamboray Luis C. Dias Pairwise support maximization methods to exploit

More information

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France

Thema Working Paper n Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Thema Working Paper n 2010-02 Université de Cergy Pontoise, France Sincere Scoring Rules Nunez Matias May, 2010 Sincere Scoring Rules Matías Núñez May 2010 Abstract Approval Voting is shown to be the unique

More information

Who wins the election? Polarizing outranking relations with large performance differences. Condorcet s Approach. Condorcet s method

Who wins the election? Polarizing outranking relations with large performance differences. Condorcet s Approach. Condorcet s method Who wins the election? Polarizing outranking relations with large performance differences Raymond Bisdorff Université du Luxembourg FSTC/ILAS ORBEL 26, Bruxelles, February 2012 Working hypothesis: 1. Each

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

Ordered Value Restriction

Ordered Value Restriction Ordered Value Restriction Salvador Barberà Bernardo Moreno Univ. Autònoma de Barcelona and Univ. de Málaga and centra March 1, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we restrict the pro les of preferences to be

More information

Extending difference of votes rules on three voting models.

Extending difference of votes rules on three voting models. University of Louisville ThinkIR: The University of Louisville's Institutional Repository Electronic Theses and Dissertations 8-2017 Extending difference of votes rules on three voting models. Sarah Schulz

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem Division of the Humanities and ocial ciences Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem KC Border Winter 2002 Let X be a nonempty set of social alternatives and let P denote the set of preference relations

More information

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Iian B. Smythe October 20, 2015 Abstract Does there exist a reasonable method of voting that when presented with three or more alternatives avoids the undue

More information

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives 3.- Social Choice and Welfare Economics 3.1 Arrow s Theorem We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives Let R denote the set of all preference relations

More information

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Martin Barbie, Clemens Puppe * Department of Economics, University of Karlsruhe D 76128 Karlsruhe, Germany and Attila Tasnádi ** Department of Mathematics, Budapest

More information

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM BY JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY Box 208281 New Haven, Connecticut 06520-8281

More information

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case

Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Resource Allocation via the Median Rule: Theory and Simulations in the Discrete Case Klaus Nehring Clemens Puppe January 2017 **** Preliminary Version ***** Not to be quoted without permission from the

More information

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS 1 B. Preference Aggregation Rules 3. Anti-Plurality a. Assign zero points to a voter's last preference and one point to all other preferences.

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra

Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Identifying Groups in a Boolean Algebra Wonki Jo Cho Biung-Ghi Ju June 27, 2018 Abstract We study the problem of determining memberships to the groups in a Boolean algebra. The Boolean algebra is composed

More information

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract) Conal Duddy, Nicolas Houy, Jérôme Lang, Ashley Piggins, and William S. Zwicker February 22, 2014 1 What is a Social Dichotomy Function? A dichotomy A = (A

More information

Reference-based Preferences Aggregation Procedures in Multicriteria Decision Making

Reference-based Preferences Aggregation Procedures in Multicriteria Decision Making Reference-based Preferences Aggregation Procedures in Multicriteria Decision Making Antoine Rolland Laboratoire ERIC - Université Lumière Lyon 2 5 avenue Pierre Mendes-France F-69676 BRON Cedex - FRANCE

More information

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Felix Brandt Christian Geist Paul Harrenstein Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract

More information

A BORDA COUNT FOR PARTIALLY ORDERED BALLOTS JOHN CULLINAN, SAMUEL K. HSIAO, AND DAVID POLETT

A BORDA COUNT FOR PARTIALLY ORDERED BALLOTS JOHN CULLINAN, SAMUEL K. HSIAO, AND DAVID POLETT A BORDA COUNT FOR PARTIALLY ORDERED BALLOTS JOHN CULLINAN, SAMUEL K. HSIAO, AND DAVID POLETT ABSTRACT. The application of the theory of partially ordered sets to voting systems is an important development

More information

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy. Amrita Dhillon and Ben Lockwood This version: March 2001 Abstract De Sinopoli and Turrini (1999) present an example to show

More information

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Journal of Economic and Social Research, 1 (1) 1999, 109-117 Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Ahmet Kara 1 Abstract. This paper presents a sufficient condition under which constitutional rights

More information

Similarity-based Classification with Dominance-based Decision Rules

Similarity-based Classification with Dominance-based Decision Rules Similarity-based Classification with Dominance-based Decision Rules Marcin Szeląg, Salvatore Greco 2,3, Roman Słowiński,4 Institute of Computing Science, Poznań University of Technology, 60-965 Poznań,

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia Abstract A procedure to construct a social welfare function from a social choice function is suggested

More information

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division Lecture 12 Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit epacuit@umd.edu October 18, 2012 PHIL 308S: Voting

More information

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models 14.773 Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Static Voting Models Daron Acemoglu MIT February 7 and 12, 2013. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 2 and 3 February

More information

Rules for Aggregating Information

Rules for Aggregating Information Rules for Aggregating Information Christopher P. Chambers and Alan D. Miller May 1, 2010 Abstract We present a model of information aggregation in which agents information is represented through partitions

More information

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate Luisa Carpente 1 Balbina Casas-Méndez 2 Ignacio García-Jurado 2 Anne van den Nouweland 3 September 22, 2005 Abstract In this paper we propose

More information

Using a hierarchical properties ranking with AHP for the ranking of electoral systems

Using a hierarchical properties ranking with AHP for the ranking of electoral systems Università di Pisa Dipartimento di Informatica Technical Report: TR-08-26 Using a hierarchical properties ranking with AHP for the ranking of electoral systems Lorenzo Cioni lcioni@di.unipi.it September

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

Sergey Shvydun NORMATIVE PROPERTIES OF MULTI-CRITERIA CHOICE PROCEDURES AND THEIR SUPERPOSITIONS: II

Sergey Shvydun NORMATIVE PROPERTIES OF MULTI-CRITERIA CHOICE PROCEDURES AND THEIR SUPERPOSITIONS: II Sergey Shvydun NORMATIVE PROPERTIES OF MULTI-CRITERIA CHOICE PROCEDURES AND THEIR SUPERPOSITIONS: II Working Paper WP7/2015/07 (Part 2) Series WP7 Mathematical methods for decision making in economics,

More information

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5

Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5 Introduction to Formal Epistemology Lecture 5 Eric Pacuit and Rohit Parikh August 17, 2007 Eric Pacuit and Rohit Parikh: Introduction to Formal Epistemology, Lecture 5 1 Plan for the Course Introduction,

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Makis Arsenis National Technical University of Athens April 216 Makis Arsenis (NTUA) AGT April 216 1 / 41 Outline 1 Social Choice Social Choice

More information

Recognizing single-peaked preferences on aggregated choice data

Recognizing single-peaked preferences on aggregated choice data Recognizing single-peaked preferences on aggregated choice data Smeulders B. KBI_1427 Recognizing Single-Peaked Preferences on Aggregated Choice Data Smeulders, B. Abstract Single-Peaked preferences play

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS THE UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS AN EFFICIENCY CHARACTERIZATION OF PLURALITY SOCIAL CHOICE ON SIMPLE PREFERENCE DOMAINS Biung-Ghi Ju University of Kansas

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary

Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives. Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary Social Welfare Functions that Satisfy Pareto, Anonymity, and Neutrality: Countable Many Alternatives Donald E. Campbell College of William and Mary Jerry S. Kelly Syracuse University College of William

More information

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games MATHIEU MARTIN THEMA, Departments of Economics Université de Cergy Pontoise, 33 Boulevard du Port, 95011 Cergy Pontoise cedex, France. e-mail: mathieu.martin@eco.u-cergy.fr

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Arrow s Impossibility Theorem and Experimental Tests of Preference Aggregation Todd Davies Symbolic Systems Program Stanford University joint work with Raja Shah, Renee Trochet, and Katarina Ling Decision

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting

14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting 14.770: Introduction to Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2: Collective Choice and Voting Daron Acemoglu MIT September 6 and 11, 2017. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Political Economy Lectures 1 and 2 September 6

More information

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1 Social Choice Lecture 11 Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Social Choice 3 Fun Game 4 Voting Paradoxes 5 Properties Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 2 Formal Definition Definition

More information

On the topological equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and Amartya Sen s liberal paradox

On the topological equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and Amartya Sen s liberal paradox Applied Mathematics and Computation 181 (2006) 1490 1498 www.elsevier.com/locate/amc On the topological equivalence of the Arrow impossibility theorem and Amartya Sen s liberal paradox Yasuhito Tanaka

More information

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: Preference Aggregation, Judgment Aggregation, Graph Aggregation Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss

More information

Metrizable ordinal proximity measures and their aggregation

Metrizable ordinal proximity measures and their aggregation Metrizable ordinal proximity measures and their aggregation José Luis GARCÍA-LAPRESTA PRESAD Research Group, BORDA Research Unit, IMUVA, Departamento de Economía Aplicada, Universidad de Valladolid, Spain

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment Université Paris-Dauphine - PSL Cycle Pluridisciplinaire d Etudes Supérieures Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment Victor Elie supervised by Miquel Oliu Barton June

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral

A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral Brice Mayag Thales R & T University of Paris I brice.mayag@thalesgroup.com Michel Grabisch University of Paris I Centre d Economie de la Sorbonne 106-112

More information

Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making

Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making Edurne Barrenechea a, Javier Fernandez a, Miguel Pagola

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Voting. José M Vidal. September 29, Abstract. The problems with voting.

Voting. José M Vidal. September 29, Abstract. The problems with voting. Voting José M Vidal Department of Computer Science and Engineering, University of South Carolina September 29, 2005 The problems with voting. Abstract The Problem The Problem The Problem Plurality The

More information

Copyright Author(s) ISSN

Copyright Author(s) ISSN Copyright Author(s) ISSN 1796-3133 Printed in Uniprint Turku 2012 Hannu Salonen Aggregating and Updating Information Aboa Centre for Economics Discussion Paper No. 73 March 2012 ABSTRACT We study information

More information

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons

Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Preliminary version - Please do not distribute Consistent multidimensional poverty comparisons Kristof Bosmans a Luc Lauwers b Erwin Ooghe b a Department of Economics, Maastricht University, Tongersestraat

More information

ORDERING OBJECTS ON THE BASIS OF POTENTIAL FUZZY RELATION FOR GROUP EXPERT EVALUATION

ORDERING OBJECTS ON THE BASIS OF POTENTIAL FUZZY RELATION FOR GROUP EXPERT EVALUATION ORDERING OBJECTS ON THE BASIS OF POTENTIAL FUZZY RELATION FOR GROUP EXPERT EVALUATION B. Kh. Sanzhapov and R. B. Sanzhapov Volgograd State University of Architecture and Civil Engineering, Akademicheskaya

More information

Cosine similarity and the Borda rule

Cosine similarity and the Borda rule Cosine siilarity and the Borda rule Yoko Kawada Abstract Cosine siilarity is a coonly used siilarity easure in coputer science. We propose a voting rule based on cosine siilarity, naely, the cosine siilarity

More information

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Alexander Zimper Working Paper Number 97 Department of Economics and Econometrics, University of Johannesburg Revisiting independence

More information

On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions

On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions Jin-Yi Cai Abstract Suppose all the individuals in a field are linearly ordered. Groups of individuals form teams. Is there a perfect ranking function

More information

Statistical Significance of Ranking Paradoxes

Statistical Significance of Ranking Paradoxes Statistical Significance of Ranking Paradoxes Anna E. Bargagliotti and Raymond N. Greenwell 1 February 28, 2009 1 Anna E. Bargagliotti is an Assistant Professor in the Department of Mathematical Sciences

More information

Compenzational Vagueness

Compenzational Vagueness Compenzational Vagueness Milan Mareš Institute of information Theory and Automation Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic P. O. Box 18, 182 08 Praha 8, Czech Republic mares@utia.cas.cz Abstract Some

More information

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD JOHN P DICKERSON Lecture #21 11/8/2016 CMSC828M Tuesdays & Thursdays 12:30pm 1:45pm IMPOSSIBILITY RESULTS IN VOTING THEORY / SOCIAL CHOICE Thanks to: Tuomas Sandholm

More information

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Egregious Errata Positive Political Theory II (University of Michigan Press, 2005) regrettably contains a variety of obscurities and errors,

More information

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011

Social Choice and Mechanism Design - Part I.2. Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Social Choice and Mechanism Design Part I.2: Social Choice Theory Summer Term 2011 Alexander Westkamp April 2011 Introduction Two concerns regarding our previous approach to collective decision making:

More information

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions Chapter 1 Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions 1.1 Arrow-Debreu model of an economy via Walras equilibrium problem. Let us consider first the so-called Arrow-Debreu model. The presentation

More information

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion José Carlos R. Alcantud and María D. García-Sanz Universidad de Salamanca, Spain 17. December

More information