Expected utility within a generalized concept of probability - a comprehensive framework for decision making under ambiguity

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Expected utility within a generalized concept of probability - a comprehensive framework for decision making under ambiguity"

Transcription

1 Statistical Papers 43, 5-22 (2002) Statistical Papers 9 Springer-Verlag 2002 Expected utility within a generalized concept of probability - a comprehensive framework for decision making under ambiguity Thomas Augustin Department of Statistics, University of Munich, AkademiestraBe 1, MUnchen, Germany (e-maih thomas@stat.uni-muenchen.de) Received: March 2000; revised version: July 2001 Abstract It had often been complained that the standard framework of decision theory is insufficient. In most applications, neither the maximin paradigm (relying on complete ignorance on the states of nature) nor the classical Bayesian paradigm (assuming perfect probabilistic information on the states of nature) reflect the situation under consideration adequately. Typically one possesses some, but incomplete, knowledge on the stochastic behaviour of the states of nature. In this paper first steps towards a comprehensive framework for decision making under such complex uncertainty will be provided. Common expected utility theory will be extended to interval probability, a generalized probabilistic setting which has the power to express incomplete stochastic knowledge and to take the extent of ambiguity (non-stochastic uncertainty) into account. Since two-monotone and totally monotone capacities are special cases of general interval probability, where Choquet integral and interval-valued expectation correspond to one another, the results also show, as a welcome by-product, how to deal efficiently with Choquet Expected Utility and how to perform a neat decision analysis in the case of belief functions. Key words Ambiguity - Interval probability - Decision Making - Expected Utility - Choquet Expected Utility - Imprecise Probabilities - Capacities - Lower and Upper Probabilities - Non-additive Measures - Belief Functions - Choquet Integral - Multiple Priors - Linear Programming - Ambiguity Aversion - Ambiguity Seeking.

2 6 Thomas Augustin 1 Introduction Consider the basic problem of decision analysis: One has to choose an action (treatment, investment decision,... ) from a non-empty, finite set IA = {al,..., as,...,an} (1) of possible actions. The consequences of every action depend on which one of a given non-empty set O = {~1,..., ~j,...,~m} (2) of states of nature (true disease, development of the market... ) comes true. Their utility is described by the utility function u: (Ih x O) -, 1R (a, u(a, (3) and by the associated random variable u(a) on (O, 7)o(0)) taking the values u(a, If the states of nature are produced by a perfectly known random mechanism (e.g. a lottery) described by a probability measure ~r(.) on (O, Po(O)), then it is widely accepted to choose that action a* which maximizes the expected utility ]Enu(a) = ~-'~jm 1 u(a, ~j). ~r((~j)) among all a 9 IA. As in the examples mentioned above, in most practical applications, however, the true state of nature can not be understood as arising from an ideal random mechanism. And even if so, the corresponding probability distribution will be not known exactly. There are two main directions to proceed in this situation. Since for a classical subjectivist, or Bayesian, every situation under uncertainty can be described by a single, precise probability measure lr(.), the lack of such a known random mechanism does not make any important difference to the decision maker. (S)he acts according to subjective expected utility. Then r(.) is called prior probability, and the optimal actions are called Bayes actions with respect to r(.). In contrast, from the viewpoint of an 'objectivist', now it does not make any sense at all to think of a probability on (O, Po(O)). Hence, the objectivist concludes, that the decision maker is completely ignorant about which state of nature will occur; (s)he has to act according to a criterion based on complete ignorance (like the maximin rule). It has often been complained that both ways to proceed, relying on subjective expected utility as well as acting according to a criterion based on complete ignorance, are inappropriate, because they both have to destroy the partial nature of the knowledge on the decision maker's hand. The objectivist's criteria treat partial knowledge like complete ignorance, often leading to unsatisfactory solutions. Subjective utility theory identifies partial knowledge with complete probabilistic knowledge. This conflicts, for

3 Generalized Expected Utility 7 instance, with Ellsberg's (1961) experiments, which made it perfectly clear that ambiguity (i.e. the deviation from ideal stochasticity) plays a constitutive role in decision making -- neglecting it may lead to deceptive conclusions. In the meantime substantial generalizations of the concept of probability and its mathematical formalization emerged which have the power to take ambiguity into account appropriately. Summaries of the state of the art are provided by decooman, Fine, Moral & Seidenfeld (2001), Weichselberger (2001, Ch. 1), and the Imprecise Probability Web Page (decooman & Walley (2001)). As a generalization of expected utility theory mainly the socalled Choquet expected utility received attention. (See Chateauneuf, Cohen & Meilijson (1997) and the corresponding chapters in Grabisch, Nguyen & Walker (1995) for surveys.) In this paper expected utility theory will be extended to the case where the decision maker's knowledge is described by interval probability, which provides a natural and comprehensive framework to handle ambiguity. Section 2 briefly introduces some basics of the theory of interval probability. In Section 3 a precise definition of generalized expected utility will be given. In the main part of the paper general algorithms will be developed to derive optimal actions. Firstly, in Section 4, optimal actions under strict ambiguity aversion will be considered. Then some attention is paid to the special case of two-monotone capacities and Choquet expected utility. In Section 5 the setting will be extended to the whole range of ambiguity attitudes (all degrees of ambiguity aversion as well as of ambiguity seeking). For the whole argumentation linear programming plays an essential role. On the one hand, it is powerful for efficient calculation of optimal solutions even by standard software, on the other hand, it provides valuable theoretical insights. 2 Interval Probability A very natural idea to represent ambiguity is to use interval probabilities. As the name suggests, the probability P(A) of every event A is described by an interval [L(A), U(A)] C_ [0, 1] instead of a real number p(a). 1 The difference between upper and lower interval limits provides a means to describe the amount of ambiguity -- the higher the ambiguity, the larger this difference. In the extreme case of complete ignorance (full ambiguity) the interval [0, 1] is appropriate, while under ideal probabilistic information without any ambiguity this interval shrinks to a single point. Hence, the usual formalization of probability as a real number is contained as a border case, which is only understood as appropriate for describing the ideal stochastic situation with an perfectly working random mechanism and complete knowledge on its stochastic behaviour. i For the sake of clarity, the following convention is made: throughout the paper, capital P is used for interval-valued assignments, while small p stands for classical probability.

4 8 Thomas Augustin 2.1 Basic Definitions With respect to the intended application the whole consideration is restricted here to the case of finitely generated algebra `4 based on a sample space ~2. Then, without loss of generality, ~ is finite, and `4 is the power set of ~2 = {oj1,...,ojk}. To distinguish in terminology, every probability measure in the usual sense, i.e. every set function p(.) satisfying Kolmogorov's axioms is called a classical probability. The set of all classical probabilities on the measurable space (~2, `4) will be denoted by C (I2, `4). Axioms for interval-valued probabilities P(-) = [L(.), U(-)] can be obtained by looking at the relation between the non-additive set-function L(.) and U(-) and the set of classical probabilities being in accordance with them. On a finite sample space, as considered throughout this paper, several concepts of interval probability coincide. They all are concerned with set-functions e(.):.4 -, {[L, U] l0 _< L <_ U _< 1} A ~ P(A) = [L(A), U(A)] with and A4 := {p(-) 9 C(12,.4) IL(A) _< p(a) <_ U(A), VA 9 A} # 0. (4) inf p(a) = L(A) p(.)e~ sup p(a) = U(A) VA 9 `4. (5) Such P(-), and the corresponding set functions L(-) and U(-), are called lower and upper probability (Huber & Strassen (1973)), envelopes (Walley & Fine (1982), Denneberg (1994)), coherent probability (Walley (1991)) and F-probability (Weichselberger (1995, 2000, 2001)). In game theory AJ is the core. Here Weichselberger's terminology is used, calling A/[ structure of the F-probability P (. ). Note that in case of F-probability there is a one-to-one correspondence between structure and interval limits. Therefore, in some situations, it is very helpful to think of an F-probability as a set of classical probabilities. For every F-probability, L(.) and U(.) are conjugate, i.e. L(A) = 1 - U(AC), VA 9,4. Therefore, every F-probability is uniquely determined either by L(-) or by U(-) alone. Then one obtains for its structure 2r : I f14 = {p(.) 9 C(/2,,4) I L(A) < p(a), VA 9.4} = {p(.) 9 C(/2,.4) I p(a) < U(A), VA 9.4}. (6) Here L(-) is used throughout, and ~- = (~2,.4, L(.)) is called an F-probability field. Specifying an F-probability field (/2,.4, L(-)), it is implicitly required that the conjugate set function U(.) = 1 - L(.e) describes the upper bound of the interval.

5 Generalized Expected Utility Special Cases: Two-monotone Capacities and Belief Functions In the literature two special cases of F-probability have extensively been studied. Definition 1 Two-monotone capacities and belief functions a) A set-function L(-) :.4 --* [0, 1] w/th L(12) = 1 and LiA ) < LIB), A C B, is called capacity. The corresponding set-function #(.) defined such that L( A) = ~-~SC_A#( B) is called its Moebius inverse. 2 b) A capacity L(. ) is called two-monotone 3 if L i A U B) + LiA n B) > L(A) + LIB), VA, B E.4, and totally monotone (or belief function with basic probability assignment #(.)), if L (. q) z Ai > ( - 1 ) IIt+1L r (n/ A~. \~ei / Accordingly, also the interval-valued assignment P(') = [Li'),U(')] with U(A) = 1 - L(AC), A E `4, will be called two-monotone probability and totally monotone probability, respectively. Totally monotone capacities are the basic entity of the Dempster-Shafer theory of belief functions (e.g., Shafer (1976), Yager, Fedrizzi and Kacprzyk (1994)), which are characterized by the non-negativity of their Moebins inverse /z(.). T h e n / z ( A ) is understood as the weight of the evidence which is contained solely in the event A. - - Clearly, every totally monotone assignment is two-monotone. Two-monotone probabilities are special cases of F-probabilities (Huber & Strassen (1973, Lemma 2.5, p. 254)). The class of two-monotone probabilities plays an important role in robust statistics as a superstructure comprising the commonly used neighborhood models (cf. the review in Augustin (2001A, Section 4.2)). Two-monotone probabilities possess some very characteristic properties (cf. also Proposition 2), but in many situations t h e y are understood to be not general enough to provide a neat basis for describing situations under ambiguity Interval-valued Expectation, Choquet Integral Many concepts of classical probability theory can appropriately be generalized to interval probability. For decision making the notion of expectation is the most important one. Looking at the classical expectation 2 It can be shown that p(.) is uniquely defined, and that there is an explicit formula to calculate p(.), see Sharer (1976). 3 For the property of two-monotonicity m a n y different names are common. In particular, it is also called 'supermodularity' (Denneberg (1994)) or 'convexity' (Jaffray (1989)).

6 10 Thomas Augustin ]EpX = f Xdp = f p({w I X(w) > t})dt of a non-negative random variable X on (~2,,4) with respect to the classical probability p(.), two ways to proceed had been suggested. The first one replaces the additive set-function p(-) by the capacity L(.) leading to the Choquet integral (or fuzzy integral) (e.g, Grabisch, Nguyen & Walker (1995)) of a non-negative random variable X on (12,.A) defined by IELX := L({w I X(~) > t})dt. (7) ~0 ~ There are two reasonable ways to extend this definition to random variables taking arbitrary real values (cf. the asymmetric integral or Choquet integral (in the narrower sense) and the symmetric integral in Denneberg (1994, Ch. 5 and Ch. 7)). These way of defining expectation are mainly applied to two-monotone capacities; their meaning for more general non-additive set-functions is not unanimously accepted. Another natural way to define expectation for arbitrary F-probabilities is to rely directly on the structure and to define expectation via the infimum and the supremum 4 over all classical expectations with respect to elements of the structure. Definition 2 (Expectation with respect to an F-probability field) For every F-probability field ~ = ($2,,4, L(.)) with structure j~4 and every random variable X on (~2,.A) ]E~X :--- [LIE~X,t~X] := [ inf ]EpX, sup EpX] (8) p(.)~.m p(.)e~ is the (interval-valued) expectation of X (with respect to ~). Remark 1 The results derived later on will be based on expectation in the sense of Definition 2. Note, however, that for two-monotone probabilities and belief functions, both ways of generalizing expectation are equivalent (cf., e.g., Denneberg (1994, Prop. 10.3, p.126)). Therefore, in this case, all results are Mso valid for the Choquet integral. 2.5 Some Properties of the Structure In the case of finite spaces ~2 = {wl,..., wk} considered throughout this paper, the structure can be given a simple geometric interpretation: Every classical probability p(.) is uniquely determined by the vector p({wl}),..., p({wk}) of probability components of the singletons wl,..., wk. Therefore, every classical probability may be identified with a point in [0, 1] k, and every structure with a certain subset of [0, 1] k. 4 It can be shown that indeed one has minimum and maximum. Note further that, because Y~ is finite, integrability is trivially satisfied.

7 Generalized Expected Utility II Proposition 1 (Extreme points) The structure.h4 of an F-probability field is (isomorphic to) a convex polyhedron. In particular, the set E(Jt4) of the extreme points (vertices) is non-empty, finite, and it uniquely determines A~. Proof: Shapley (1971, p. 16), Weichselberger (2001, Ch. 2). [] This relation to convex polyhedra makes linear programming a power~ ful tool for working with interval probability. Weichselberger (1996) gives characterizations of F-probabilities in terms of linear programs. By linear programming also efficient algorithms are available to calculate the structure f14 and E(f14) for a given F-probability field. For two-monotone probabilities an alternative, closed form can be derived which additionally gives an elegant characterization of two-monotone probabilities. Proposition 2 Let J: = (12,.4, L(. )) be an F-probability field with structure M4, and denote the set of all permutations of {1,...,k} by T. The lower interval limit L(.) is a two-monotone capacity iff E(A4) = {pc(.) I r E T} withpr = L(U' j=l {we(j) }) - L (U j=l '-1 {w~(i)}), for aui= 1,..., k. Proof: It is easy to check that defining L(.) := minp(.)ez(~) p(.) leads to a two-monotone capacity. For the other direction compare, e.g., Dempster (1967, p ) and Shapley (1971, p.19). [] Given a random variable X, calculating 1E~X means to maximize or minimize the expression ~-~,~ea X(w). p({w}) over all p(.) E M/I, i.e. to calculate extremes of a linear function on a convex polyhedron. This can easily be done by linear programming. From linear programming one also knows that it is sufficient for the calculation to concentrate on the extreme points C(A4) of the structure f14. 5 Lemma 1 Let ~ = (12; ~4; L(.)) be an F-probability field with structure and extreme points E(f14). Then f ] IE~X min F, px; max IEpX (9) [P()ez(~) p(.)ez(~) J In the decision theoretic setting the following immediate conclusion will become very important. Corollary 1 (Reduction lemma) In the situation of Lemma 1, for every real g, LIE~ X >- g ", ~." ]EvX >- g, Vp(.) E ~(J$4). (10) 5 This result can be generalized to arbitrary measurable spaces (f~, ~4), with I"2 infinite, by introducing an additional continuity condition which guarantees compactness in an appropriate weak* topology, cf. Augustin (1998, Satz 2.12, p. 77).

8 12 Thomas Augustin 3 The Generalized Decision Theoretic Framework 3.1 Some Preliminaries In this paper the decision problem as described in the Relations (1) - (3) will be analyzed. For brevity of reference, the relevant components, the set IA of actions, the set O of states of nature and the precise utility function 6 u(.), are collected in the triple (IA, O, u(.)) which is called basic decision problem. For many applications it will prove helpful to extend the problem by allowing for randomized actions. Formally, every randomized action can be identified with a classical probability 7 )~(-) on (IA, :Po(IA)) where 1({a}), a E IA, is interpreted as the classical probability to perform action a. The set of all randomized actions will be denoted by A(IA). Pure (or unrandomized) actions, i.e. elements a of IA itself, are identified with the Dirac measure in the point {a}, and therefore are also understood as elements of A(IA). The utility function is extended in a canonical way to randomized actions, i.e. to the domain A(IA) O, by u(.h, vqj) := ~-]~'~=z )~(as). u(as, v~j). Analogously to above, u(1) is understood as that random variable which gives the utility of )~ in dependence on the true state ~. 3.P Generalized Expected Utility Now all the ingredients are prepared needed to cast the extended decision theoretic framework where the ambiguous prior knowledge is described by interval probability. With this generalization at hand, it becomes possible to formulate the decision maker's knowledge in a substantially more flexible way. The partial character of the prior knowledge can be expressed appropriately and need no longer be denied; the constitutive role ambiguity plays is reflected in the model. With the consideration in Section 2.3 on interval-valued expectation one immediately obtains the basic elements of a generalized decision theory. Definition 3 (Generalized expected utility) Given the basic decision problem (IA, O, u(.) ) and an F-probability II (.) on (IA, 7Po(IA) ) with structure rid. For every pure action a E IA and for every randomized action )~ in A(IA), IE~u(a) and ]E~u(1) are the generalized expected utility (with respect to the prior II(.)). 6 Throughout the paper it is assumed that a (precise) utility function is given. On the construction of utility functions in the presence of ambiguity, generalizing the Neumann Morgenstern approach, see Jaffray (1989) and Schmeidler (1989). 7 This paper argues in favor of generalized probabilities. Hence, it may appear reasonable, at a first glance, to consider also interval-valued randomization probabilities. Though, formally, this would be possible without the need of substantial modifications, it is not quite coherent with the theory, because the concept of randomization is based on ideal random experiments, for which classical probabilities are still understood as appropriate.

9 Generalized Expected Utility 13 Note that ]E~u(a) and le~u(a) are interval-valued quantities. In most cases, comparing the generalized expected utilities of actions directly will lead only to partial orders on IA and A(IA). But typically, in decision analysis, a linear (complete) order of actions is desired. This can be achieved by choosing an appropriate representation, i.e. by a mapping from IR IR to lit which evaluates intervals by real numbers to make use of the natural order on ]R for distinguishing optimal actions. The representation is strongly connected with the attitude towards ambiguity; the more ambiguity averse the decision maker is, the higher is the influence of the lower interval limit of generalized expected utility. In Section 4 and 5 calculation of optimal actions and their properties will be discussed for two important representations. These results are based on the characteristic properties of the structure of F-probabilities and of two-monotone probabilities collected in Section Optimal Actions under Strict Ambiguity Aversion 3.1 The Criterion Under strict ambiguity aversion every action is evaluated by its minimal expected utility over the structure; therefore, the interval-valued expectations [LIE~u()Q, VIEjvtu(A)] are represented by the lower interval limit alone. An action ),* is optimal iff LIEA4u(A*) >_ L]EA4u()~), VA 9 A(IA). (11) This criterion corresponds to the Gamma-Minimax criterion (e.g. Berger (1984, Section 4.7.6), Vidakovic (2000)), to the Maxmin expected utility model (Gilboa & Schmeidler (1989)), and to the MaxEMin criterion considered by Kofler & Menges (1976; cf. also Kofler (1989) and the references therein.) In the case of two-monotone capacities it is equivalent to maximizing Choquet expected utility. Remark P It should be noted that the criterion considered here contains the two classical decision criteria as border cases. If there is perfect probabilistic information and therefore no ambiguity, then A4 consists only of one single classical prior probability ~r(.), and (11) coincides with Bayes optimality with respect to ~r(.). On the other hand, in the case of completely lacking information, II(B) = [0, 1], for every B 9 Po(Y2) \ {0, O}, ('non-selective or vacuous prior'). Then one can show that LIEA4u(,k ) = minje{1... m} u(a, zgj), and (11) leads to the maximin criterion. 4.2 Optimal Actions - Calculation and Basic Properties Searching for an optimal action means to maximize m LIEA4u(A) = rain ~-~ (u(a;zgj). 7r({tgj})) (12)

10 14 Thomas Augustin among all A(-) E A(IA), i.e. to solve min (u(as;tgj)a(aa)). lr({zgj}) --* max ~r(-)ea4 ~ s (13) under the constraints -~A(as) = 1, A(as) ~ O, s = 1,...,n. (14) s----1 This originally non-linear problem can be made linear by introducing an auxiliary variable g for LIE~.tu(A): The maximization in (13) is equivalent to g --* max under the additional constraints (u(as, >g, w(-) (15) Now both, the objective function as well as the constraints, are linear in a finite number of variables, A(al),..., A(as),..., A(an) and g. Nevertheless this is no linear programming problem in the usual sense. Except in the case of a classical prior probability, the structure A4 consists of non-countable many elements. Hence, in the way as it is written, (15) contains an infinite number of constraints. At this point the reduction lemma (Corollary 1) becomes very valuable: it states that Relation (15) is equivalent to requiring the constraints )-~jrn----1()-~:----1(u(as,~j). A(as)). ~l'({tgj})) ~ g only for ah lr(.) in the set s of extreme points of f14. Since, according to Proposition 1, the cardinality of the set s is finite, the original decision problem was successfully transformed into a linear programming problem. This result is of double interest. Firstly, it means that the calculation of optimal actions can be done by standard numerical routines even implemented in most software packages. Secondly, it allows to apply general results from the theory of linear programming to the decision problem under consideration. Summing up one obtains Theorem 1 Consider a basic decision problem (IA, O, u(.)), an F-probability H (. ) on ((9, 7~ o( 0 ) ) with structure All, and the linear programming problem under the constraints (14) and g ---}max (16)

11 Generalized Expected Utility 15 a) Let (A*({al}),...,A*({an}),g*) be an optimal solution, then the randomized action s ~'(.) = (A'({al}),...,)~*({an}) is maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the prior 1I(.) and the criterion (11). Furthermore, LIE~u()~*) = g*. b) Every action,k*(.) maximizing generalized expected utility uniquely corresponds to an optimal solution of this optimization problem. c) There always exists an action maximizing generalized expected utility. d) The set A* of actions maximizing generalized expected utility is convex and compact. Proof: Part a) and b) directly follow from the considerations preceding the theorem. Part c) and d) are applications of general results from linear optimization: With respect to Part c) it is important that for the existence of an optimal solution of a bounded linear programming problem the existence of an arbitrary admissible solution not contradicting the constraints is sufficient. (A0({al}),...,A0({an},g0) with A0({al}) = 1, A0({as}) = 0, s ,...,n, and 90 = minje{1... m} u(al, Oj) is such an admissible solution. Part d) uses the fact that the set of optimal solutions (and therefore also the projection on the first n-components) is convex and closed. Since A(IA) is bounded, A* is bounded and therefore, by Heine and Borel's Theorem, compact. Remark 3 If one explicitly wants to concentrate on pure actions a E IA, Theorem 1 still is useful for efficient calculation of optimal solutions: it then can be interpreted as a (partially) Boolean optimization problem where the variables A({al},. :.,A({an}) are only allowed to take the values zero or one. 4.3 Special Cases: Two-monotone Capacities and Choquet Integral Of particular interest is the special case where the decision maker's prior knowledge can be expressed by two-monotone or totally monotone capacities (belief functions). Then, following Remark 1, the lower interval limit of generalized expected utility in the sense of Definition 2 and the Choquet integral (cf. Relation (7)) coincide, and actions maximizing generalized expected utility are also maximizing Choquet expected utility. Note further that, according to Proposition 2, it then becomes possible to describe the elements of s in closed form. Therefore, Theorem 1 immediately offers a very efficient procedure to calculate optimal actions. Corollary 2 Consider a basic decision problem (Ilk, (9, u(.) ), and an F-probability Hi. ) = [L(-), U(.)] on (O,:Po(~)) with structure )~4 where L(.) is a two-monotone capacity. Let T be the set of all permutations of {1,..., rn}. s Here, and later on, every element,k(.) of A(IA) is identified with the vector (~({al)),..., ~({a,}))'.

12 16 Thomas Augustin a) The following three statements are equivalent: i) ~*(.) is maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the prior II(.) and the criterion (11). ii) )r is maximizing Choquet expected utility with respect to L(.), i.e., lelu()~*) _> IELU(A), for all ~ 9 A(IA). iii) A*(.) corresponds to an optimal solution (A*({al}),...,A*({an},g*) of the linear programming problem g"* max under the constraints (14) and (0,) -(U,)) V~ E :F. j:l s=l 1: b) If p(.) is the Moebius inverse of L(.), then the relation above can be written as m n ~-'~-~u(a,,#i).a(a,). E #(muzgr V~eT. (17) j:l s=l j-1 AC_UI= l t%(o Proof." Part a) of Corollary 2 immediately follows from Theorem 1 by using the special form of the extreme points (cf. Proposition 2). Additionally taking into account that ]z(.) is the Moebius inverse of L(-) yields Part b).[:] Part b) is in particular attractive for belief functions which are often directly assigned via the function ]z(.). It may be noted that (17) is also valid for two-monotone capacities but not for arbitrary F-probabilities. The Moebius inversion still may be applied to the lower interval limit of the latter, but the extreme points of the structure are no longer of the form described in Proposition Some Further Properties Actions maximizing expected utility with respect to a classical prior probability lr(-) have two characteristic properties which deserve a brief look in the generalized setting considered here. a) Essentially completeness of pure actions: For every optimal A* (.) E A(IA) there exists an a* E IA with 1E~u(a*) --- IE~u(~*). b) Compatibility with the dominance principle: Optimal actions A*(-) are not uniformly dominated by other actions A(-), i.e, there is no action A0(-) with u(a0, ~j) > u(a*, tgj) for all j = 1,..., k. The first statement does not apply to maximin actions. Since, according to Remark 2, maximin solutions are a special case, namely actions maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the non-selective or vacuous

13 Generalized Expected Utility 17 prior, this property can not generally be satisfied under interval-valued priors: under ambiguity, introducing ideal randomness by randomization may improve the utility. The second property may be understood as a minimal requirement for optimality criteria. Admissibility in the sense of being not uniformly dominated is related to Pareto optimality: one can not improve in any state without getting worse somewhere else. Indeed, it is straightforwardly shown by contradiction that actions maximizing generalized expected utility are admissible. 5 Optimal Actions under General Ambiguity Attitudes 5.1 The Criterion Being strictly ambiguity averse is a very pessimistic attitude towards ambiguity, which inherits - even though in a weakened way - some of the counterintuitive properties of maximin solutions. Already Ellsberg had emphasized the importance of considering other ambiguity attitudes. In many decision situations it is quite reasonable to take also into account the maximal expected utility compatible with the prior. Indeed, a plenty of empirical evidence strongly suggests that many decision makers are not strictly ambiguity averse, some of them indeed are even ambiguity seeking. Such more complex ambiguity attitudes can be reflected by other representations of interval-valued expectations. A convenient and flexible choice is a linear combination (compare with Ellsberg (1961, p. 664), Jaffray (1989), Weichselberger &: Augustin (1998), Weichselberger (2001, Ch. 2.6)) which represents E~u()~) by U. LIE~u(A) + (1-77). UE~u(A). (18) The parameter ~, called caution by Weichselberger (2001), reflects the degree of ambiguity aversion: the closer 77 comes to 1, the higher is the ambiguity aversion, y = 1 corresponds to strict ambiguity aversion, 71 = 0 expresses maximal ambiguity seeking attitudes. Remark 4 This criterion again contains two criteria from classical decision theory as border cases (compare with Remark 2): If there is no ambiguity, then //(-) = lr(.) for a classical probability It(-), and optimality based on (18) again coincides with Bayes optimality with respect to lr(.). In the case of completely lacking information, (18) leads to the Hurwicz criterion with optimism parameter 1 - y.

14 18 T h o m a s Augustin 5.2 Calculating Optimal Actions To obtain actions maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the representation (18), one has to maximize min ~-~ (u(as;v~j)a(as)).tr({v~j}) + +(1 - r/) 9 ( max s \ ' ( ) ~ M j=l under the constraints (14). Trying to make this problem linear, the s u m m a n d corresponding to LIE~u(A) can be handled as in the previous section. Though looking quite similar, the second summand, which corresponds to UlE~u(A), needs some additional care. Now, instead of the maximization of a minimum, two connected maximizations have to be performed: one has 'there exists a 7r(-) E ~ / ' instead of 'for all 7r(.) E A/I'. The direct way to deal with this is to put UIE~u(A) into the objective function. Then one introduces new variables #({z91}),..., #({0m}) describing t h a t element #(.) of the structure under which UlE~u(A) becomes maximal. The condition #(-) G A4 can be rewritten as U( U {OJ}) -> Z#({'O./})_> L( U {0i}), V,.7C_{1,...,m}. (19) iej jej iej All in all one obtains L e m m a 2 Consider a basic decision problem (IA, O, u(.) ), an F-probability 11(.) on (0, 7~o(0)) with structure A4, the caution 77, and the programming problem ~?.g + (1-7/). (u(as; Oj)A(as)). #({Og}) ---* max (20) j=l under the constraints (14), (16), and (19). A randomized action A*(.) G A(IA) is maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the representation (18) and the prior 1-I(.), iff it corresponds to an optimal solution (x* ({al }), 99 9 ~* ({a,, }), g*, h', ~-" ({Ol } ),..., ~* ( { o,, })). Note that in (20), for 7/ < 1, A(.) and 7r(.) vary simultaneously. As a consequence, the objective function is no longer linear but bilinear. The resulting optimization problem can be solved by viewing it as a special case of a quadratic optimization problem. (See, e.g., Fromm (1975) or Bazaraa & Shetty (1979) for quadratic programming.)

15 Generalized Expected Utility 19 Surprisingly, one can go a step further: it is possible to reformulate even this problem in terms of a single linear programming problem, which again is helpful for efficient calculation by standard software as well as for deriving properties of the optimal solution. Inspired by (16) one can introduce an auxiliary variable h with the additional constraints j=l and consider the objective function -< h, e E(M), (21),7 -g + (1 - ri). h --, max. (22) Of course, this does not immediately yield an optimal action. The fact that one has 'less or equal h' in (21) lets, together with the maximization in (22), h become unbounded; every increase in h also results in a higher value of the objective function. Now, the major idea is to additionally bound h by a penalty variable z which guarantees that h satisfying (21) becomes, ceteris paribus, as small as possible. Then, the value h* of h in the optimal solution will be the smallest value being greater than or equal to ~-~.jm l ()-~sn l(u(as, ~j). )~(as)))" ~r({~j}), for all lr(.) E E(A~t). This means nothing else but that h* is the maximum of )'~jm=l()-~,n l(u(a,, ~j). A(as))))- 7r((#j )), for all Ir E ~(~4). By the reduction lemma (Corollary 1), h* is even the maximum over all 7r E rid. Combining these arguments with the considerations preceding Theorem 1 yields the following result: Theorem 2 Consider a basic decision problem (IA, O, u(.)), an F-probability II(.) on (0, go(o)) with structure rid, a caution ~1 < 1, and the programming problem under the constraints (14) and (7 "g + (1-7/). h) - z --* max z>o. a) A randomized action ~*(.) E A(IA) is maximizing generalized expected utility with respect to the representation (18) and the prior H(.), iff it corresponds to an optimal solution (~*((al)),..., ~* ({a~)), g*, h*, 0). b) Mutatis mutandis, Corollary ~ on maximizing Choquet expected utility as well as the remaining parts of Theorem 1 still hold.

16 20 Thomas Augustin 6 Concluding Remarks The paper extended expected utility theory to interval probability, a generalized probabilistic setting which has the power to take ambiguity into account and to allow for a more appropriate modeling of the decision situation. While classical decision theory can only deal with the unrealistic border cases of perfect probabilistic information or of complete ignorance, the framework developed here allows to express the decision maker's state of knowledge in a flexible way and without the need of introducing artificial assumptions. A general algorithm was derived to calculate optimal actions and to describe their properties. As a side product, applying them to the special case of two-monotone capacities, the results also provide a new point of view how to handle Choquet expected utility efficiently. The mathematical main arguments are based on the fact that the structure associated with the interval-valued prior is a convex polyhedron. Hence, most of the results presented should carry over to those approaches which work with more general types of sets of classical probabilities (in particluar imprecise probabilities (with a finite domain) in the sense of Walley (1991) or linear partial information (cf. Kofler (1989)). Beside this aspect three topics of further research appear to be of special interest. Firstly, the framework developed has to be extended to incorporate sampling information. This can be done, just as in classical decision theory, by considering data-dependent decision functions. Some first results on this topic can be found in Augnstin (2001B). Secondly, duality theory should be studied carefully. In the very special decision problem of hypotheses testing, duality theory for linear programming provides valuable insights leading to an extension of the generalized Neyman Pearson lemma (Augnstin (1998, Ch. 5.1f)). Applying similar techniques here promises to be very helpful. One will obtain a deeper understanding of the decision problem, mainly by characterizing least favorable elements of the structure of the interval-valued prior. Finally, because one source of ambiguity is the aggregation of (expert) opinions, further work has to clarify the implications of the results presented here for group decision making. Acknowledgements I am indebted to two anonymous referees, Dieter Denneberg and Kurt Weichselberger for many very valuable comments. I am also grateful to participants of the Workshop on Risk, Uncertainty and Decision (Paris, 2000) and to members of the research group 'Making Choices' (ZIF, Bielefeld, 1999/2000) for inspiring discussions.

17 Generalized Expected Utility 21 References 1. Augustin, T. (1998): Optimale Tests bei lntervallwahrscheinlichkeit. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, GSttingen. (In German, with an English summary on pages ) 2. Augustin, T. (2001A): Neyman-Pearson testing under interval probability by globally least favorable pairs - reviewing Huber-Strassen theory and extending it to general interval probability. To appear in: Journal of Statistical Planning and Inference. 3. Augustin, T. (2001B): On decision making under ambiguous prior and sampiing information. In: decooman, G.; Fine, T.L.,; Moral, S., Seidenfeld, T. (eds.): ISIPTA 01: Proceedings of the Second International Symposium on Imprecise Probabilities and their Apphcations. Cornell University, Ithaca, New York; c.f. also htzp://decsai.ugr.es/~smc/isiptaol/proceedings/index. html 4. Bazaraa, M.S.; Sherry, C.M. (1979): Nonlinear Programming. Theory and Algorithms Wiley. New York. 5. Berger, J.O. (1984): Statistical Decision Theory and Bayesian Analysis. (2nd edition). Springer. New York. 6. Chateauneuf, A.; Cohen, M.; Meilijson, I. (1997): New tools to better model behavior under risk and uncertainty: An overview. Finance. 18, decooman, G; Fine, T.L.; Moral, S.; Seidenfeld, T. (eds.): ISIPTA 01: Proceedings of the Second International Symposium on Imprecise Probabilities and their Applications. Cornell University, Ithaca, New York; c.f. also http ://decsai. ugr. es/- smc/isiptao i/proceedings/index, html 8. decooman, G.; Walley, P. (eds.) (2001): The Imprecise Probability Project. http ://ippserv. rug. ac. be/ 9. Dempster, A.P. (1967): Upper and lower probabilities induced by a multivalued mapping. The Annals of Mathematical Statistics. 37; Denneberg, D. (1994): Non-Additive Measure and Integral. Kluwer, Dordrecht. 11. Ellsberg, D. (1961): Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 75, Fromm, A. (1975): Nichtlineare Optimierungsmodelle. Ausgew~hlte AnMitze, Kritik and Anwendungen. Harri Deutsch, Frankfurt/M. 13. Gilboa, I.; Sehmeidler, D. (1989): Maxmin expected utility with nonunique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics. 18, Grabisch, M.; Nguyen, H.T.; Walker, E.A. (1995): Fundamentals of Uncertainty Calculi with Applications to Fuzzy Inference. Kluwer, Dordrecht. 15. Huber, P.J.; Strassen, V. (1973): Minimax tests and the Neyman-Pearson lemma for capacities. Annals of Statistics. 1, ; Correction: 2, Jaffray, J.Y. (1989): Linear utility theory and belief functions. Operations Research Letters. 8, Kofler, E. (1989): Prognosen and Stabilitiit bei unvollstiindiger Information. Campus, Frankfurt/Main. 18. Kofler, E.; Menges, G. (1976): Entscheidungen bei unvollst~ndiger Information. Springer, Berlin (Lecture Notes in Economics and Mathematical Systems, 136). 19. Papamareou, A.; Fine, T.L. (1991): Unstable collectives and envelopes of probability measures. Annals of Probability. 19,

18 22 Thomas Augustin 20. Schmeidler, D. (1989): Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica. 57, Shafer, G. (1976): A Mathematical Theory of Evidence. Princeton University Press. Princeton. 22. Shapley, S. (1971): Cores of convex games. International Journal of Game Theory. 1, Smithson, M. (1999): Human judgement research on imprecise probabilities -- a reference list distributed at ISIPTA99. Division of Psychology, The Australian National University. 24. Vidakovic, B. (2000): F-minimax: A paradigm for conservative robust Bayesians. In: Insua, D.R., and Ruggeri, F. (eds.) Robust Bayesian Analysis. Springer. 25. Walley, P. (1991): Statistical Reasoning with Imprecise Probabilities. Chapman & Hall, London. 26. Walley, P.; Fine, T.L. (1982): Towards a frequentist theory of upper and lower probability. The Annals of Statistics. 10, Weichselberger, K. (1995): Axiomatic foundations of the theory of intervalprobability. In: Mammitzsch, V., Schneeweifl, H. (eds.) Symposia Gaussiana Conference B. de Gruyter, Berlin; Weichselberger, K. (1996): Interval-probability on finite sample-spaces. In: Rieder, H. (ed.) Robust Statistics, Data Analysis and Computer Intensive Methods. Springer, New York; Weichselberger, K. (2000): The theory of interval-probability as a unifying concept for uncertainty. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning. 24, Weichselberger, K. (2001): Elementare Grundbegriffe einer allgemeineren Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung L IntervaUwahrscheinlichkeit als umfassendes Konzept. Physika, Heidelberg. 31. Weichselberger, K.; Augustin, T. (1998): Analysing Ellsberg's Paradox by means of interval-probability. In: Galata, R.; Kiichenhof, H. (eds.): Econometrics in Theory and Practice. (Festschrift for Hans Schneewei]3.) Physika. Heidelberg; Yager, R.R.; Fedrizzi, M.; Kaeprzyk, J. (eds.) (1994): Advances in the Dempster-Shafer Theory of Evidence. Wiley. New York.

University of Bielefeld

University of Bielefeld On the Information Value of Additional Data and Expert Knowledge in Updating Imprecise Prior Information Pertisau, September 2002 Thomas Augustin University of Bielefeld thomas@stat.uni-muenchen.de www.stat.uni-muenchen.de/

More information

THOMAS AUGUSTIN Ludwig-Maximilians University of Munich, Germany

THOMAS AUGUSTIN Ludwig-Maximilians University of Munich, Germany On the Suboptimality of the Generalized Bayes Rule and Robust Bayesian Procedures from the Decision Theoretic Point of View: A Cautionary Note on Updating Imprecise Priors THOMAS AUGUSTIN Ludwig-Maximilians

More information

Regular finite Markov chains with interval probabilities

Regular finite Markov chains with interval probabilities 5th International Symposium on Imprecise Probability: Theories and Applications, Prague, Czech Republic, 2007 Regular finite Markov chains with interval probabilities Damjan Škulj Faculty of Social Sciences

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures

Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures Martin Brüning and Dieter Denneberg FB 3 Universität Bremen, D-28334 Bremen, Germany e-mail:

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series. The Knob of the Discord. Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series The Knob of the Discord Massimiliano Amarante Fabio Maccheroni Discussion Paper No.: 0405-14 Department of Economics Columbia University

More information

Multi-criteria Decision Making by Incomplete Preferences

Multi-criteria Decision Making by Incomplete Preferences Journal of Uncertain Systems Vol.2, No.4, pp.255-266, 2008 Online at: www.jus.org.uk Multi-criteria Decision Making by Incomplete Preferences Lev V. Utkin Natalia V. Simanova Department of Computer Science,

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons

Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons Extensions of Expected Utility Theory and some Limitations of Pairwise Comparisons M. J. SCHERVISH Carnegie Mellon University, USA T. SEIDENFELD Carnegie Mellon University, USA J. B. KADANE Carnegie Mellon

More information

The Logical Concept of Probability and Statistical Inference

The Logical Concept of Probability and Statistical Inference 4th International Symposium on Imprecise Probabilities and Their Applications, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania, 2005 The Logical Concept of Probability and Statistical Inference Kurt Weichselberger (In cooperation

More information

Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs

Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs 26 February 2009 Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs Abstract We analyze three rules that have been proposed for updating capacities. First we consider their implications for updating the Choquet

More information

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Leen Gilbert Gert de Cooman Etienne E. Kerre October 12, 2000 Abstract Probability assessments of events are often linguistic in nature.

More information

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions

Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Soft Computing manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Practical implementation of possibilistic probability mass functions Leen Gilbert, Gert de Cooman 1, Etienne E. Kerre 2 1 Universiteit Gent,

More information

On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory

On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory 131 On Markov Properties in Evidence Theory Jiřina Vejnarová Institute of Information Theory and Automation of the ASCR & University of Economics, Prague vejnar@utia.cas.cz

More information

On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory

On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory 6th International Symposium on Imprecise Probability: Theories and Applications, Durham, United Kingdom, 2009 On Conditional Independence in Evidence Theory Jiřina Vejnarová Institute of Information Theory

More information

Decision-making with belief functions

Decision-making with belief functions Decision-making with belief functions Thierry Denœux Université de Technologie de Compiègne, France HEUDIASYC (UMR CNRS 7253) https://www.hds.utc.fr/ tdenoeux Fourth School on Belief Functions and their

More information

About partial probabilistic information

About partial probabilistic information About partial probabilistic information Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura To cite this version: Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura. About partial probabilistic information. Documents de travail du Centre

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

Nonparametric predictive inference for ordinal data

Nonparametric predictive inference for ordinal data Nonparametric predictive inference for ordinal data F.P.A. Coolen a,, P. Coolen-Schrijner, T. Coolen-Maturi b,, F.F. Ali a, a Dept of Mathematical Sciences, Durham University, Durham DH1 3LE, UK b Kent

More information

Imprecise Probability

Imprecise Probability Imprecise Probability Alexander Karlsson University of Skövde School of Humanities and Informatics alexander.karlsson@his.se 6th October 2006 0 D W 0 L 0 Introduction The term imprecise probability refers

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Coherent Choice Functions Under Uncertainty* OUTLINE

Coherent Choice Functions Under Uncertainty* OUTLINE Coherent Choice Functions Under Uncertainty* Teddy Seidenfeld joint work with Jay Kadane and Mark Schervish Carnegie Mellon University OUTLINE 1. Preliminaries a. Coherent choice functions b. The framework

More information

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from Topics in Data Analysis Steven N. Durlauf University of Wisconsin Lecture Notes : Decisions and Data In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from The Data:

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.ai] 16 Aug 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.ai] 16 Aug 2018 Decision-Making with Belief Functions: a Review Thierry Denœux arxiv:1808.05322v1 [cs.ai] 16 Aug 2018 Université de Technologie de Compiègne, CNRS UMR 7253 Heudiasyc, Compiègne, France email: thierry.denoeux@utc.fr

More information

Lecture notes on statistical decision theory Econ 2110, fall 2013

Lecture notes on statistical decision theory Econ 2110, fall 2013 Lecture notes on statistical decision theory Econ 2110, fall 2013 Maximilian Kasy March 10, 2014 These lecture notes are roughly based on Robert, C. (2007). The Bayesian choice: from decision-theoretic

More information

Serena Doria. Department of Sciences, University G.d Annunzio, Via dei Vestini, 31, Chieti, Italy. Received 7 July 2008; Revised 25 December 2008

Serena Doria. Department of Sciences, University G.d Annunzio, Via dei Vestini, 31, Chieti, Italy. Received 7 July 2008; Revised 25 December 2008 Journal of Uncertain Systems Vol.4, No.1, pp.73-80, 2010 Online at: www.jus.org.uk Different Types of Convergence for Random Variables with Respect to Separately Coherent Upper Conditional Probabilities

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

On maxitive integration

On maxitive integration On maxitive integration Marco E. G. V. Cattaneo Department of Mathematics, University of Hull m.cattaneo@hull.ac.uk Abstract A functional is said to be maxitive if it commutes with the (pointwise supremum

More information

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries

Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Revisiting independence and stochastic dominance for compound lotteries Alexander Zimper Working Paper Number 97 Department of Economics and Econometrics, University of Johannesburg Revisiting independence

More information

A Study of the Pari-Mutuel Model from the Point of View of Imprecise Probabilities

A Study of the Pari-Mutuel Model from the Point of View of Imprecise Probabilities PMLR: Proceedings of Machine Learning Research, vol. 62, 229-240, 2017 ISIPTA 17 A Study of the Pari-Mutuel Model from the Point of View of Imprecise Probabilities Ignacio Montes Enrique Miranda Dep. of

More information

Quantifying Degrees of E-admissibility in Decision Making with Imprecise Probabilities

Quantifying Degrees of E-admissibility in Decision Making with Imprecise Probabilities Christoph Jansen, Georg Schollmeyer and Thomas Augustin Quantifying Degrees of E-admissibility in Decision Making with Imprecise Probabilities Technical Report Number 215, 2018 Department of Statistics

More information

Extendibility of Choquet rational preferences on generalized lotteries

Extendibility of Choquet rational preferences on generalized lotteries Extendibility of Choquet rational preferences on generalized lotteries Giulianella Coletti, Davide Petturiti, and Barbara Vantaggi Dip. Matematica e Informatica, Università di Perugia, Italy coletti@dmi.unipg.it

More information

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1

Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Journal of Economic Theory 105, 531539 (2002) doi:10.1006jeth.2001.2824 Completing the State Space with Subjective States 1 Emre Ozdenoren Department of Economics, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan

More information

Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances

Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances Approximation of Belief Functions by Minimizing Euclidean Distances Thomas Weiler and Ulrich Bodenhofer Software Competence Center Hagenberg A-4232 Hagenberg, Austria e-mail: {thomas.weiler,ulrich.bodenhofer}@scch.at

More information

On the Impact of Robust Statistics on Imprecise Probability Models

On the Impact of Robust Statistics on Imprecise Probability Models ICOSSAR 2009 September 14th, 2009 On the Impact of Robust Statistics on Imprecise Probability Models A Review Thomas Augustin Department of Statistics LMU Munich Germany Robert Hable Department of Mathematics

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information

Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Stochastic dominance with imprecise information Ignacio Montes, Enrique Miranda, Susana Montes University of Oviedo, Dep. of Statistics and Operations Research. Abstract Stochastic dominance, which is

More information

Mathematical Social Sciences

Mathematical Social Sciences Mathematical Social Sciences 74 (2015) 68 72 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Mathematical Social Sciences journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Continuity, completeness, betweenness

More information

Rationality and Uncertainty

Rationality and Uncertainty Rationality and Uncertainty Based on papers by Itzhak Gilboa, Massimo Marinacci, Andy Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler Warwick Aug 23, 2013 Risk and Uncertainty Dual use of probability: empirical frequencies

More information

U n iversity o f H ei delberg. Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition

U n iversity o f H ei delberg. Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition U n iversity o f H ei delberg Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series No. 572 482482 Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition Daniel Heyen and Boris R. Wiesenfarth October

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

Symmetric Probability Theory

Symmetric Probability Theory Symmetric Probability Theory Kurt Weichselberger, Munich I. The Project p. 2 II. The Theory of Interval Probability p. 4 III. The Logical Concept of Probability p. 6 IV. Inference p. 11 Kurt.Weichselberger@stat.uni-muenchen.de

More information

Decision Making Under Uncertainty. First Masterclass

Decision Making Under Uncertainty. First Masterclass Decision Making Under Uncertainty First Masterclass 1 Outline A short history Decision problems Uncertainty The Ellsberg paradox Probability as a measure of uncertainty Ignorance 2 Probability Blaise Pascal

More information

Concepts for decision making under severe uncertainty with partial ordinal and partial cardinal preferences

Concepts for decision making under severe uncertainty with partial ordinal and partial cardinal preferences Concepts for decision making under severe uncertainty with partial ordinal and partial cardinal preferences Christoph Jansen Georg Schollmeyer Thomas Augustin Department of Statistics, LMU Munich ISIPTA

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Bayesian Inference under Ambiguity: Conditional Prior Belief Functions

Bayesian Inference under Ambiguity: Conditional Prior Belief Functions PMLR: Proceedings of Machine Learning Research, vol. 6, 7-84, 07 ISIPTA 7 Bayesian Inference under Ambiguity: Conditional Prior Belief Functions Giulianella Coletti Dip. Matematica e Informatica, Università

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Augustin: Some Basic Results on the Extension of Quasi-Likelihood Based Measurement Error Correction to Multivariate and Flexible Structural Models

Augustin: Some Basic Results on the Extension of Quasi-Likelihood Based Measurement Error Correction to Multivariate and Flexible Structural Models Augustin: Some Basic Results on the Extension of Quasi-Likelihood Based Measurement Error Correction to Multivariate and Flexible Structural Models Sonderforschungsbereich 386, Paper 196 (2000) Online

More information

Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality

Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality Pedro A. Ortega and Daniel A. Braun Department of Engineering, University of Cambridge Trumpington Street, Cambridge, CB2 PZ, UK {dab54,pao32}@cam.ac.uk Abstract.

More information

Conditional Belief Functions: a Comparison among Different Definitions

Conditional Belief Functions: a Comparison among Different Definitions Conditional Belief Functions: a Comparison among Different Definitions Giulianella Coletti Marcello Mastroleo Dipartimento di Matematica e Informatica University of Perugia (coletti,mastroleo)@dipmat.unipg.it

More information

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014 SANDWICH GAMES EHUD LEHRER AND ROEE TEPER July 9, 204 Abstract. The extension of set functions (or capacities) in a concave fashion, namely a concavification, is an important issue in decision theory and

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016 SKLAR S THEOREM IN AN IMPRECISE SETTING IGNACIO MONTES, ENRIQUE MIRANDA, RENATO PELESSONI, AND PAOLO VICIG arxiv:1601.02121v1 [math.pr] 9 Jan 2016 Abstract. Sklar s theorem is an important tool that connects

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting

Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting Sklar s theorem in an imprecise setting Ignacio Montes a,, Enrique Miranda a, Renato Pelessoni b, Paolo Vicig b a University of Oviedo (Spain), Dept. of Statistics and O.R. b University of Trieste (Italy),

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality Felix Brandt Christian Geist Paul Harrenstein Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract

More information

A New Fenchel Dual Problem in Vector Optimization

A New Fenchel Dual Problem in Vector Optimization A New Fenchel Dual Problem in Vector Optimization Radu Ioan Boţ Anca Dumitru Gert Wanka Abstract We introduce a new Fenchel dual for vector optimization problems inspired by the form of the Fenchel dual

More information

Gaussian Estimation under Attack Uncertainty

Gaussian Estimation under Attack Uncertainty Gaussian Estimation under Attack Uncertainty Tara Javidi Yonatan Kaspi Himanshu Tyagi Abstract We consider the estimation of a standard Gaussian random variable under an observation attack where an adversary

More information

A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models

A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models A gentle introduction to imprecise probability models and their behavioural interpretation Gert de Cooman gert.decooman@ugent.be SYSTeMS research group, Ghent University A gentle introduction to imprecise

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi yzx August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form

More information

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION

THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION THE UNIQUE MINIMAL DUAL REPRESENTATION OF A CONVEX FUNCTION HALUK ERGIN AND TODD SARVER Abstract. Suppose (i) X is a separable Banach space, (ii) C is a convex subset of X that is a Baire space (when endowed

More information

A Note On Comparative Probability

A Note On Comparative Probability A Note On Comparative Probability Nick Haverkamp and Moritz Schulz Penultimate draft. Please quote from the published version (Erkenntnis 2012). Abstract A possible event always seems to be more probable

More information

Variations of non-additive measures

Variations of non-additive measures Variations of non-additive measures Endre Pap Department of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Novi Sad Trg D. Obradovica 4, 21 000 Novi Sad, Serbia and Montenegro e-mail: pape@eunet.yu Abstract:

More information

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders

Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Continuity and completeness of strongly independent preorders David McCarthy and Kalle Mikkola Dept. of Philosophy, University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong, Dept. of Mathematics

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

September 2007, France

September 2007, France LIKELIHOOD CONSISTENCY M h dabd ll i (& P t P W kk ) Mohammed Abdellaoui (& Peter P. Wakker) September 2007, France A new method is presented for measuring beliefs/likelihoods under uncertainty. It will

More information

Questions in Decision Theory

Questions in Decision Theory Questions in Decision Theory Itzhak Gilboa June 15, 2011 Gilboa () Questions in Decision Theory June 15, 2011 1 / 18 History Pascal and Bernoulli Gilboa () Questions in Decision Theory June 15, 2011 2

More information

Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox. by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper

Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox. by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper Explaining the harmonic sequence paradox by Ulrich Schmidt, and Alexander Zimper No. 1724 August 2011 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No.

More information

Only Intervals Preserve the Invertibility of Arithmetic Operations

Only Intervals Preserve the Invertibility of Arithmetic Operations Only Intervals Preserve the Invertibility of Arithmetic Operations Olga Kosheleva 1 and Vladik Kreinovich 2 1 Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering 2 Department of Computer Science University

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

Projektpartner. Sonderforschungsbereich 386, Paper 172 (1999) Online unter:

Projektpartner. Sonderforschungsbereich 386, Paper 172 (1999) Online unter: Augustin: Neyman-Pearson Testing under Interval Probability by Globally Least Favorable Pairs: A Survey of Huber-Strassen Theory and Some Results on its Extension to General Interval Probability Sonderforschungsbereich

More information

Decision Making under Interval and Fuzzy Uncertainty: Towards an Operational Approach

Decision Making under Interval and Fuzzy Uncertainty: Towards an Operational Approach University of Texas at El Paso DigitalCommons@UTEP Departmental Technical Reports (CS) Department of Computer Science 7-1-2012 Decision Making under Interval and Fuzzy Uncertainty: Towards an Operational

More information

CONDITIONAL MODELS: COHERENCE AND INFERENCE THROUGH SEQUENCES OF JOINT MASS FUNCTIONS

CONDITIONAL MODELS: COHERENCE AND INFERENCE THROUGH SEQUENCES OF JOINT MASS FUNCTIONS CONDITIONAL MODELS: COHERENCE AND INFERENCE THROUGH SEQUENCES OF JOINT MASS FUNCTIONS ENRIQUE MIRANDA AND MARCO ZAFFALON Abstract. We call a conditional model any set of statements made of conditional

More information

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009 Measurable Ambiguity with Wolfgang Pesendorfer August 2009 A Few Definitions A Lottery is a (cumulative) probability distribution over monetary prizes. It is a probabilistic description of the DMs uncertain

More information

Decision Making under Uncertainty using Imprecise Probabilities

Decision Making under Uncertainty using Imprecise Probabilities Matthias C. M. Troffaes. Decision making under uncertainty using imprecise probabilities. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 45:17-29, 2007. Decision Making under Uncertainty using Imprecise

More information

A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions

A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions A survey of the theory of coherent lower previsions Enrique Miranda Abstract This paper presents a summary of Peter Walley s theory of coherent lower previsions. We introduce three representations of coherent

More information

P (Ei*) PI(Ei*).P2(Ei*) [ i~i,pl(ei)'p2(ei) ]-1 i=l [ Infi~i,Pl(Ei).P2(Ei) 1-1 [ Inf~ (Ei).P2(Ei)] -1

P (Ei*) PI(Ei*).P2(Ei*) [ i~i,pl(ei)'p2(ei) ]-1 i=l [ Infi~i,Pl(Ei).P2(Ei) 1-1 [ Inf~ (Ei).P2(Ei)] -1 APPENDIX Application of Formula (3.21) to Structures Defined by k-ppds. We have P,(Ei*) i=l P(Ei*) = ~PI(EI) "..." PI(Ei*) "..." PI(Ei) (3.21) and Sup Pj(Ei) = Uji PiES~. Inf Pj(Ei) = Lji PjES~. i=l,...,k;

More information

S-MEASURES, T -MEASURES AND DISTINGUISHED CLASSES OF FUZZY MEASURES

S-MEASURES, T -MEASURES AND DISTINGUISHED CLASSES OF FUZZY MEASURES K Y B E R N E T I K A V O L U M E 4 2 ( 2 0 0 6 ), N U M B E R 3, P A G E S 3 6 7 3 7 8 S-MEASURES, T -MEASURES AND DISTINGUISHED CLASSES OF FUZZY MEASURES Peter Struk and Andrea Stupňanová S-measures

More information

Persuading a Pessimist

Persuading a Pessimist Persuading a Pessimist Afshin Nikzad PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract While in practice most persuasion mechanisms have a simple structure, optimal signals in the Bayesian persuasion framework may not be so.

More information

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Mantas Radzvilas July 2017 Abstract In 1986 David Gauthier proposed an arbitration scheme

More information

Reasoning with Uncertainty

Reasoning with Uncertainty Reasoning with Uncertainty Representing Uncertainty Manfred Huber 2005 1 Reasoning with Uncertainty The goal of reasoning is usually to: Determine the state of the world Determine what actions to take

More information

A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral

A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral Brice Mayag Thales R & T University of Paris I brice.mayag@thalesgroup.com Michel Grabisch University of Paris I Centre d Economie de la Sorbonne 106-112

More information

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES

ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES Submitted to the Annals of Probability ON THE EQUIVALENCE OF CONGLOMERABILITY AND DISINTEGRABILITY FOR UNBOUNDED RANDOM VARIABLES By Mark J. Schervish, Teddy Seidenfeld, and Joseph B. Kadane, Carnegie

More information

The willingness to pay for health improvements under comorbidity ambiguity 1

The willingness to pay for health improvements under comorbidity ambiguity 1 The willingness to pay for health improvements under comorbidity ambiguity 1 Yoichiro Fujii, Osaka Sangyo University Yusuke Osaki 2, Osaka Sangyo University Abstract Accumulated medical information is

More information

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty*

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* journal of economic theory 75, 194204 (1997) article no. ET962280 On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* Elchanan Ben-Porath Tel-Aviv University, Ramit-Aviv, 69 978 Tel-Aviv, Israel; and Northwestern

More information

An Update on Generalized Information Theory

An Update on Generalized Information Theory An Update on Generalized Information Theory GEORGE J. KLIR Binghamton University (SUNY), USA Abstract The purpose of this paper is to survey recent developments and trends in the area of generalized information

More information

Semantics of the relative belief of singletons

Semantics of the relative belief of singletons Semantics of the relative belief of singletons Fabio Cuzzolin INRIA Rhône-Alpes 655 avenue de l Europe, 38334 SAINT ISMIER CEDEX, France Fabio.Cuzzolin@inrialpes.fr Summary. In this paper we introduce

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 26 Mar 2008

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 26 Mar 2008 arxiv:0803.3679v1 [math.pr] 26 Mar 2008 The game-theoretic martingales behind the zero-one laws Akimichi Takemura 1 takemura@stat.t.u-tokyo.ac.jp, http://www.e.u-tokyo.ac.jp/ takemura Vladimir Vovk 2 vovk@cs.rhul.ac.uk,

More information

Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs

Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs Decomposability and time consistency of risk averse multistage programs arxiv:1806.01497v1 [math.oc] 5 Jun 2018 A. Shapiro School of Industrial and Systems Engineering Georgia Institute of Technology Atlanta,

More information

A Criterion for the Stochasticity of Matrices with Specified Order Relations

A Criterion for the Stochasticity of Matrices with Specified Order Relations Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Vol. XL, 55 64 (2009) A Criterion for the Stochasticity of Matrices with Specified Order Relations Luca Bortolussi and Andrea Sgarro Abstract. We tackle the following problem:

More information

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures

Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued Risk Measures Applied Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 8, 2014, no. 109, 5439-5447 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com http://dx.doi.org/10.12988/ams.2014.43176 Monetary Risk Measures and Generalized Prices Relevant to Set-Valued

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures

On Kusuoka Representation of Law Invariant Risk Measures MATHEMATICS OF OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 38, No. 1, February 213, pp. 142 152 ISSN 364-765X (print) ISSN 1526-5471 (online) http://dx.doi.org/1.1287/moor.112.563 213 INFORMS On Kusuoka Representation of

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

BIVARIATE P-BOXES AND MAXITIVE FUNCTIONS. Keywords: Uni- and bivariate p-boxes, maxitive functions, focal sets, comonotonicity,

BIVARIATE P-BOXES AND MAXITIVE FUNCTIONS. Keywords: Uni- and bivariate p-boxes, maxitive functions, focal sets, comonotonicity, BIVARIATE P-BOXES AND MAXITIVE FUNCTIONS IGNACIO MONTES AND ENRIQUE MIRANDA Abstract. We give necessary and sufficient conditions for a maxitive function to be the upper probability of a bivariate p-box,

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

An axiomatic approach of the discrete Choquet integral as a tool to aggregate interacting criteria

An axiomatic approach of the discrete Choquet integral as a tool to aggregate interacting criteria An axiomatic approach of the discrete Choquet integral as a tool to aggregate interacting criteria Jean-Luc Marichal Revised version, December 22, 999 Abstract The most often used operator to aggregate

More information