Pre-probabilistic sophistication. Osamu Kada. July, 2009

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Pre-probabilistic sophistication. Osamu Kada. July, 2009"

Transcription

1 Pre-probabilistic sophistication Osamu Kada Faculty of Engineering, Yokohama National University 79-5 Tokiwadai, Hodogaya, Yokohama , Japan ( July, 2009 We consider pre-probabilistic sophistication where an agent s two-consequence act is based on a probabilistic belief over a finite λ-system of events. We identify the likelihood relation on the events such that if an agent is pre-probabilistically sophisticated, then its probability measure must represents the likelihood relation. We give conditions on the relation that characterize pre-probabilistic sophistication. We also give a minimal condition that extends pre-probabilistic sophistication to probabilistic sophistication when events constitute an algebra. Keywords: Subjective probability, uncertainty, likelihood consistency, nonexpected utility, pre-probabilistic sophistication, probabilistic sophistication.

2 . Introduction Savage (954) characterized choice under uncertainty that is represented by mathematical expectation of utility with respect to probabilistic belief: subjective expected utility (SEU). Starting with Machina and Schmeidler (992), there has been a string of papers that attempted to characterize choice under uncertainty that does not conform to SEU, and yet that choice is based on probabilistic belief. An agent is called probabilistic sophisticated if she makes such choice patterns: she has a unique subjective probabilities such that two acts that generate the same distribution on consequences must come from the same indifferent class. This notion of probabilistic sophistication is composed of two parts: (a) the agent has a unique probabilistic belief over events which is characterized by her two-consequence acts, and (b) her (many-consequence) acts are based on this probabilistic belief. These two parts are conceptually different, and it seems to be considered separately. We call pre-probabilistic sophistication which is a notion corresponding to the first part (a). That is, an agent is pre-probabilistic sophisticated if two-consequence act is based on a probabilistic belief over events. It seems that there are differences between an agent s preferences on acts of two consequences and three or more consequences. She may have probabilistic belief and behave according to the belief in a simple betting, but in a more complicated betting, she may not behave according to the probabilistic belief. For instance, consider an agent who computes probabilities of events according to an information available and according to these probabilities she makes a choice, but she has a bounded capacity to calculate them. In the choice of simple betting, say, betting to two events A or B, she can calculate two probabilities that A occurs or B occurs, so that she can choose A or B according to its probabilities. But in the choice of more complicated betting, say, betting to [$30 if A, $20 if A 2, $0 if A 3 ] or [$30 if B, $20 if B 2, $0 if B 3 ], she cannot calculate six probabilities of A i, B i, i =, 2, 3 because of her limited ability. So that she makes a choice not by probabilistic belief but according to another one, say, by labelling; names or numbers. In this case, she may be pre-probabilistic sophisticated but not probabilistic sophisticated. 2

3 It seems that there are many examples as the above which show this gap between pre-probabilistic sophistication and probabilistic sophistication, because of bounded rationality, or by other behavioral aspects. Considering pre-probabilistic sophistication has its importance per se, but also for probabilistic sophistication. First, to extract subjective probabilities, considering many-consequence acts is complicated, not simple in comparison with twoconsequence acts. Second, there arises a question as to what condition that distinguishes between pre-probabilistic sophistication and probabilistic sophistication. This is an interesting question, and serves as an understanding of probabilistic sophistication. For pre-probabilistic sophistication, first question which must be considered is as follows: What is the likelihood relation on events such that pre-probabilistic sophisticated agent must have? If we require stochastic dominance in probabilistic sophistication, then the relation by betting is the likelihood relation that we are seeking (see Sarin Wakker (2000)). But in general, it is not known what the relation it is. Chew and Sagi (2006) introduced exchangeability, and showed that exchangeability based likelihood relation must satisfy event non-satiation. Examples of delayed resolution of uncertainty and Machina s Mom (see Example 2.5) do not satisfy event non-satiation, therefore, their likelihood relations are not based on exchangeability. In this paper, we define more probable relation on events and show that it is the likelihood relation that pre-probabilistic sophisticated agent s probability measure represents. This is defined as follows. We say events A and B are equally evaluated if they are indifferent by simple betting on them. This equally evaluated binary relation on events is not equivalent to equally probable relation as the above example shows, but restricting to small events, whom we call minimal events, the equivalence holds. We define that an event A is more probable than an event B if A contains an event B such that B and B have finite partitions by minimal events and they are piecewise equally evaluated. This definition conforms to additivity of probability measure. The notion of more probable relation might seem to be complicated, but with other axioms, it is shown that it is not complicated (see Remark 2.). 3

4 Second question is: What conditions on the more probable relation ensure preprobabilistic sophistication? We give two conditions on the more probable relation. One is the likelihood consistency on the relation, which is a reminiscence of likelihood consistency by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2008) or of event non-satiation by Chew and Sagi (2006) (see section 3). The other is the Pre-probabilistic Belief (PB), which requires that two events have finite partitions by minimal events which are piecewise equally evaluated, then they are equally evaluated. This is a reminiscence of additivity of probability measure. With these axioms and Archimedean Property and solvability, we get a characterization of pre-probabilistically sophistication. Third question mentioned as before: What condition extends pre-probabilistic sophistication to probabilistic sophistication? We show that Probabilistically Sophisticated Belief, which is a notion stronger than PB, is the condition that extends pre-probabilistic sophistication to probabilistically sophistication. This paper proceeds as follows. In section 2, we characterize pre-probabilistic sophistication; Subsection 2. is the definition of pre-probabilistic sophistication. Subsection 2.2 gives examples. Subsection 2.3 gives the notion of more probable relation, showing that a pre-probabilistic sophisticated agent s probability measure must represent it. Subsection 2.4 characterizes pre-probabilistic sophistication. Subsection 2.5 gives a condition that extends pre-probabilistic sophistication to probabilistic sophistication. In section 3, we give relations between our notions of minimal events and likelihood consistency, event non-satiation by Chew and Sagi (2006), and ps-likelihood consistency by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2008). In the Appendix, some lemmas for our main theorem and proofs are given. 2. Pre-probabilistic Sophistication 2.. Definition Let S be a set of states. A collection A of subsets of S is called a finite λ-system if it is closed with respect to complements and finite disjoint unions, and contains S. We consider on a finite λ-system. Restricting a domain of probability measure to λ-system was considered by Zhang (999) and Epstein and Zhang (200) relating to unambiguity. Consider a domain of probability measure as the events the agent 4

5 knows or can conceive the probability based on her some information; then even if she has her subjective probabilities on two events, she may not have a probability of the event of their intersection. Thus, finite λ-system seems to be an appropriate notion to be considered. Elements of A are called events. For E A, we denote by E c its complement. Let C be a set of consequences. A (simple) act f from (S, A) to C is a mapping from ( S to C such ) that f (c) A for all c C and its range is finite. f = A A 2... A n = [c c c 2... c i on A i ] n i= denotes the act that yields c i C on A i n A, i =,..., n. Let F = F((S, A); C) be the set of all acts from (S, A) to C. For each consequence c C, we identify c as a constant act. For A A, acts f, g, we denote by f A g the act that yields f on A and g on A c. A preference relation over A is a binary relation on the set of acts F = F((S, A); C), and throughout this paper we assume that is a weak order; that is, it is complete (f g or g f for all f, g) and transitive (f g and g h implies f h). A function V : F R represents if: for all f, g F, f g iff V (f) V (g). Savage (954) defined that an event A is null if two acts are indifferent whenever they are the same outside of A. This notion is to mean that an agent consider A virtually impossible (Savage (954, p. 24)), and when she is probabilistically sophisticated, this is equivalent to her assessment of the probability of A as zero. We consider pre-probabilistically sophisticated agents, that is, her subjective probability is based only simple betting (two-consequence act), so the definition must be modified. That is, we define null to mean that its subjective probability is zero for an agent who is pre-probabilistically sophisticated. So that even if she has subjective probabilities, if she is not probabilistically sophisticated, a null event may not be null in the sense of Savage. Further, to accommodate with finite λ-system, we take a weaker condition as a definition of null. Definition 2.. Event A is null if for each event B A, consequences c, c, c B c c (see Lemma 4.7). Outcomes c, c C are equivalent to each other if for each event A, c A c c (see Remark 2.9, (b) (i)). Nondegeneracy holds if there are 5

6 non-equivalent consequences c, c. If nondegeneracy holds, then there is a nonnull event. Remark 2.2. Event A is Savage-null if f A h g A h for all acts f, g, h. Savagenull implies null, but the converse does not hold. Restricting Savage-null to two consequence acts, we get the following: for all B, B A and D A c, for all c, c, c (B D) c c (B D)c. Letting B = D =, this becomes our definition. In probability theory, events considered constitute an (σ-)algebra. Zhang (999), and Epstein and Zhang (200) considered more general class of events, λ-system, and Kopylov (2005) introduced more general mosaic. Earlier, consideration of general finite λ-system as the domain of probability measure was given relating quantummechanics by Krantz et al (97). We consider a finitely additive probability measure on the finite λ-system A. Let P be a finitely additive probability measure on A. P represents a binary relation l on A if: for all A, B A, A l B iff P (A) P (B). P is solvable if for all A, B A, P (A) P (B) implies that there exists B A such that B A and P (B ) = P (B). A nonnull event A is an atom if A cannot be partitioned into two nonnull events. P is purely and uniformly atomic if the union of all atoms has unit measure and all atoms have equal measure. An agent is pre-probabilistically sophisticated if she has a unique subjective probabilities on events such that if the probabilities on two events are the same, she equally evaluates the events. She is probabilistically sophisticated if she has a unique subjective probabilities such that two acts that generate the same distribution on consequences must come from the same indifferent class. Formally, we define as follows. Definition 2.3. (Pre-probabilistically Sophistication) Let be a preference relation over a finite λ-system A. (a) is pre-probabilistically sophisticated if there exists a unique finitely additive and solvable probability measure P on A such that P (A) = 0 whenever A is null, and for any pair of events A and B in A and consequences c and c in C, (2.) P (A) = P (B) implies c A c c B c. 6

7 (b) is probabilistically sophisticated if in the above (a), (2.) is replaced by the following: for any pair of act f and g (2.2) P (f (c)) = P (g (c)) for all consequences c implies f g. Taking f, g to be two-consequence acts c A c and c B c, respectively, (2.2) becomes (2.), so that pre-probabilistically sophistication is a notion weaker than probabilistically sophistication. As stated in the introduction, consider an agent who calculates probabilities of events according to an information available to her, but for its limited ability of its calculation who can only make a probabilistic belief on simple betting. For such an agent, her preference relation may be pre-probabilistically sophisticated but may not be probabilistically sophisticated Examples We give examples of pre-probabilistically sophistication. Example 2.4. (cf. Chew and Sagi (2006, Example )) Let A = {A, B, C} be a partition of a state space S, C = [0, ], and is represented by: ( ) A B C V = x + y + z (x y)(y z)(z x) x. x y z 8 Then is pre-probabilistically sophisticated with the uniform probability measure, and satisfies eventwise monotonicity. This follows by showing that( partial derivatives are positive except finite points. But for different x, y, z, V ) A B C x y z ( ) A B C V due to the asymmetry between x and y in the last term. Hence, y x z is not probabilistically sophisticated. The following Examples 2.5 do not satisfy event non-satiation (see section 3.) or eventwise monotonicity, and these are given by Machina and Schmeidler (992) (delayed resolution of uncertainty), and by Grant (995) (social ordering or ethical preference over subjectively uncertain acts). Example 2.5. (a) (Delayed resolution of uncertainty) Let S = [0, ], A = B [0,] : the Borel algebra on [0, ], and ( P is the Lebesgue ) measure. Let C = {x, x 2,..., x n }, A A and is represented by: V 2... A n d = max n x x 2... x c D i= u(x i, c)p (A i ), n 7

8 here D is a set of actions taken before the uncertainty is resolved, and u is von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function. Since auxiliary action c D must be made before the state is known, although an agent has an expected utility after she chooses c D, she is not an expected utility maximizer. For instance, consider the following story. Suppose you are going to a conference, and it is uncertain whether you can have your favorite coffee for free in the conference or not. You make a choice between going to a coffee house or not before the conference is held with the following preference ranking: (not coffee, coffee) (coffee, not coffee) (coffee, coffee) (not coffee, not coffee), here (not coffee, coffee) means you do not go to a coffee house having no coffee before the conference, and have your favorite coffee for free in the conference; similarly for others. Let p be your subjective probability that there is your favorite coffee for free in the conference. If p = 0, you may go to a coffee house and have a coffee, but as p increases in some degrees, your expected payoff will decrease, which means you are locally satiated at p = 0. Let n = m = 2, x = there is a favorite coffee for free in the conference, x 2 = there is no favorite coffee for free in the conference, ( c = go) to a( coffee ) house, c 2 = not go to a ( coffee house, ) a a u(x i, c j ) = a ij, 2 a b A A =, b c > a d. Then V 2 a 2 a 22 c d d = x x 2 max{ (c a)p + c, (b d)p + d}, here p = P (A ). Letting p = p = c d, we have the following Figure. b d c d and b+c a d b c a d 0 p p p Figure. Delayed resolution of uncertainty 8

9 (b) (Social ordering or ethical preference over subjectively uncertain acts) Consider a social planner as Machina s Mom, or an individual of ethical preference as Harsanyi (955) considered. Let S = [0, ], A = B [0,], P be as the above (a). Let C = {x,..., x n } and consider it as the set of social consequences, there are I individuals, and social preference or individual ( ethical preference ) over A A subjectively uncertain prospects (an act) f = 2... A n. Suppose x x 2... x n the preference is represented by: ( ) A A V 2... A n s = W (U x x 2... x (p),..., U I (p)), n here p = n j= P (A j)δ xj and U i (p) = n j= u i(x j )P (A j ) is an expected utility with von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function u i for each individual i. W is a social welfare function (SWF); (i) W is generalized utilitarian if W (u,..., u I ) = I i= g(u i) for an increasing and concave function g( ) (see Mas-colell et al. (995 Example 22.C.3)), and it is purely utilitarian if g is the identity. (ii) W is quadratic if it is a polynomial of order two (see Epstein and Siegel (992)). If W is not purely but generalized utilitarian, then it does not satisfy event non-satiation, therefore does not satisfy event monotonicity (see Figure 3). Consider the example of Machina s Mom, which is based on Diamond (967): a mother gives an indivisible treat to her daughter or her son. Suppose there is a subjective uncertainty upon which the mother submmit her choice whether she gives the good to her daughter or her son. Let p be the probability that the daughter gets the good. By consideration of fairness, p = is the best 2 for the mother, and the more the probability gets greater than, the less 2 becomes the mother s satisfaction. Therefore, at p ( =, the mother is satiated. This example is quadratic: n = I = 2, V 2 2 ) A A s = W (p x x, p 2 ) = 2 { if i = j p p 2, here p i = P (A i ), and U i (p δ x + p 2 δ x2 ) = p i, u i (x j ) = 0 if i j. ( ) A A More generally, let V 2... A n s = W (p x x 2... x,..., p n ) = i<j p ip j, p i = n P (A i ), U i ( n j= p jδ xj ) = p i, u i is as the above. This is an example of quadratic 9

10 form axiomatized by Epstein and Siegel (992). It is easy to see that the above W s has the maximum when p i = for all i. n p W (p, p ) = p ( p ) 0 2 p W (p, p ) = p + p Figure 2. Machina s mom Figure 3. Generalized utilitarian The following Examples satisfy event non-satiation but do not satisfy eventwise monotonicity or other axioms, which are given by Chew and Sagi (2006). Example 2.6. Let S = [0, ], A = B [0,], P be as in Example 2.5 (a). (a) (Lexicographic preference) Let C = R. For f P = n i= p iδ xi, let E(f) = n i= p ix i, Var(f) = n i= p i(x i E(f)) 2. Define f g if E(f) > E(g), or E(f) = E(g) and Var(f) < Var(g), and, as usual. Then as stated by Chew and Sagi (2006), does not satisfy P6 (continuity). (b) Let C = R 2 +. For L = n i= p iδ xi (R 2 +), x i = (x i, x 2 i ), let U(L) = n i= p i( + x i )( + x 2 i ) Var(L), here Var(L) = n 2 i= p i x i E(L), is the Euclidean metric, E(L) = n i= p ix i. Let be represented by: for f F(A), V (f) = U(f P ). P (A) = P (B). Hence, Let x = (, 0), y = (0, 0). Then x A y x B y implies A ev B iff P (A) = P (B). In this example, x A y x B y for some x y does not imply P (A) = P (B). Let x = (4, 0), y = (0, 3), A, B be events such that P (A) = 3 5, P (B) = 5. Then x y and x A y x B y but P (A) P (B). As shown by Chew and Sagi (2006, Appendix), this example (b) violates P3 (event monotonicity), P4 (comparative likelihood) in Machina and Schmeidler 0

11 (992), and P 3 CU, P 3 CL, and P 4 CE in Grant (995). But the above examples (a) and (b) satisfy Chew and Sagi s (2006) Axioms, and also our Axioms What is the Likelihood Relation that a Pre-probabilistically Sophisticated Agent Must Have? To extract probability measure from preference, Savage-De Finetti betting method is such that it considers how an agent bets on events. That is, an event A is more likely than an event B, denoted by A l B, if c A c c B c for all c c, and considers conditions on l for the existence of a probability measure that represents l. If we require stochastic dominance in probabilistic sophistication, then l is the likelihood relation that the probability measure of a pre-probabilistically sophisticated agent represents as noted by Sarin Wakker (2000, pp. 92)). But generally, it is not the case. Thus we have a question: For a pre-probabilistically sophisticated agent, what is the likelihood relation that she has? We define a more probable relation pr and shows that it is the likelihood relation that the probability measure of pre-probabilistically sophistication represents. First we introduce an equally evaluated relation on events. This is a notion that an agent s evaluation on the two events which is represented by simple betting on the events are the same. Definition 2.7. Event A is revealed equally evaluated as event B, denoted by A ev B, if for all consequences c, c c A c c B c. Note that two events iff their compliments are equally evaluated, and ev transitive. Next we define minimal events, and equally probable relation on events, which does not necessarily coincide with the equally evaluated relation. Then we define more probable relation. For a pair of events A and B, if we divide them fine enough to satisfy monotonocity on each piece, and they are piecewise equally evaluated, then by additivity of probabilistic belief, A and B will be equally probable. And if A contains an event which is equally probable with B, then A will be more probable is

12 than B. Thus, we define equally probable and more probable relation on events as follows. Definition 2.8. (a) Event A A is minimal if: for each event B A, B ev A implies A \B is null. A is strongly minimal if each event B A is minimal. (b) Event A is revealed equally probable as event B, denoted by A pr B, if there exist finite partitions by minimal events {A i } n i= and {B i } n i= of A and B, respectively, such that A i ev B i for all i. (c) Event A is revealed strictly more probable than event B, denoted by A pr B, if there exists an event B A with nonnull A \ B such that B pr B; and A is revealed more probable than event B, denoted by A pr B, if A pr B or A pr B. Hereafter, we assume that for each event A, there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events of A. Therefore, Example in Remark 2.9 (c) (see Appendix) is excluded. If we consider sufficient many times of adequate coin flips, this assumption will be reasonable. Remark 2.9. Suppose that A is an algebra. (a) Let A be the equivalence class by the relation that setwise difference is null. Define A B for A, B A if there exists A A, B B such that A B and A ev B. Then A A is minimal iff A is minimal by the above relation. (b) Savage s P3 (Eventwise monotonicity) states that for all consequences c, c, Savage-nonnull event A, c A f c Af iff c c. Assume P3. Then, (i) c, c are non-equivalent to each other iff c c or c c; (ii) all events are minimal; and (iii) event non-satiation defined by Chew and Sagi (2006) holds (see section 3.2). (c) There is an example that there are no nonnull minimal events. (d) Consider Example 2.5 (a). Let A be an event and let p be its probability. Then A is not minimal if p (p, p], A is minimal if p [0, p] (p, ], and A is strongly minimal if p [0, p]. (e) We consider Example 2.5 (b) of Machina s Mom. Let A be an event such that P (A). Then there exists a subevent 2 A of A such that P (A ) = P (A). 2

13 Since V m (x A y) = P (A )[ P (A )] = [ P (A)]P A = V m (x A y), we have A ev A with nonnull A\A. Hence, A is not minimal. For each event A with P A, A is strongly minimal. Let A = (0, 3], B = (0, ], C = ( 3, ]. Then A is not minimal, and A ev B but A C ev B C. Therefore, ev cannot be a symmetric part of a likelihood relation in this example (cf. Chew and Sagi (2006, 2.2. Lemma )). If consequence space is enlarged in this example as Chew and Sagi (2006, pp 779) argues, then event non-satiation holds. But it seems that the question is: If restricted to two consequences, is it possible to characterize Mom s probabilistic belief by her preference? The following proposition shows that the more probable relation is the likelihood relation that the probability measure of pre-probabilistically sophistication represents. In particular, the above holds for probabilistically sophistication. Proposition 2.0. Let be pre-probabilistically sophisticated with its probability measure P. Assume that there is a finite partition by minimal events for each event. Then P represents pr. Remark 2.. Although the more probable relation pr is the only binary relation on events whom the probability measure of pre-probabilistic sophistication represents, it may be argued that it is somewhat complicated. It appears that in order to check A pr B, we may have to apply Definition 2.8 (b) to all finite partitions by minimal events of A and B, and in order to check whether an event is minimal, apply Definition 2.8 (a) for all subsets of this event; therefore it might seem to have little descriptive value. But in characterization of pre-probabilistic sophistication in section 2.4, it is shown in Lemma 4.0 that with some assumptions (Axioms S, LC and PB), A pr B iff for each partition {B i } n i= of B by minimal events, there exists a partition {A i } n i= of A by minimal events such that A i ev B i for all i. Therefore, we need not to apply Definition 2.8 to all finite partitions by minimal events but to some finite partition by minimal events. Moreover, we assume that there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events for each event, which may be reasonable by considering, for instance, by sufficient many times of adequate coin flips. Therefore, it is not complicated. If we assume eventwise monotonicity, then all events are minimal (Remark 2.9 (b) (ii)). 3

14 2.4. Characterization of Pre-probabilistic Sophistication We consider conditions on the more probable relation pr, and characterize preprobabilistic sophistication. If there is a probability measure representing pr, the probability measure is necessarily solvable (see Proposition 2.0). In other words, in the definition of pr, solvability is implicitly assumed. Our first assumption is that if there exists a sequence of nonnull events that are equally probable, then they are finite. Axiom A (Archimedean Property): There exists no infinite sequence of disjoint nonnull events {A j } j= such that A j pr A j+ for all j. The second assumption ensures that for every two events, one event is more probable than the other. If the agent s behavior is based on a unique probability measure, then the above assumption is reasonable. Axiom S (Solvability): For all strongly minimal events A and B, there exists A B such that A ev A, or there exists B A such that B ev B. Lemma 2.2. Assume that there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events for each event. Then Axiom S holds iff pr is complete. We give a sufficient condition for Solvability. We assume that A is an σ-algebra. The following axiom weakens P4 (Weak Comparative Probability) by Savage (954). P4 If A and B are strongly minimal events, c and c are non-equivalent consequences, such that c A c c B c, then d A d d B d for all consequences d and d. For consequences c, c, define a binary relation c,c on events by: A c,c B if c A c c B c. Define c,c and c,c as usual. Axiom C (Continuity): (a) (Small Event Continuity on Minimal Events) There exists a sequence of refining finite non-null partitions {S n } n=, S n = {Si n } k n i= such that if S n+ j Si n then S n+ j+ Sn i or S n i+ and the following holds: For all strongly minimal events A, B and consequences c, c with A c,c B, 4

15 (i) for each n, m m, A ( m i=si n ) c,c A ( ) m i=si n, and there exist n and m such that A c,c A ( m i=s n i ) c,c B, or (ii) for each n, m m, B ( ) m i=si n c,c B ( m i=si n ), and there exist n and m such that (b) (Monotone Continuity) A c,c B ( m i=s n i ) c,c B. If {E n } n= is a decreasing sequence of events, A, B are strongly minimal events, c, c are consequences, such that A c,c E n c,c B for all n, then A c,c n=e n c,c B. Roughly speaking, the above (a) shows that for strongly minimal events A, B, c,c is monotone with respect to set inclusion on E A,B := {E A c,c E c,c B}. The example 2.5 (b) Machina s Mom is the case of (i), [P (B), P (A)] [0, ], and c,c 2 is increasing on E A,B. The example 2.5 (a) Delayed resolution of uncertainty is the case of (ii), [P (A), P (B)] [0, p ], and c,c is decreasing on E A,B. Considering {S n i } kn i= as the events of flips of a coin n times, Axiom C may be a reasonable assumption of continuity. In this case, define as follows. Suppose S = Ω {H, T }, and let H n and T n be events of head and tail in n-th coin flips, respectively. We define a sequence of partitions {S n } n=(s n = {S n i } 2n i=) of S inductively as follows: S = {H }, S 2 = {T }, and S n+ 2i = {Sn i H n+ }, S n+ 2i = {S n i T n+ }, i =,..., 2 n. Axiom C (a) and (b) are translations of P6 of Savage (954) and the condition of Villegas (964), respectively. The following lemma shows that P4 and Axiom C (Continuity) is a sufficient condition for solvability. Lemma 2.3. Suppose A is a σ-algebra. implies Axiom S (Solvability). Then P4 and Axiom C (Continuity) The next assumption excludes inconsistencies between comparative measurements of two pair of events. Axiom LC (Likelihood Consistency): A pr B and A pr B for no events A, B. 5

16 LC implies that there does not exist two pairs of non-null partitions of A and B as follows: one is such that strict subset of the partition of A is piecewise equally evaluated with the partition of B itself, and the other is such that the two partitions of A and B are piecewise equally evaluated. For instance, consider the case of ambiguous averse agent as in the Ellsberg paradox (so that she does not have subjective probabilities). Consider a partition of A by unambiguous events, and two partitions of B by ambiguous events and by unamgiuous ones, respectively. Then by ambiguity aversion, a strict subset of the partition of A may be piecewise equally evaluated with the partiton of B by ambiguous events, but the partition of A itself may piecewise equally evaluated in comparison with the partition of B by unambiguous events. This implies that LC does not hold. Hence, LC excludes such an agnet. The next assumption rephrase the condition of pre-probabilistic sophistication if there exists a probability measure representing equally probable relation pr. Axiom PB (Pre-probabilistically Sophisticated Belief ): For all events A and B, A pr B implies A ev B. Again, consider the case of ambiguous averse agent. Assume that there is a partition of an event A by unambiguous events and a partition of an event B by ambiguous events such that they are piecewise equally evaluated. Since she is ambiguous averse, she may strictly prefer A to B, which means that PB does not hold. Hence, PB excludes such an agnet. Note that even if two events are equally evaluated, it does not necessarily mean that they are equally probable. For instance, in Example of Machina s Mom 2.5 (b), to give the indivisible good to her son with probability is equally evaluated as to give him with probability 0, because she considers equality between her son and daughter. Remark 2.4. If we assume Savage s P3 (Eventwise monotonicity), then PB implies LC. Therefore in this case, LC does not needed. To consider more concretely, we give the following exampl. Example 2.5. Consider the following two-coin example due to Schmeidler, which is equivalent to two-color urn example of Ellsberg (96) (see Gilboa (2004)): One 6

17 coin is such that an agent is familiar with and she believes to be fair, another one unfamiliar, and bet on sides of the either coin. She may consider fifty-fifty on each side of the unfamiliar coin as well as to the familiar coin, but bet on the head (tail) of the familiar coin rather than the head (tail) of the unfamiliar coin. Let A f = {H f, T f } be the events that flip of familiar coin of known probability is head and tail, and similarly A uf = {H uf, T uf } for unfamiliar, ambiguous coin. Let S = {H f H uf, H f T uf, T f H uf, T f T uf }, A = 2 S. By symmetry, we may assume H f T uf ev T f H uf. Then we have H f = (H f T uf ) (H f H uf ) pr (T f H uf ) (H f H uf ) = H uf. But H f ev H uf. Thus, Head of the familiar coin and Head of the unfamiliar coin is equally probable but not equally evaluated, which implies that PB does not hold. On the other hand, LC holds. But in this case, the preference does not satisfy Axiom S, solvablity. So, enlarge the state space S to S := S [0, ]. Since H uf [0, ] is less likely than H f [0, ], assuming continuity and monotonicity, there may exist an interval J such that H uf [0, ] ev H f J, and similarly, T uf [0, ] ev T f J. Then we have S = (H uf [0, ]) (T uf [0, ]) pr (H f J) (T f J) S, hence S pr S. Together with S pr S, LC does not hold either. We can consider similarly that in three urn example of Elsberg, it does not hold PB or LC. In the above example, which satisfies monotonicity, neither LC nor PB is satisfied. So, the question is: Are there examples of continuous preferences (so that solvability holds) that (a) LC holds but PB does not hold, and (b) PB holds but LC does not hold? The following examples give these two cases, which does not satisfy event non-satiation (see section 3.). Example 2.6. Let S = [0, ] [0, ], C = {x, y}, A = B [0, ], A 2 = [0, ] B, here B is the Borel algebra on [0, ], and A := A A 2 is a λ-system. Let f( ) and g( ) be some functions on [0, ] such that f(0) = g(0) and f() = g(), and let V ( x (A B) y ) { f(p (A)) if B = [0, ] = here P is the Lebesgue measure. Let g(p (B)) if A = [0, ], be represented by the above V. We consider the following f( ) and g( ) s. (a) Let f( ) and g( ) be as in Figure 4 and 5, respectively. That is, 7

18 f(x) = { 2x if 0 x 2 and g(x) = 2(x ) if x, 2 { 2x if x 4 2(x ) 3 if x. 4 f( ) g( ) A A 2 B B Figure 4. Figure 5. Let E = [0, 4 ], E 2 = ( 4, 2 ], A i = E i [0, ] A, B i = [0, ] E i A 2, i =, 2. Then for each i =, 2, A i and B i are minimal, A i ev B i, hence, A := A A 2 pr B B 2 =: B. Since V (x A y) > V (x B y), we have A ev B. Hence, PB does not hold. On the other hand, LC holds. (b) Let { f( ) and g( ) be functions on [0, ] of Figure 6 and 7, respectively. That is, 2x if 0 x 3 f(x) = 4 and g(x) = x. 2(x ) + if 3 x, 4 f( ) g( ) 0 A A Figure B B 2 2 Figure 7. Let E = [0, 4 ], E 2 = ( 4, 2 ], E 3 = ( 2, 3 4 ], E 4 = ( 3 4, ], F = E E 2, F 2 = E 3 E 4, A i = E i [0, ], i =,..., 4, B j = [0, ] F j, j =, 2. Then A i, B i are minimal, A i ev B i, i =, 2, hence, S A := A A 2 pr B B 2 = S, and A ev S. 8

19 This implies S pr S. Since S pr S, LC does not hold. On the other hand, PB holds. In the above example (a), if the events whose probabilities are less that 4, since f( ) and g( ) coincide on these probalities, there does not exist two different measurements, and Likelyhood Consistency holds. But if probabilities are greater than and not equal to, then f( ) and g( ) are different on these probalities, so that, A 4 and B have partitions such that they are piecewise equally evaluated does not mean A and B are equally evaluated. In the above example (b), probabilities of events are less than 3, then f( ) is two times of g( ), so that events A and B have partitions 4 such that they are piecewise equally evaluated means that 2P (A) = P (B), and Likelyhood Consistency does not hold. But f( ) and g( ) coincides on the probabilities of A and S, so that PB holds. The following theorem characterize pre-probabilistically sophistication. Theorem 2.7. Let A be a finite λ-system on S, and the preference relation on the set of acts over A is a weak order, nondegeneracy holds, and there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events for each event. Then Axioms A, S, LC and PB hold iff is pre-probabilistically sophisticated. Here its probability measure P is solvable and represents pr, and it is either atomless or purely and uniformly atomic. Remark 2.8. In the Only if part of the above Theorem, assuming A is a σ- algebra, replacing Axiom S (Solvability) by P4 and Axiom C (Continuity) (so that Axiom S holds), pre-probabilistic sophistication is replaced by pre-probabilistic sophistication with the probability measure which is stomless, solvable, and countably additive (see Villegas (964)) What Condition Extends Pre-probabilistic Sophistication to Probabilistic Sophistication? As the example of bounded rational agent in the introduction shows, an agent who is pre-probabilistically sophisticated needs not be probabilistically sophisticated. Then, what condition ensures pre-probabilistically sophisticated agent to be probabilistically sophisticated? Similar question was considered by Sarin Wakker (2000), 9

20 where they showed that cumulative dominance is what extends qualitative probability to probabilistically sophistication assuming monotonicity. In this subsection, we show that PB (Probabilistically Sophisticated Belief) is the condition that extends pre-probabilistic sophistication to probabilistically sophistication without assuming monotonicity. We assume that A is an algebra. Consider the exchangeable relation on disjoint events defined by Chew and Sagi (2006): Events A and ( B are exchageable, ) A B (A B) denoted by A B, if for all consequences c, c c and acts f, c c f ( ) A B (A B) c c. We extend exchangeable relation to general events by the following: [A B] if [A \B B \A]. Consider the following c f condition. Axiom PB (Probabilistically Sophisticated Belief ): For all pair of events A and B, A pr B implies A B. That is, if events are equally probable, then they are exchangeable. This is a notion weaker than P 4 (strong comparative probability) of Machina and Schmeidler (992). The following is our theorem. Theorem 2.9. Assume A is an algebra, is a weak order, nondegeneracy holds, there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events for each event, and assume that Axioms A, S and LC hold. Then the following two statements are equivalent. (a) Probabilistic sophistication holds. (b) PB holds. In particular, assuming pre-probabilistic sophistication, probabilistic sophistication holds iff PB holds. And in Theorem 2.7, assuming A is an algebra and replacing Axiom PB by PB, pre-probabilistic sophistication is replaced by probabilistic sophistication. 3. Likelihood Consistencies, Minimal Events, and Event Non-satiation In this section, we compare our notions of likelihood consistency, minimal events to event non-satiation by Chew and Sagi (2006) and ps-likelihood consistency by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005). 20

21 3.. Event Non-satiation First we consider event non-satiation (EN) introduced by Chew and Sagi (2006), which is a necessary assumption for their axiomatization of probabilistic sophistication. We assume that A is an algebra in this subsection. Chew and Sagi (2006) defined event non-satiation as follows: (EN) : If E E, then E A F for no Savage-nonnull event A with E A = and F E. We consider in a more general setting. Let l be a binary relation (likelihood relation) on events that is reflexive (A l A) and symmetric (A l B B l A), which is not necessarily an equivalent relation. Let l -null ( A) be a property of an event such that If A is l -null (A l -null), A B = and B l C, then A B l C. The following give examples of being l -null. Example 3.. (a) Let l be the exchangeability relation, l -null be Savagenull. (b) Define that A is l -null if A B = and B l C, then A B l C. (c) Let l be the equally evaluated relation ev, l -null be null as defined in this paper. Since ev is transitive, this is well defined by Lemma 4.7 (a) (b). Define l -event non-satiation as follows: ( l -EN) : If E l E, then E A l F for no l -nonnull event A with E A = and F E. -event non-satiation is the event non-satiation (EN) defined by Chew and Sagi (2006). Define A l B if there exists an subevent B of A with l -nonnull A \ B such that B l B, and A l B if A l B or A l B. Consider the following l -likelihood consistency: ( l -LC) : A l B and B l A for no events A and B. The following proposition shows that event non-satiation can be considered as a likelihood consistency. 2

22 Proposition 3.2. l -event non-satiation ( l -EN) is equivalent to l -likelihood consistency ( l -LC). Next we consider on minimal events. Define that event A is l -minimal if there exists no subevent A of A with l -nonnull A \A such that A l A. We have the following: Lemma 3.3. l -event non-satiation implies that all events are l -minimal. In particular, -event non-satiation implies that all events are -minimal Ps-likelihood Consistency Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005) introduced likelihood method for various models. Especially, they defined ps-likelihood consistency, and assumed it in axiomatization of probabilistic sophistication. We consider a relation to our ps-likelihood consistency. They defined binary relations ps and ps on the set of events A as follow: A ps B (resp. A ps B) holds if: c A f c B g, d A f d B g (resp. d A f d B g), and c Af c Bg imply d Af d Bg (resp. d Af d Bg ), whenever d c, d c, f, g F((S, A); {c, d}), f, g F((S, A); {c, d }). Axiom LC AW (Ps-likelihood consistency by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005)): A ps B and A ps B for no events A, B. They assumed monotonicity, that is, f g whenever f(s) g(s) for all s. The following lemma shows that with some assumptions, ps-likelihood consistency by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005) implies our likelihood consistency. Lemma 3.4. (a) Assume monotonicity and solvability (Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005, Definition 5.2)). Then LC AW implies LC and P B. (b) In Example 2.6 (b), LC and P B hold, but LC AW does not hold. 4. Appendix 4.. Proofs Proof of Remark 2.9: (b) (i) Suppose c c. (Only if): Let A be such that c A c c. Then by P3, c c A c c. (If): c S c = c c. 22

23 (ii): We may assume that there exist c c. Suppose A is not minimal, and let A ( A be such that ) ( A \A is nonnull )(so that Savage-nonnull) and A ev A. Then A \A A A c A \A A c c c A c c c c, which contradicts P3. (iii): We may assume that there exist c c. Let {E, A, E, G} be a partition of S, ( A is Savage-nonnull, ) E E and E A F E. Denote (c c 2 c 3 c 4 c 5 ) by E A F E \F G. Then c c 2 c 3 c 4 c 5 which contradicts P3. (cc c c c ) (c c ccc ) (by E E ) (c c cc c ) (by P 3) (ccc c c ) (by E A F ), (c) Let S = [0, ], A = B [0,], C = {c, c }, P the Lebesgue measure. is represented by: V (c A c ) = { sin π if P (A) > 0 2 P (A) 0 if P (A) = 0. Let A A be such that P (A) > 0. Then for any n N, any events A n A such that P (A n ) =, we have A 4n+ n ev A. Therefore, each nonnull event is not P (A) minimal in this example. We exclude the case in our main theorem. To prove Proposition 2.0, we give a lemma. Lemma 4.. Let be pre-probabilistically sophisticated with its probability measure P. (a) For each event A, P (A) = 0 iff A is null. (b) Let A, B A be such that P A = P B. Then A is minimal iff B is minimal. (c) Let A, B be minimal events. Then P (A) = P (B) iff A ev B. Proof. (a) If P (A) = 0, then for each A A, P (A ) = 0 = P ( ) implying A ev. Hence, A is null. (b) Suppose A is minimal and B is not minimal. Then there exists B B with nonnull C := B \ B such that B ev B. By the solvability of P, there exist disjoint events A, C A such that P (A ) = P (B ) and P (C ) = P (C). Then 23

24 A ev B. Hence, A ev B ev B ev A. Since C is nonnull by the above (a), this contradicts the assumption that A is minimal. (c) (If): Suppose A ev B and P (A) > P (B). By the solvability of P, there exists B A such that P (B ) = P (B). Then B ev B ev A. Since P (A \B ) > 0, A \B is nonnull. This contradicts the assumption that A is minimal. Proof of Proposition 2.0: Suppose P A P B. We show A pr B. By the solvability of P, there exists B A such that P (B) = P (B ). Let {B i } n i= be a partition of B by minimal events. By the solvability of P, there exists a partition {B i} n i= of B by minimal events such that P (B i ) = P (B i) for all i. Then B i ev B i for all i. By Lemma 4. (b) each B i is minimal. Hence, B pr B, which implies A pr B. Next, suppose A pr B. We show P A P B. Then there exists B A such that B pr B. Let {B i } n i=, {B i} n i= be partitions by minimal events of B and B, respectively, such that B i ev B i for all i. By Lemma 4. (c), P (B i ) = P (B i) for all i. Hence, P (B) = P (B ), which implies P (A) P (B). Proof of Lemma 2.2: (Only if): Let A, B be events, and let {A i } m i=, {B i } n i= be partitions by strongly minimal events of A and B, respectively. By Axiom S, (a) there exists A A such that B ev A, or (b) there exists B B such that A ev B. Thus we have partitions (a) {A \ A, A 2,..., A m } and {B 2,..., B n } of A \ A and B \ B, respectively, or (b) {A 2,..., A m } and {B \ B, B 2,..., B n } of A \ A and B \ B, respectively. Continuing this procedure, we have partitions {A i} k i= and {B j} l i= of A and B, respectively, such that (i) k l and A i ev B i for i =,..., l, or (ii) k l and A i ev B i for i =,..., k. Then, we have A pr B in case (i) or B pr A in case (ii). Proof of Lemma 2.3: Let A, B be strongly minimal events. We suppose that Axiom C (a) holds. The case Axiom C (b) holds is similar. We define a decreasing sequence of events {A nk } k= such that A n k A and A nk c,c B, inductively by the following: Let A n := A and suppose A nk Define A nk := A nk ( m k is defined. Let n k n k and m k be such that A nk c,c A nk ( m k i= Sn k i ) c,c B. i= Sn k i ) = A ( m k i= Sn k i ). Let A := k= A n k. We prove A c,c B. By Axiom C (b), A c,c B. Suppose A c,c B. Then there exist n and 24

25 m such that Since A ( m i=s n i ) = A ( i=s n k i A c,c A ( m i=s n i ) c,c B. ) ( m i=si n ) = A ( i=s n k i ) = A, we have A c,c A, which is a contradiction. Thus we get A A such that A c,c B, which implies A ev B by P4. (If): Evident. Proof of Remark 2.4: Suppose PB holds but LC does not hold. Then there exist A, B such that A pr B and A pr B. Therefore there exists A A with nonnull A \A such that B pr A. By PB, A ev B ev A, which implies that A is not a minimal event. This is a contradiction. Proof of Example 2.6: (a) We prove LC. Note that A A (resp. B A 2 ) is minimal iff P (A) ( resp. P (B) ); and for minimal events A A 2 4 and B A 2, A ev B iff P (A) = P (B). Let A A and B A 2 be such that A pr B, and let {A i } n i=, {B i } n i= be partitions of A and B, respectively, such that A i ev B i for all i. Then P (A i ) = P (B i ) for all i, so that P (A) = P (B). This implies A pr B does not hold. Indeed, if there exists B A with non-null A \ B such that B pr B, then P (B) = P (B ) < P (A), a contradiction. Hence, LC holds. (b) We prove PB. Note that A A is minimal iff P (A) 3, and each B 4 A 2 is minimal. Let A A and B A 2 be such that A pr B, and let {A i } n i=, {B i } n i= be partitions of A and B, respectively, such that A i ev B i for all i. Then 2P (A i ) = P (B i ) for all i, so that 2P (A) = P (B), implying P (A) 2. Thus A ev B holds. Proof of Proposition 3.2: ( l -EN) ( l -LC): Suppose A l B and B l A. By A l B, there exists B A such that A \ B is l -nonnull and B l B. By B l A, we consider the following two cases: (i) Case : If A l B, then we have B l B and B (A \ B ) = A l B, which contradicts l -EN. (ii) Case 2: If B l A, then A B with l -nonnull B \ A such that A l A. Then B l B and B (A \B ) = A l A B, which contradicts l -EN. ( l -EN) ( l -LC): Suppose E l E and E A l F E with E A = and 25

26 l -nonnull A. We consider the following two cases: (i) Case : If E \F is l -null, then E A l F E \ F = E implying E l E A. Since A is l -nonnull and E l E we have E A l E, which contradicts l -LC. (i) Case 2: If E \ F is l -nonnull, then E l E A. Since E A l E we have E A l E, which contradicts l -LC. Proof of Lemma 3.3: Suppose A is not l -minimal. Then there exists A A with l -nonnull A \ A such that A l A. Since A (A \ A ) = A l A, this contradicts EN. Proof of Lemma 3.4: (a) Suppose LC AW holds. Define A b B (resp. A b B) if there exists c c such that c A c c B c (resp. c A c c B c ). Note that by LC AW, A b B (resp. A b B) iff A ps B (resp. A ps B). First we show (4.3) A ev B iff A b B. (Only if) is obvious. (If): Suppose A ev B. We may assume that there exist c, c such that c A c c B c. Case. c c ; By monotonicity, we have c c, a contradiction. Case 2. c c ; We have A b B implying A ps B. By LC AW, we have A b B. Case 3. c c; We have A c b B c. Suppose A b B. Then by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005, Lemma D2), S = A A c b B B c = S, implying d d for some d, a contradiction. Hence, (4.3) holds. Next we show Axiom PB holds. Suppose A pr B. Let {A i } n i= and {B i } n i= be finite partitions by minimal events of A and B, respectively, such that A i ev B i for all i. Then A i b B i for all i, and by Abdellaoui and Wakker (2005, Lemma D2), we have A b B. We have A ev B by (4.3), so that PB holds. Next we show Axiom LC holds. Suppose A pr B and A pr B. Let B A be such that A\B is nonnull and B pr B. Then by the above result we have A ev B. Therefore, for all outomes c, c, c A c c B c, which implies that (4.4) C := A \B ps. ( ) D C \D C Since C is nonnull, there exist D C and c c c such that c c c c. This implies that D ps. Hence, D b. By Abdellaoui and Wakker 26

27 (2005, Lemma D2), C = D (C\D) b C\D. Since C\D b by monotonicity, we have C b. This implies C ps by LC AW. This contradicts (4.4) by LC AW. Thus LC holds. (b) Suppose LC AW holds. Let x = (4, 0), y = (0, 3), x = (, 0), y = (0, 0), and A, B be events such that P (A) = 3, P (B) =. Then x y, x 5 5 Ay x B y, and x y, x Ay x By. Therefore, A b B and A b B, which implies A ps B and A ps B by LC AW. This contradicts LC AW Lemmas for Proof of the Main Theorems Throughout this subsection, we assume that there exists a finite partition by strongly minimal events for each event. So that Axiom S implies that pr is complete by Lemma 2.2. Lemma 4.2. Let A B = C D =. (a) (i) A pr C and B pr D implies A B pr C D. (ii) A pr C and B pr D (resp. B pr D) implies A B pr C D (resp. A B pr C D). (b) Under Axioms S and LC; (i) A B pr C D and A pr C implies B pr D. (ii) A pr B iff A c pr B c. Proof. (a) These assertions hold by Definition 2.8 directly. (b) (i) Suppose B pr D. By completeness of pr, we may assume that B pr D. Then there exists D B with nonnull B \ D such that D pr D. By (a) A D pr C D. Since A B \ (A D ) is nonnull, this implies A B pr C D, which contradicts LC. (ii) Suppose A pr B and A c pr B c. By completenss of pr, we may assume that A c pr B c. Then by (a), S = A A c pr B B c = S, which contradicts LC. Lemma 4.3. Under Axioms S and LC; let A pr B and {C, D} be a partition of B. Then there exists a partition {C, D } of A such that C pr C and D pr D. 27

September 2007, France

September 2007, France LIKELIHOOD CONSISTENCY M h dabd ll i (& P t P W kk ) Mohammed Abdellaoui (& Peter P. Wakker) September 2007, France A new method is presented for measuring beliefs/likelihoods under uncertainty. It will

More information

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009

Measurable Ambiguity. with Wolfgang Pesendorfer. August 2009 Measurable Ambiguity with Wolfgang Pesendorfer August 2009 A Few Definitions A Lottery is a (cumulative) probability distribution over monetary prizes. It is a probabilistic description of the DMs uncertain

More information

Small Worlds: Modeling Attitudes towards Sources of Uncertainty. October Abstract

Small Worlds: Modeling Attitudes towards Sources of Uncertainty. October Abstract Small Worlds: Modeling Attitudes towards Sources of Uncertainty Chew Soo Hong and Jacob S. Sagi October 2003 Abstract In the literature on decision making under uncertainty, Ramsey and de Finetti originated

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and

Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and Uniform Sources of Uncertainty for Subjective Probabilities and Ambiguity Mohammed Abdellaoui (joint with Aurélien Baillon and Peter Wakker) 1 Informal Central in this work will be the recent finding of

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

Rationality and Uncertainty

Rationality and Uncertainty Rationality and Uncertainty Based on papers by Itzhak Gilboa, Massimo Marinacci, Andy Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler Warwick Aug 23, 2013 Risk and Uncertainty Dual use of probability: empirical frequencies

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities

Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective. Probabilities Decision Making under Uncertainty and Subjective Probabilities Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University September 7, 2005 Abstract This paper presents two axiomatic models of decision making under uncertainty

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

An additively separable representation in the Savage framework

An additively separable representation in the Savage framework An additively separable representation in the Savage framework Brian Hill HEC Paris October 29, 2007 Abstract This paper elicits an additively separable representation of preferences in the Savage framework

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITIES ON SMALL DOMAINS

SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITIES ON SMALL DOMAINS SUBJECTIVE PROBABILITIES ON SMALL DOMAINS Igor Kopylov Institute for Mathematical Behavioral Sciences, and Department of Economics, University of California, Irvine, CA 92697 Abstract The choice-theoretic

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

EVENT EXCHANGEABILITY: PROBABILISTIC SOPHISTICATION WITHOUT CONTINUITY OR MONOTONICITY

EVENT EXCHANGEABILITY: PROBABILISTIC SOPHISTICATION WITHOUT CONTINUITY OR MONOTONICITY Econometrica,Vol.74,No.3(May,2006),771 786 EVENT EXCHANGEABILITY: PROBABILISTIC SOPHISTICATION WITHOUT CONTINUITY OR MONOTONICITY BY CHEW SOO HONG AND JACOB S. SAGI 1 Building on the Ramsey de Finetti

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Adam Dominiak 1 and Gerelt Tserenjigmid 2 1,2 Department of Economics, Virginia Tech September 10, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we study choice under growing awareness

More information

Subjective Expected Utility in Games

Subjective Expected Utility in Games Subective Expected Utility in Games Alfredo Di Tillio Department of Economics University of Pennsylvania 3718 Locust Walk Philadelphia, PA 19104 June 23, 2004 Abstract This paper extends the scope of Savage

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty*

On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* journal of economic theory 75, 194204 (1997) article no. ET962280 On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty* Elchanan Ben-Porath Tel-Aviv University, Ramit-Aviv, 69 978 Tel-Aviv, Israel; and Northwestern

More information

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS CHAPTER 1: MEASURE THEORY In this chapter we define the notion of measure µ on a space, construct integrals on this space, and establish their basic properties under limits. The measure µ(e) will be defined

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi yzx August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form

More information

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 56, No., February 05 RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES BY DAVID DILLENBERGER AND UZI SEGAL University of Pennsylvania, U.S.A.; Boston College, U.S.A., and Warwick

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 2 44706 (1394-95 2 nd term) Group 2 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 6: Choice under Uncertainty

More information

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn

Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Econ Theory (2011) 48:425 436 DOI 10.1007/s00199-011-0652-4 SYMPOSIUM Event-Separability in the Ellsberg urn Mark J. Machina Received: 5 April 2011 / Accepted: 9 June 2011 / Published online: 16 July 2011

More information

Module 1. Probability

Module 1. Probability Module 1 Probability 1. Introduction In our daily life we come across many processes whose nature cannot be predicted in advance. Such processes are referred to as random processes. The only way to derive

More information

A Note On Comparative Probability

A Note On Comparative Probability A Note On Comparative Probability Nick Haverkamp and Moritz Schulz Penultimate draft. Please quote from the published version (Erkenntnis 2012). Abstract A possible event always seems to be more probable

More information

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9 MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES PROFESSOR: JOHN QUIGG SEMESTER: FALL 204 Contents. Sets 2 2. Functions 5 3. Countability 7 4. Axiom of choice 8 5. Equivalence relations 9 6. Real numbers 9 7. Extended

More information

WORKING PAPER SERIES

WORKING PAPER SERIES INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR ECONOMIC RESEARCH WORKING PAPER SERIES Paolo Ghirardato and Massimo Marinacci RISK, AMBIGUITY, AND THE SEPARATION OF UTILITY AND BELIEFS Working Paper no. 21/2001 September 2001

More information

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance

Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Anscombe & Aumann Expected Utility Betting and Insurance Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 11, October 3 Outline 1 Subjective Expected Utility 2 Qualitative Probabilities 3 Allais and Ellsebrg Paradoxes 4 Utility

More information

Choice under uncertainty

Choice under uncertainty Choice under uncertainty Expected utility theory The agent chooses among a set of risky alternatives (lotteries) Description of risky alternatives (lotteries) a lottery L = a random variable on a set of

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Alternative Characterizations of Boston Mechanism

Alternative Characterizations of Boston Mechanism Alternative Characterizations of Boston Mechanism Mustafa Oǧuz Afacan April 15, 2013 Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences, Sabancı University, 34956, İstanbul, Turkey. Abstract Kojima and Ünver (2011) are

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories

Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories Chapter 2 Classical Probability Theories In principle, those who are not interested in mathematical foundations of probability theory might jump directly to Part II. One should just know that, besides

More information

A PECULIAR COIN-TOSSING MODEL

A PECULIAR COIN-TOSSING MODEL A PECULIAR COIN-TOSSING MODEL EDWARD J. GREEN 1. Coin tossing according to de Finetti A coin is drawn at random from a finite set of coins. Each coin generates an i.i.d. sequence of outcomes (heads or

More information

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory

Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory Review of Economic Analysis 4 (01) 67-75 1973-3909/01067 Weak* Axiom of Independence and the Non-Expected Utility Theory TAPAN BISWAS University of Hull 1 Introduction The axiomatic foundation of the expected

More information

Three contrasts between two senses of coherence

Three contrasts between two senses of coherence Three contrasts between two senses of coherence Teddy Seidenfeld Joint work with M.J.Schervish and J.B.Kadane Statistics, CMU Call an agent s choices coherent when they respect simple dominance relative

More information

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging

Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Allais, Ellsberg, and Preferences for Hedging Mark Dean and Pietro Ortoleva Abstract Two of the most well-known regularities observed in preferences under risk and uncertainty are ambiguity aversion and

More information

Measurable functions are approximately nice, even if look terrible.

Measurable functions are approximately nice, even if look terrible. Tel Aviv University, 2015 Functions of real variables 74 7 Approximation 7a A terrible integrable function........... 74 7b Approximation of sets................ 76 7c Approximation of functions............

More information

About partial probabilistic information

About partial probabilistic information About partial probabilistic information Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura To cite this version: Alain Chateauneuf, Caroline Ventura. About partial probabilistic information. Documents de travail du Centre

More information

A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries

A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries A Theory of Subjective Compound Lotteries Haluk Ergin Washington University in St Louis and Faruk Gul Princeton University September 2008 Abstract We develop a Savage-type model of choice under uncertainty

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

A theory of robust experiments for choice under uncertainty

A theory of robust experiments for choice under uncertainty A theory of robust experiments for choice under uncertainty S. Grant a,, J. Kline b, I. Meneghel a, J. Quiggin b, R. Tourky a a Australian National University b The University of Queensland Abstract Thought

More information

CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY DIVISION OF THE HUMANITIES AND SOCIAL SCIENCES CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY PASADENA, CALIFORNIA 91125 RANGE CONVEXITY AND AMBIGUITY AVERSE PREFERENCES. Paolo Ghirardato California Institute of Technology

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Introduction to Information Entropy Adapted from Papoulis (1991)

Introduction to Information Entropy Adapted from Papoulis (1991) Introduction to Information Entropy Adapted from Papoulis (1991) Federico Lombardo Papoulis, A., Probability, Random Variables and Stochastic Processes, 3rd edition, McGraw ill, 1991. 1 1. INTRODUCTION

More information

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences

Conditional and Dynamic Preferences Conditional and Dynamic Preferences How can we Understand Risk in a Dynamic Setting? Samuel Drapeau Joint work with Hans Föllmer Humboldt University Berlin Jena - March 17th 2009 Samuel Drapeau Joint work

More information

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001)

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001) Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001) Klaus Nehring University of California, Davis April 2006 Abstract It is shown that well-behaved

More information

Origins of Probability Theory

Origins of Probability Theory 1 16.584: INTRODUCTION Theory and Tools of Probability required to analyze and design systems subject to uncertain outcomes/unpredictability/randomness. Such systems more generally referred to as Experiments.

More information

Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component

Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component Two Factor Additive Conjoint Measurement With One Solvable Component Christophe Gonzales LIP6 Université Paris 6 tour 46-0, ème étage 4, place Jussieu 755 Paris Cedex 05, France e-mail: ChristopheGonzales@lip6fr

More information

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Fundamenta Informaticae 69 (2006) 1 20 1 IOS Press On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Lirong Xia State Key Laboratory of Intelligent Technology and Systems Department of Computer Science

More information

Subjective expected utility in games

Subjective expected utility in games Theoretical Economics 3 (2008), 287 323 1555-7561/20080287 Subjective expected utility in games ALFREDO DI TILLIO Department of Economics and IGIER, Università Bocconi This paper extends Savage s subjective

More information

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities

Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities Ambiguity Aversion: An Axiomatic Approach Using Second Order Probabilities William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu April 1993 Abstract

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

Extrapolated Social Preferences

Extrapolated Social Preferences Extrapolated Social Preferences Maya Eden World Bank July 17, 2017 Abstract This paper proposes a simpler interpretation of Harsanyi s impartial observer idea. It postulates an impartiality axiom with

More information

Fundamentals of Probability CE 311S

Fundamentals of Probability CE 311S Fundamentals of Probability CE 311S OUTLINE Review Elementary set theory Probability fundamentals: outcomes, sample spaces, events Outline ELEMENTARY SET THEORY Basic probability concepts can be cast in

More information

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice http://selod.ensae.net/m1 Paris School of Economics (selod@ens.fr) September 27, 2007 Notations Consider an individual (agent) facing a choice set X. Definition (Choice set, "Consumption set") X is a set

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

I. ANALYSIS; PROBABILITY

I. ANALYSIS; PROBABILITY ma414l1.tex Lecture 1. 12.1.2012 I. NLYSIS; PROBBILITY 1. Lebesgue Measure and Integral We recall Lebesgue measure (M411 Probability and Measure) λ: defined on intervals (a, b] by λ((a, b]) := b a (so

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 1 Number Systems and Matrix Algebra Integers The whole numbers 0, ±1, ±2, ±3, ±4,...

More information

STAT 7032 Probability Spring Wlodek Bryc

STAT 7032 Probability Spring Wlodek Bryc STAT 7032 Probability Spring 2018 Wlodek Bryc Created: Friday, Jan 2, 2014 Revised for Spring 2018 Printed: January 9, 2018 File: Grad-Prob-2018.TEX Department of Mathematical Sciences, University of Cincinnati,

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

Quantum Decision Theory

Quantum Decision Theory Quantum Decision Theory V.I. Yukalov and D. Sornette Department of Management, Technology and Economics\ ETH Zürich Plan 1. Classical Decision Theory 1.1. Notations and definitions 1.2. Typical paradoxes

More information

Mean-Variance Utility

Mean-Variance Utility Mean-Variance Utility Yutaka Nakamura University of Tsukuba Graduate School of Systems and Information Engineering Division of Social Systems and Management -- Tennnoudai, Tsukuba, Ibaraki 305-8573, Japan

More information

Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial l

Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial l Subjective multi-prior probability: a representation of a partial likelihood relation TAU, 22-11-2011 Outline of the talk: Motivation Background Examples Axioms Result Related literature Outline of the

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. MA651 Topology. Lecture 9. Compactness 2. This text is based on the following books: Topology by James Dugundgji Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology

More information

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization

Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Reverse Bayesianism: A Generalization Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University and Warwick Business School Quitzé Valenzuela-Stookey Northwestern University Marie-Louise Vierø Queen s University December 10,

More information

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts

Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure Parts Review of Economics & Finance Submitted on 28/Nov./2011 Article ID: 1923-7529-2012-02-65-11 Yutaka Matsushita Certainty Equivalent Representation of Binary Gambles That Are Decomposed into Risky and Sure

More information

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences Daniela Saban and Jay Sethuraman March 7, 2014 Abstract We consider the problem of allocating m objects to n agents. Each agent has unit demand,

More information

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS REAL AND COMPLE ANALYSIS Third Edition Walter Rudin Professor of Mathematics University of Wisconsin, Madison Version 1.1 No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any

More information

Axiomatic Foundations of Expected Utility. and Subjective Probability

Axiomatic Foundations of Expected Utility. and Subjective Probability Axiomatic Foundations of Expected Utility and Subjective Probability Edi Karni Johns Hopkins University April 29, 2013 This is a chapter commissioned for the Handbook of Risk and Uncertainty (Machina and

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity

Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity Efficient Allocations under Ambiguity Tomasz Strzalecki Harvard University Jan Werner University of Minnesota May 2010 Abstract An important implication of the expected utility model under risk aversion

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Expected Utility Framework

Expected Utility Framework Expected Utility Framework Preferences We want to examine the behavior of an individual, called a player, who must choose from among a set of outcomes. Let X be the (finite) set of outcomes with common

More information

Three grades of coherence for non-archimedean preferences

Three grades of coherence for non-archimedean preferences Teddy Seidenfeld (CMU) in collaboration with Mark Schervish (CMU) Jay Kadane (CMU) Rafael Stern (UFdSC) Robin Gong (Rutgers) 1 OUTLINE 1. We review de Finetti s theory of coherence for a (weakly-ordered)

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank

Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point. by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank Endogenizing Prospect Theory s Reference Point by Ulrich Schmidt and Horst Zank No. 1611 March 2010 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1611

More information

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define 1 Measures 1.1 Jordan content in R N II - REAL ANALYSIS Let I be an interval in R. Then its 1-content is defined as c 1 (I) := b a if I is bounded with endpoints a, b. If I is unbounded, we define c 1

More information

The Lebesgue Integral

The Lebesgue Integral The Lebesgue Integral Brent Nelson In these notes we give an introduction to the Lebesgue integral, assuming only a knowledge of metric spaces and the iemann integral. For more details see [1, Chapters

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs

Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Dynamic Consistency and Subjective Beliefs Spyros Galanis August 24, 2017 Abstract Ambiguity sensitive preferences must either fail Consequentialism or Dynamic Consistency (DC), two properties that are

More information

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich

CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich CER-ETH Center of Economic Research at ETH Zurich A Dual Approach to Ambiguity Aversion A. Bommier Working Paper 14/207 December 2014 Economics Working Paper Series A Dual Approach to Ambiguity Aversion

More information

Nash Equilibrium without. Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1. Kin Chung Lo. Department of Economics, University oftoronto, July, 1995.

Nash Equilibrium without. Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1. Kin Chung Lo. Department of Economics, University oftoronto, July, 1995. Nash Equilibrium without Mutual Knowledge of Rationality 1 Kin Chung Lo Department of Economics, University oftoronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 1A1 July, 1995 Abstract This paper denes an equilibrium

More information

The Banach-Tarski paradox

The Banach-Tarski paradox The Banach-Tarski paradox 1 Non-measurable sets In these notes I want to present a proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox, a consequence of the axiom of choice that shows us that a naive understanding of the

More information

Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions.

Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions. Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions. Problem 1. Prove Proposition 0.2.2. A guide to this problem: start with the open set S = (a, b), for example. First assume that a >, and show that the number a has the properties

More information

Measures and Measure Spaces

Measures and Measure Spaces Chapter 2 Measures and Measure Spaces In summarizing the flaws of the Riemann integral we can focus on two main points: 1) Many nice functions are not Riemann integrable. 2) The Riemann integral does not

More information

Lecture 4: Probability and Discrete Random Variables

Lecture 4: Probability and Discrete Random Variables Error Correcting Codes: Combinatorics, Algorithms and Applications (Fall 2007) Lecture 4: Probability and Discrete Random Variables Wednesday, January 21, 2009 Lecturer: Atri Rudra Scribe: Anonymous 1

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

RS Chapter 1 Random Variables 6/5/2017. Chapter 1. Probability Theory: Introduction

RS Chapter 1 Random Variables 6/5/2017. Chapter 1. Probability Theory: Introduction Chapter 1 Probability Theory: Introduction Basic Probability General In a probability space (Ω, Σ, P), the set Ω is the set of all possible outcomes of a probability experiment. Mathematically, Ω is just

More information

212a1214Daniell s integration theory.

212a1214Daniell s integration theory. 212a1214 Daniell s integration theory. October 30, 2014 Daniell s idea was to take the axiomatic properties of the integral as the starting point and develop integration for broader and broader classes

More information

Bernoulli Without Bayes: A Theory of Utility-Sophisticated Preferences under Ambiguity

Bernoulli Without Bayes: A Theory of Utility-Sophisticated Preferences under Ambiguity Bernoulli Without Bayes: A Theory of Utility-Sophisticated Preferences under Ambiguity Klaus Nehring 1 University of California, Davis May 30, 2006 2 1 e-mail: kdnehring@ucdavis.edu 2 Some of the material

More information

A Subjective Foundation of Objective Probability

A Subjective Foundation of Objective Probability A Subjective Foundation of Objective Probability Luciano De Castro and Nabil I. Al-Najjar First draft: December 2008; This version: July 2009 Abstract De Finetti s concept of exchangeability provides a

More information

n [ F (b j ) F (a j ) ], n j=1(a j, b j ] E (4.1)

n [ F (b j ) F (a j ) ], n j=1(a j, b j ] E (4.1) 1.4. CONSTRUCTION OF LEBESGUE-STIELTJES MEASURES In this section we shall put to use the Carathéodory-Hahn theory, in order to construct measures with certain desirable properties first on the real line

More information

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber

Analysis I. Classroom Notes. H.-D. Alber Analysis I Classroom Notes H-D Alber Contents 1 Fundamental notions 1 11 Sets 1 12 Product sets, relations 5 13 Composition of statements 7 14 Quantifiers, negation of statements 9 2 Real numbers 11 21

More information

Evaluating Ambiguous Random Variables and Updating by Proxy

Evaluating Ambiguous Random Variables and Updating by Proxy Evaluating Ambiguous Random Variables and Updating by Proxy Faruk Gul and Wolfgang Pesendorfer Princeton University June 2018 Abstract We introduce a new theory of belief revision under ambiguity. It is

More information

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers

Logical Connectives and Quantifiers Chapter 1 Logical Connectives and Quantifiers 1.1 Logical Connectives 1.2 Quantifiers 1.3 Techniques of Proof: I 1.4 Techniques of Proof: II Theorem 1. Let f be a continuous function. If 1 f(x)dx 0, then

More information