On the Law of Importation. in Fuzzy Logic. J.Balasubramaniam, Member IEEE. Abstract

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "On the Law of Importation. in Fuzzy Logic. J.Balasubramaniam, Member IEEE. Abstract"

Transcription

1 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 1 On the Law of Importation (x y) z (x (y z)) in Fuzzy Logic J.Balasubramaniam, Member IEEE Abstract The law of importation, given by the equivalence (x y) z (x (y z)), is a tautology in classical logic. In A-implications defined by Turksen et al., the above equivalence is taken as an axiom. In this work we investigate the general form of the law of importation J(T (x, y), z) J(x, J(y, z)), where T is a t-norm and J is a fuzzy implication, for the three main classes of fuzzy implications, viz., R-, S- and QL-implications and also for the recently proposed Yager s classes of fuzzy implications, viz., f- and g-implications. We give necessary and sufficient conditions under which the law of importation holds for R-, S-, f- and g-implications. We also give necessary conditions under which QL-implications have the law of importation and investigate some specific families of QL-implications. Also we have investigated the general form of the law of importation in the more general setting of uninorms and t-operators for the above classes of fuzzy implications. Following this, we propose a novel modified scheme of CRI inferencing called the Hierarchical CRI that alleviates some of the drawbacks of Zadeh s CRI. We give sufficient conditions on the operators employed under which the inference obtained from the Zadeh s CRI and the Hierarchical CRI become identical, highlighting the significant role played by the law of importation. Index Terms Law of Importation, Fuzzy Implications, Compositional Rule of Inference, Fuzzy Inference, Approximate Reasoning, Rule Reduction. The author is with the Department of Mathematics and Computer Sciences, Sri Sathya Sai Institute of Higher Learning, Prasanthi Nilayam, A.P , India. jbala@ieee.org.

2 2 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic I. INTRODUCTION The equation (x y) z (x (y z)), known as the law of importation, is a tautology in classical logic. The general form of the above equivalence is given by J(T (x, y), z) J(x, J(y, z)), (LI) where T is a t-norm and J a fuzzy implication. In the framework of fuzzy logic, the law of importation has not been studied so far in isolation. In A-implications defined by Turksen et al. [46], (LI) with T as the product t-norm T P (x, y) = x y, was taken as one of the axioms. Baczyński [1] has studied the law of importation in conjunction with the general form of the following distributive property of fuzzy implications [x (y z)] [(x y) (x z)] (1) and has given a characterisation. Bouchon-Meunier and Kreinovich [10] have characterised fuzzy implications that have the law of importation as one of the axioms along with (1). They have considered T M (x, y) = min(x, y) for the t-norm T and claim that Mamdani s choice of implication min is not so strange after all. A. Motivation for this work Recently, there have been many attempts to examine classical logic tautologies involving fuzzy implication operators, both from a theoretical perspective and also from possible applicational value. There were a number of correspondences [9], [12], [13], [14], [16], [31], [44] on the equivalence (x y) z (x z) (y z), (1) and related distributive properties in fuzzy logic, in the context of Inference Invariant Complexity Reduction in Fuzzy Rule Based Systems (see [7], [8], [41], [48]). Daniel-Ruiz and Torrens have investigated the distributivity of fuzzy implications over uninorms in [39]. Fodor [18] has investigated the contrapositive symmetry of the three classes of fuzzy implications, viz., R-, S- and QL-implications with respect to a strong negation. Igel and Tamme [26] have dealt with chaining of implication operators in a syllogistic fashion. Thus the investigation of these properties of fuzzy implications has interesting applications in Approximate Reasoning. In this work we consider the general form of the law of importation in the setting of fuzzy logic and explore its potential applications in the field of approximate reasoning. Hence the present work should be seen in this context.

3 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 3 B. Main contents of the paper The three established and well-studied classes of fuzzy implications in the literature are the R-, S- and QL-implications. Recently, Yager [49] has proposed two new classes of fuzzy implications, viz., f- and g-implications, that can be seen to be obtained from the additive generators of continuous Archimedean t-norms and t-conorms, respectively. In this work, we consider the above law of importation for these classes of fuzzy implications, viz., R-, S-, QL-, f- and g-implications. We give necessary and sufficient conditions under which the above equivalence can be established for R-, S-, f- and g-implications. We also give necessary conditions underwhich QL-implications have the law of importation and investigate some specific families of QL-implications. Also we have investigated the general form of law of importation in the more general setting of uninorms and t-operators and show that they get reduced to t-norms. The Compositional Rule of Inference (CRI) proposed by Zadeh [52] is one of the earliest and most important inference schemes in approximate reasoning involving fuzzy propositions. Inferencing in CRI involves fuzzy relations that are multi-dimensional and hence is resource consuming - both memory and time. We propose a novel modified scheme of CRI inferencing called the Hierarchical CRI that alleviates the above drawback and also has many advantages. Subsequently, we give sufficient conditions on the operators employed in the Hierarchical CRI under which the inference obtained from Zadeh s CRI and the Hierarchical CRI become identical. The law of importation plays a significant role in the above equivalence. We illustrate the above concepts through some numerical examples. It is not uncommon to use a t-norm for relating antecedents to consequents in CRI, in which case we have shown that under even less restrictive conditions the equivalence between the inferences in Zadeh s CRI and Hierarchical CRI can be obtained. C. Outline of the paper In section II we review the basic fuzzy logic operators and their different properties. The main theoretical results of this work are contained in Section III - wherein we investigate the general form of law of importation for some well-known classes of fuzzy implications, and in Section IV - where we investigate the general form of law of importation in the more general setting of uninorms and t-operators. In Section V we propose a novel scheme of inferencing called the Hierarchical CRI and highlight its advantages. In Section VI we illustrate the applicational values of the theoretical results in Sections III and IV, by demonstrating the

4 4 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic significant role the law of importation plays in the equivalence of the outputs obtained from Zadeh s CRI and the Hierarchical CRI. Section VII gives a few concluding remarks. II. PRELIMINARIES To make this work self-contained, we briefly mention some of the concepts and results employed in the rest of the work. Definition 1: Let ϕ : [0, 1] [0, 1] be an increasing bijection. If f : [0, 1] [0, 1] is any function, then the ϕ-conjugate of f is given by f ϕ (x) = ϕ 1 (f(ϕ(x))), x [0, 1]. (2) If F : [0, 1] [0, 1] [0, 1] is any binary function, then the ϕ-conjugate of F is F ϕ (x, y) = ϕ 1 (F (ϕ(x), ϕ(y))), x, y [0, 1]. (3) A. Negations Definition 2 ( Fodor & Roubens [19], Definitions ): (i) A function N : [0, 1] [0, 1] is called a fuzzy negation if N(0) = 1, N(1) = 0 and N is non-increasing. (ii) A fuzzy negation N is called strict if, in addition, N is strictly decreasing and N is continuous. (iii) A fuzzy negation N is called strong if it is an involution, i.e., N(N(x)) = x for all x [0, 1]. Theorem 1 (cf. Trillas [43], Fodor & Roubens [19] Theorem 1.1, Pg 4): A function N : [0, 1] [0, 1] is a strong negation if and only if there exists an increasing bijection ϕ : [0, 1] [0, 1], such that N(x) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)). B. T-norms and T-conorms Definition 3 ( Cf. Schweizer & Sklar [40]; Klement et al., [27] Definition 1.1 Pg 4): A function T from [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] is called a triangular norm (shortly t-norm) if, for all x, y, z [0, 1], T (x, y) = T (y, x), T (x, T (y, z)) = T (T (x, y), z), (T1) (T2) T (x, y) T (x, z) whenever y z, (T3) T (x, 1) = x. (T4)

5 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 5 Definition 4 (Cf. Schweizer & Sklar [40]; Klement et al., [27] Definition 1.13 Pg 11): A function S : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] is called a triangular conorm (shortly t-conorm) if, for all x, y, z [0, 1], it satisfies S(x, y) = S(y, x), S(x, S(y, z)) = S(S(x, y), z), (S1) (S2) S(x, y) S(x, z) whenever y z, (S3) S(x, 0) = x. If F is an associative binary operation on a domain X then by the notation x (n) F F (x,, x) for an x X and n 2. Also x (1) }{{} F = x. n times (S4) we mean Definition 5 ( Klement et al., [27] Definitions 2.9 Pg 26 & 2.13 Pg 28): A t-norm T (tconorm S resp.) is said to be Continuous if it is continuous in both the arguments; Archimedean if T (S resp.) is such that for every x, y (0, 1] (x, y [0, 1) resp.) there is an n N with x (n) T < y ( x (n) S > y ) ; Strict if T (S resp.) is continuous and stricly monotone, i.e., T (x, y) < T (x, z) ( S(x, y) < S(x, z) ) whenever x > 0 (x < 1 resp.) and y < z; Nilpotent if T (S resp.) is continuous and if each x (0, 1) is such that x (n) T = 0 ( x (n) S = 1 ) for some n N. Theorem 2 ( Klement et al., [27] Theorem 5.1 Pg 122): For a function T : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] the following are equivalent: (i) T is a continuous Archimedean t-norm. (ii) T has a continuous additive generator, i.e., there exists a continuous, strictly decreasing function f : [0, 1] [0, ] with f(1) = 0, which is uniquely determined up to a positive multiplicative constant, such that for all x, y [0, 1] T (x, y) = f ( 1) (f(x) + f(y)), (4) where f ( 1) is the pseudo-inverse of f and is defined as: f 1 (x), if x [0, f(0)] f ( 1) (x) =. (5) 0, if x [f(0), ] If f(0) = then T is strict and if f(0) < then T is nilpotent. Proposition 1 (Klement et al.,[27], Propositions 5.9 & 5.10 pp ): Let T be a continuous t-norm.

6 6 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic (i) T is strict if and only if it is a conjugate of the product t-norm T P (x, y) = x y, i.e., there exists a strictly increasing bijection ϕ on [0, 1] such that T (x, y) = ϕ 1 (ϕ(x) ϕ(y)), x, y [0, 1]. (6) (ii) T is nilpotent if and only if it is a conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-norm T L (x, y) = max(x + y 1, 0), i.e., there exists a strictly increasing bijection ϕ on [0, 1] such that T (x, y) = ϕ 1 (max{ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) 1, 0}), x, y [0, 1]. (7) Theorem 3 (Klement et al., [27] Corollary 5.5 Pg 125): For a function S : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] the following are equivalent: (i) S is a continuous Archimedean t-conorm. (ii) S has a continuous additive generator, i.e., there exists a continuous, strictly increasing function g : [0, 1] [0, ] with g(0) = 0, which is uniquely determined up to a positive multiplicative constant, such that for all x, y [0, 1] we have S(x, y) = g ( 1) (g(x) + g(y)) where g ( 1) is the pseudo-inverse of g and is given by g 1 (x), if x [0, g(1)] g ( 1) (x) =. (8) 1, if x [g(1), ] Theorem 4 ( Cf. Fodor & Roubens [19]; Klement et al [27]): Let S be a continuous t- conorm. (i) S is strict if and only if S is a conjugate of the algebraic sum t-conorm S P (x, y) = x + y x y, i.e., there exists an increasing bijection ϕ of the unit interval [0, 1] such that S(x, y) = ϕ 1 (ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) ϕ(x) ϕ(y)), x, y [0, 1]. (9) (ii) S is nilpotent if and only if S is a conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-conorm, S L (x, y) = min(x + y, 1), i.e., there exists an increasing bijection ϕ on [0, 1] such that S(x, y) = ϕ 1( min(ϕ(x) + ϕ(y), 1) ), x, y [0, 1]. (10) Theorem 5 (Fodor & Roubens [19] Theorem 1.8 Pg 14): A continuous t-conorm S satisfies S(N(x), x) = 1, for all x [0, 1] with a strict negation N if and only if there exists a strictly increasing bijection ϕ of the unit interval [0, 1] such that S has the representation in (10), and N has the following representation: N(x) ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)), x [0, 1]. (11)

7 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 7 C. Uninorms and t-operators Definition 6 ( Fodor et al., [20] Definition 1, Pg 411): A uninorm is a two-place function U : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] which is associative, commutative, non-decreasing in each place and such that there exists some element e [0, 1] called the neutral element such that U(e, x) = x, x [0, 1]. If e = 0 then U is a t-conorm and if e = 1 then U is a t-norm. For any uninorm U, U(1, 0) {0, 1} (see [20] Corollary 1). A uninorm U such that U(1, 0) = 0 is called a conjunctive uninorm and if U(1, 0) = 1 it is called a disjunctive uninorm. Note that it can be easily shown that a uninorm U that is continuous on the whole of [0, 1] 2 is either a t-norm or a t-conorm. There are three main classes of uninorms that have been well studied in the literature, viz., 1) Pseudo-continuous uninorms (see [30]), i.e., uninorms U that are continuous on [0, 1] 2 except on the segments (0, e), (1, e) and (e, 0), (e, 1). These are precisely the uninorms such that both functions U(x, 1) and U(x, 0) are continuous except at the point x = e. The class of conjunctive uninorms having this property are usually referred to as U Min and the disjunctive ones by U Max (see [20] ). 2) Idempotent uninorms, i.e., uninorms U such that U(x, x) = x for all x [0, 1] (see [50], [4], [28], [38] ). 3) Representable uninorms that have additive generators and are continuous everywhere on the [0, 1] 2 except at the points (0, 1), (1, 0) (see [20]). Definition 7 (Mas et al., [29] Definition 3.1): A t-operator is a two-place function F : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] which is associative, commutative, non-decreasing in each place and such that F (0, 0) = 0; F (1, 1) = 1. The sections F 0, F 1 : [0, 1] [0, 1] are continuous functions, where F 0 (x) = F (0, x) ; F 1 (x) = F (1, x), for all x [0, 1]. Theorem 6 ( Mas et al., [29] Theorem 3.2): Let F : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] be a t-operator with F (1, 0) = k [0, 1]. Then If k = 0, F is a t-norm. If k = 1, F is a t-conorm.

8 8 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic If k 0, 1, there exist a t-conorm S and a t-norm T such that ( x ks k, y ), if 0 x, y k k ( x k F (x, y) = k + (1 k)t 1 k, y k ), if k x, y 1 1 k k, if min(x, y) k max(x, y) (12) D. Fuzzy Implications Definition 8 ( Fodor & Roubens [19] Definition 1.15, Pg 22): A function J : [0, 1] 2 [0, 1] is called a fuzzy implication if for all x, y, z [0, 1], it satisfies J(x, z) J(y, z), if x y, (J1) J(x, y) J(x, z), if y z, (J2) J(0, y) = 1, J(x, 1) = 1, (J3) (J4) J(1, 0) = 0. (J5) A fuzzy implication J is said to be Neutral if J(1, y) = y for all y [0, 1]. The following are the two important classes of fuzzy implications well-established in the literature: Definition 9 (Fodor & Roubens [19] Definition 1.16, Pg 24): An S-implication J S,N is obtained from a t-conorm S and a strong negation N as follows: J S,N (x, y) = S(N(x), y), x, y [0, 1]. (13) Definition 10 (Fodor & Roubens [19] Definition 1.16, Pg 24): An R-implication J T is obtained from a t-norm T as its residuation as follows: J T (x, y) = Sup {t [0, 1] : T (x, t) y}, x, y [0, 1]. (14) A t-norm T and J T the R-implication obtained from T are said to have the residuation principle if they satisfy the following: T (x, y) z iff J T (x, z) y, x, y [0, 1]. (RP) Remark 1: It is important to note that (RP) is a characterising condition for a left-continuous t-norm T (see [19] Pg 25, [25] Proposition 5.4.2). In this work we only consider R- implications J T obtained from t-norms T such that the pair (J T, T ) satisfy the residuation principle (RP), or equivalently T is a left-continuous t-norm. Also if T is a left-continuous t-norm then sup in (14) reduces to max.

9 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 9 Any R-implication J T obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T has the following properties (see for example, Trillas and Valverde [45] ) for all x, y, z [0, 1]: J T (x, J T (y, z)) = J T (y, J T (x, z)), Exchange Principle (EP) x y J T (x, y) = 1, Ordering Property (OP) J T (1, y) = y, Neutrality Principle (NP) An R-implication J T also satisfies the following inequality (see Pedrycz [35], [36]): J T (x, T (x, y)) y, x, y [0, 1]. (15) Since an Archimedean t-norm T that is left-continous is also continuous, and viceversa, (see Klement et al., [27] Proposition 2.16 Pg 30), the R-implications J T considered in the sequel all have the properties (EP) - (NP) and (15). Proposition 2 (Baczyński [2] Propositions 12, Pg. 271 & 21, Pg 276 ): Let ϕ : [0, 1] [0, 1] be an increasing bijection. (i) If J S,N is an S-implication obtained from a t-conorm S and strong negation N, then its ϕ-conjugate (J S,N ) ϕ is also an S-implication obtained from the t-conorm S ϕ and the strong negation N ϕ. (ii) If J T is an R-implication obtained from a left continuous t-norm T, then its ϕ-conjugate (J T ) ϕ is also an R-implication obtained from the left continuous t-norm T ϕ. A third important class of fuzzy implications studied in the literature is the following: Definition 11 (Fodor & Roubens [19] Pg 24): A QL-implication is obtained from a t- conorm S, t-norm T and a strong negation N as follows: J QL (x, y) = S(N(x), T (x, y)), x, y [0, 1]. (16) Remark 2: Again an S-implication J S,N (Definition 9) or a QL-implication J QL can be considered for non-involutive negations also, but in this study we only consider the stronger definition as given in [19]. It should also be noted that not all QL-implications satisfy the condition (J1) of Definition 8. Further, a QL-implication satisfies (J4) only if the strong negation N and the t-conorm S in Definition 11 are such that S(x, N(x)) = 1 for all x [0, 1]. All the above three classes of R-, S- and QL-implications are neutral. Tables I, II and III list few of the well-known S-, R- and QL-implications, respectively.

10 10 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic Name S(x, y) J S,N (x, y)y T (x, y) : N-dual of S Kleene-Dienes S M : max(x, y) J KD(x, y) = max(1 x, y) T M : min(x, y) Reichenbach S P : x + y x y J R(x, y) = 1 x + x y T P : x y Łukasiewicz S L : min(1, x + y) J L(x, y) = min(1, 1 x + y) T L : max(0, x + y 1) TABLE I SOME OF THE WELL KNOWN S-IMPLICATIONS WITH THEIR CORRESPONDING t-conorms, WHERE N IS THE STANDARD NEGATION 1 x Name T (x, y) J T (x, y) 8 Godel T M : min(x, y) >< 1, if x y J GD(x, y) = >: y, otherwise Łukasiewicz T L : max(0, x + y 1) J L(x, y) = min(1, 1 x + y) n Goguen T P : x y J GG(x, y) = min 1, y o x TABLE II SOME OF THE WELL-KNOWN R-IMPLICATIONS AND THEIR CORRESPONDING t-norms E. Yager s Classes of Fuzzy Implication Recently Yager [49] has proposed two new classes of fuzzy implication operators, viz., f- and g-generated implications, that cannot be strictly categorised to fall in the above classes. The recent work [3] discusses the intersection of the above classes of fuzzy implications with the classes of R- and (S, N)-implications. They can be seen to be obtained from additive generators of t-norms and t-conorms, whose definitions we give below along with few of their properties. Definition 12 ( Yager [49] Pg 196): An f-generator is a function f : [0, 1] [0, ] that is a strictly decreasing and continuous function with f(1) = 0. Also we denote its pseudoinverse by f ( 1) given by (5). Definition 13 (Yager [49] Pg 197): A function from [0, 1] 2 to [0, 1] defined by an f-generator as J f (x, y) = f ( 1) (x f(y)), (17) with the understanding that 0 = 0, is called an f-generated implication. It can easily be shown that J f is a fuzzy implication (see [49], Pg 197).

11 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 11 Name S(x, y) T (x, y) J QL(x, y) Zadeh S M : max(x, y) T M : min(x, y) J Z(x, y) = max(1 x, min(x, y)) - S P : x + y x y T P : x y J(x, y) = 1 x + x 2 y Łukasiewicz S L : min(1, x + y) T M : min(x, y) J L(x, y) = min(1, 1 x + y) Kleene-Dienes S L : min(1, x + y) T L : max(0, x + y 1) J KD(x, y) = max(1 x, y) TABLE III EXAMPLES OF QL-IMPLICATIONS WITH THEIR CORRESPONDING t-conorms AND t-norms, WHERE N IS THE STANDARD NEGATION 1 x Name f(x) f(0) J f (x, y) - log x y x s x 1 Frank ln ; s > 0, s 1 log s 1 + (s 1) 1 x (s y 1) x s 1 Trigonometric cos π 2 x 1 cos 1 x cos π 2 y Yager s class (1 x) λ ; λ > x 1 λ (1 y) TABLE IV EXAMPLES OF SOME J f IMPLICATIONS WITH THEIR f -GENERATORS Definition 14 (Yager [49] Pg 201): A g-generator is a function g : [0, 1] [0, ] that is a strictly increasing and continuous function with g(0) = 0. Also we denote its pseudo-inverse by g ( 1) given by (8). as Definition 15 (Yager [49] Pg 201): A function from [0, 1] 2 to [0, 1] defined by a g-generator J g (x, y) = g ( 1) ( 1 x g(y) ), (18) with the understanding that 0 =, is a fuzzy implication and is called a g-generated implication. Note that, since x 1, x f(y) f(y) f(0), we have f ( 1) = f 1 in (17). As can be seen from Theorems 2 and 3 the f- and g-generators can be used as additive generators for generating t-norms and t-conorms, respectively. We will use the terms f-generated (ggenerated resp.) implication and f-implication (g-implication resp.) interchangeably. It is easy to see that J f, J g are neutral fuzzy implications and a few examples from these two classes are given in Tables IV and V (see [49] Pp ).

12 12 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic g(x) g ( 1) (z) g(1) J g(x, y) log(1 x) 1 e z 1 (1 y) x 1 π tan 2 x 2 π tan 1 (z) π 1 π 2 tan 1 x tan 2 y x min(1, z) 1 min 1, y x x λ min 1, z λ 1 y ; λ (0, ) 1 min 1, x 1 λ TABLE V EXAMPLES OF SOME J g IMPLICATIONS WITH THEIR g-generators Lemma 1: Let J be (i) an f-implication J f obtained from an f-generator, or (ii) a g-implication J g obtained from a g-generator such that g(1) =. Then J(x, y) = 1 iff either x = 0 or y = 1. Proof: (i) Let J be an f-implication J f. Then the reverse implication is obvious. On the other hand, J f (x, y) = 1 = f ( 1) (x f(y)) = 1 = x f(y) = f(1) = 0, which implies either x = 0 or f(y) = 0, which by the strictness of f means y = 1. (ii) Let J be a g-implication J g obtained from a g-generator such that g(1) =. Again, the reverse implication is obvious. On the other hand, since g(1) =, we have g ( 1) = g 1 and ( ) 1 J g (x, y) = 1 = g 1 x g(y) = 1 = 1 g(y) = g(1) = x which implies either x = 0 or g(y) =, i.e., y = 1. Lemma 2: Let J be (i) an f-implication J f obtained from an f-generator with f(0) =, or (ii) a g-implication J g. Then 0, if x (0, 1] J(x, 0) = 1, if x = 0.

13 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 13 Proof: x 0, then If x = 0 then J f (x, 0) = J g (x, 0) = 1 since J f, J g are fuzzy implications. If (i) J f (x, 0) = f 1 (x f(0)) = f 1 (x ) = f 1 ( ) = 0, by definition of f. 1 (ii) x and since g is strictly increasing and g(0) = 0 we have J g(x, 0) = g ( 1) g ( 1) (0) = 0. ( ) 1 x g(0) = III. THE LAW OF IMPORTATION In the following sub-sections we discuss the validity of (LI) when J is an R-, S-, QL-, f- and a g-implication. A. R- and S-Implications and the Law of Importation (LI) The following result can easily be seen: Lemma 3: If x {0, 1} or y {0, 1} or z = 1 then (LI) holds for any neutral fuzzy implication J and any t-norm T. Since all the classes of fuzzy implications considered in this work, viz., R-, S-, QL-, f- and g-implications, are neutral implications, by Lemma 3 it suffices to consider the cases when x, y (0, 1) and z [0, 1). Theorem 7: An S-implication J S,N, obtained from a t-conorm S and a strong negation N satisfies (LI) with a t-norm T iff T is the N-dual of S. Proof: Let J S,N be an S-implication obtained from a t-conorm S and a strong negation N. (= :) Let J S,N satisfy (LI) with a t-norm T. If S is the N-dual t-conorm of T then LHS (LI) = J S,N (T (x, y), z) = S[N(T (x, y)), z] = S[S (N(x), N(y)), z] (19) RHS (LI) = J S,N (x, J S,N (y, z)) = S[N(x), J S,N (y, z)] = S[N(x), S(N(y), z)] (20) Since (19) = (20), taking z = 0 we have S (N(x), N(y) = S(N(x), N(y) for all x, y [0, 1]. Since N is a strong negation and hence both one-to-one and onto on [0, 1], for every

14 14 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic x, y [0, 1] there exists x, y [0, 1] such that x = N(x ); y = N(y ). Now it follows that S (x, y) = S(x, y) for all x, y [0, 1], and that S is the N-dual t-conorm of T. ( =:) If T is the N-dual of S, then S = S and (19) = (20), by associativity (S2) of S. Thus an S-implication J S,N and a t-norm T satisfy (LI) iff T is the N-dual of S. Theorem 8: An R-implication J T obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T satisfies (LI) with a t-norm T iff T = T. Proof: Let J T be the R-implication obtained as the residuation of the left-continuous t-norm T. Then J T (x, y) = max{t [0, 1] : T (x, t) y}, for all x, y [0, 1]. Since ( JT, T ) satisfy the residuation principle (RP), we have, T (x, y) z x J T (y, z). Also by (OP) we have J T (x, y) = 1 iff x y. ( =:) Let T = T. Now, since T is left-continuous we have LHS (LI) = J T (T (x, y), z) = J T (T (x, y), z) (= :) Let J T z = T (x, y). Now, = max{t [0, 1] : T (T (x, y), t) z} = max{t [0, 1] : T (T (t, x), y) z} [ Associativity (T2) of T = max{t [0, 1] : T (t, x) J T (y, z)} [ By (RP) = max{t [0, 1] : t J T (x, J T (y, z))} [ By (RP) = J T (x, J T (y, z)) = RHS (LI) satisfy (LI) for some t-norm T. Let x, y (0, 1) be arbitrary but fixed and J T (T (x, y), T (x, y)) = J T (x, J T (y, T (x, y))) = J T (x, J T (y, T (y, x))) [ Commutativity (T1) of T J T (x, x) = 1 [ From (15) & (OP) = T (x, y) T (x, y). [ From (OP) (21) On the other hand, for the above fixed x, y let z = T (x, y). Then we have, J T (T (x, y), T (x, y)) = 1 = J T (x, J T (y, T (x, y))) = 1 = x J T (y, T (y, x))) [ From (OP) = T (x, y) T (x, y). [ From (RP) (22)

15 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 15 From (21) and (22) and since x, y are arbitrary we see that T = T. In Table I the t-norms under the column T and in Table II the t-norms under the column T are the t-norms corresponding to the S-implications and R-implications ( under the columns J S,N and J T ), respectively, that satisfy (LI). From Theorems 7, 8 and Proposition 2 we have the following Corollary: Corollary 1: Let ϕ : [0, 1] [0, 1] be an increasing bijection. (i) The ϕ-conjugate of an S-implication J S,N satisfies (LI) iff T is the N ϕ -dual of S ϕ. (ii) The ϕ-conjugate of an R-implication J T satisfies (LI) iff T = Tϕ, where Tϕ is the ϕ-conjugate of the t-norm whose residuation J T is. B. QL-Implications and the Law of Importation Theorem 9: Let J QL be a QL-implication obtained from a t-conorm S, t-norm T and a strong negation N. If (LI) holds for a QL-implication J QL and a t-norm T then S (N (x), x) = 1, for all x [0, 1]. If S is continuous then (LI) implies that S and N have the representation as given in (10) and (11), respectively. Proof: Let J QL be a QL-implication obtained from a t-conorm S, t-norm T and a strong negation N and T be any t-norm. Consider the case when y = 0 and x, z [0, 1]. Then LHS (LI) = J QL (T (x, 0), z) = J QL (0, z) = 1 [ From (J3) RHS (LI) = J QL (x, J QL (0, z)) = J QL (x, 1) Since J QL satisfies (LI), from Remark 2 we see that J QL (x, 1) = 1 only if S (N (x), x) = 1, for all x [0, 1]. If S is a continuous t-conorm, then that S and N have the representation as given in (10) and (11), respectively, is an obvious consequence from Theorem 5. In the rest of this sub-section we consider only continuous t-conorms S and hence by Theorem 9 if the QL-implication J QL given by (16) satisfies (LI) then we know that S is nilpotent and hence from Theorem 4 the ϕ-conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-conorm S L (x, y) = min(x + y, 1) for an increasing bijection ϕ of the unit interval [0, 1]. Let us consider the extreme case when N (x) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)) (from the same bijection ϕ), in which case from Theorem 1 we have that N is a strong negation. Also we consider T to be either a ϕ-conjugate of a continuous Archimedean t-norm or min. Theorem 10: Let S be a continuous t-conorm with representation (10) for an increasing bijection ϕ : [0, 1] [0, 1], N be the associated strong negation, i.e., N (x) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)).

16 16 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic Let J QL be a QL-implication obtained from S, T, N. (i) If the t-norm T is the ϕ-conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-norm T L, then J QL satisfies (LI) with a t-norm T iff T = T M, the minimum t-norm. (ii) If the t-norm T is the ϕ-conjugate of the product t-norm T P, then J QL satisfies (LI) with a t-norm T iff T = T. (iii) If the t-norm T = T M, the minimum t-norm, then J QL satisfies (LI) with a t-norm T iff T is the ϕ-conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-norm T L. Proof: By the choice of S, N we have that they satisfy S (N (x), x) = 1, for all x [0, 1]. Also from our assumptions on N we have ϕ(n (x)) = ϕ ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)) = 1 ϕ(x). (i) Let T be the ϕ-conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-norm. Note also that T is the N -dual of S. Then it is immediate that T is a nilpotent t-norm and has a representation as in (7) and ϕ(t (x, y)) = max{ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) 1, 0}. Now, J QL (x, y) = S (N (x), T (x, y)) = ϕ 1 (min{ϕ(n (x)) + ϕ(t (x, y)), 1}) = ϕ 1 (min{1 ϕ(x) + max[ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) 1, 0], 1}) ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)), if ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) 1 = y, if ϕ(x) + ϕ(y) > 1 N (x), if y ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)) i.e., y N (x) i.e., J QL (x, y) = y, if y > ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)) i.e., y > N (x) = max{n (x), y} which is an S-implication with S = max. Hence by Theorem 7 we have that J QL satisfies (LI) iff T = min, which is the N-dual of max for any strong N. (ii) Let T be the ϕ-conjugate of the product t-norm. Then it is immediate that T is a strict t-norm and has a representation as in (6). Also ϕ(t (x, y)) = ϕ(x) ϕ(y) and J QL (x, y) = S (N (x), T (x, y)) = ϕ 1 (min{ϕ(n (x)) + ϕ(t (x, y)), 1}) = ϕ 1 (min{1 ϕ(x) + ϕ(x) ϕ(y), 1}) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x) + ϕ(x) ϕ(y))

17 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 17 which is the ϕ-conjugate of the Reichenbach implication J R (x, y) = 1 x+x y which is an S-implication obtained from the algebraic sum t-conorm S P (x, y) = x + y x y and the strong negation N(x) = 1 x. Now by Corollary 1 (i) we have that J QL satisfies (LI) if and only if T is the N ϕ -dual of the ϕ-conjugate of the algebraic sum t-conorm (S P ) ϕ (x, y) = ϕ 1 (ϕ(x)+ϕ(y) ϕ(x) ϕ(y)) where N ϕ (x) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x)) = N (x). Now by an easy verification we can see that T (x, y) = N ϕ [S ϕ (N ϕ (x), N ϕ (y))] = ϕ 1 (ϕ(x) ϕ(y)) = T (x, y). (iii) Let T = min. Then J QL (x, y) = S (N (x), min(x, y)) = ϕ 1 (min{ϕ(n (x)) + ϕ(min(x, y)), 1}) = ϕ 1 (min{1 ϕ(x) + min[ϕ(x), ϕ(y)], 1}) 1, if ϕ(x) ϕ(y) = ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x) + ϕ(y)), if ϕ(x) > ϕ(y) = min{1, ϕ 1 (1 ϕ(x) + ϕ(y))} which is the ϕ-conjugate of the Łukasiewicz implication J L (x, y) = min(1, 1 x + y). Now by Corollary 1 (ii) we have that J QL satisfies (LI) if and only if T is the ϕ- conjugate of the Łukasiewicz t-norm T L, i.e., T (x, y) = ϕ 1 (max{ϕ(x)+ϕ(y) 1, 0}). C. Yagers f- and g-implications and the law of importation Theorem 11: Let J f be an f-generated implication. J f satisfies the law of importation (LI) with a t-norm T if and only if T = T P, the product t-norm. Proof: Since J f is a neutral fuzzy implication by Lemma 3 it suffices to consider (LI) only for the cases x, y (0, 1) and z [0, 1). ( =:) Let T be the product t-norm. Then for all x, y (0, 1) and z [0, 1), RHS (LI) = J f (x, J f (y, z)) = f ( 1) [x f(j f (y, z))] = f ( 1) [x f f ( 1) (y f(z))] [ f ( 1) = f 1 = f ( 1) [x (y f(z))] = J f (x y, z) = LHS (LI)

18 18 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic (= :) Let J f obey the law of importation (LI) with a t-norm T. Then for all x, y (0, 1) and z [0, 1), LHS (LI) = RHS (LI) = J f (T (x, y), z)) = J f (x, J f (y, z)) = f ( 1) [T (x, y) f(z)] = f ( 1) [x f f ( 1) (y f(z))] = [T (x, y) f(z)] = x y f(z) [ f ( 1) = f 1 (23) Now, if z (0, 1) then, since f is strictly decreasing, 0 < f(z) < and hence from (23) we have T (x, y) = x y for all x, y [0, 1]. Lemma 4: If a g-implication J g satisfies the law of importation (LI) with a t-norm T, then T (x, y) 0 for any x, y (0, 1). Proof: On the contrary, let T (x 0, y 0 ) = 0 for some x 0, y 0 (0, 1). Let z [0, 1). Then J g (T (x 0, y 0 ), z) = J g (0, z) = 1 by (J3). Since, J g satisfies the law of importation (LI) w.r.to T we have 1 = J g (x 0, J g (y 0, z)). In particular if z = 0 then J g (y 0, z) = J g (y 0, 0) = 0 and J g (x 0, J g (y 0, z)) = J g (x 0, 0) = 0 from Lemma 2 (ii) from which we have 1 = 0, a contradiction. Hence T (x, y) 0 for any x, y (0, 1). Theorem 12: Let J g be a g-generated implication with g : [0, 1] [0, ] such that g(1) =. J g satisfies the law of importation (LI) with a t-norm T if and only if T = T P, the product t-norm. Proof: Let J g be a g-generated implication obtained from a g-generator such that g(1) =. Then we have g ( 1) = g 1. Again from Lemma 2 (ii) J g (x, 0) = 0, for all x (0, 1] and hence (LI) holds for J g and any t-norm T when z = 0. Hence in the following we consider (LI) only for z (0, 1), which implies g(z) (0, ). ( =:) Let T be the product t-norm. Then for all x, y, z (0, 1) RHS (LI) = J g (x, J g (y, z)) ( ) 1 = g 1 x g [J g(y, z)] ( [ ]) 1 1 = g 1 x g g 1 y g(z) ( ) [ ] 1 = g 1 x y g(z) = g 1 1 T (x, y) g(z) = J g (T (x, y), z)) = LHS (LI)

19 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 19 (= :) Let J g obey the law of importation (LI) with a t-norm T. Then for all x, y, z (0, 1), we note that from Lemma 4 T (x, y) 0, and also [ ] J g (T (x, y), z) = J g (x, J g (y, z)) = g 1 1 T (x, y) g(z) i.e., 1 T (x, y) g(z) = 1 x y g(z) ( ) 1 = g 1 x g [J g(y, z)] from which we obtain T (x, y) = x y, for all x, y [0, 1], since g(z) (0, ). Toward proving the above result for the case when g(1) < we prove the following proposition: Proposition 3: Let g be a g-generator with g(1) < and let x, y, z (0, 1) such that 1 y g(z) < g(1). Then the following equality (24) holds if and only if T = T P, the product t-norm: ( ) ( ) 1 1 g ( 1) x y g(z) = g ( 1) T (x, y) g(z) (24) Proof: (= :) Clearly if T = T P then we have the equality (24). ( =:) We prove the converse by considering the following two cases. Let ( ) ( ) 1 1 d = g ( 1) y g(z) = g 1 y g(z), with y, z (0, 1) where 1 y g(z) < g(1). Note that g(d) = 1 y g(z). 1) Let x (0, 1) be such that 1 g(d) g(1). Then we claim that T (x, y) x y. Indeed, x since 1 x g(d) g(1) we have g( 1) ( 1 x g(d) ) g ( 1) g(1) = 1. Hence from the equality (24) we have ( ) 1 g ( 1) T (x, y) g(z) = 1 ( ) 1 T (x, y) g(z) g(1). Now, under the above assumptions on x, y, z let T (x, y) > x y. Then T (x, y) > x y = 1 x y > 1 T (x, y) = g(z) x y > g(z) T (x, y) = g ( 1) ( g(z) x y ) > g ( 1) ( g(z) T (x, y) a contradiction to the fact that the equality (24) holds. 1 2) Let x (0, 1) be such that g(d) < g(1). Then we claim T (x, y) = x y for x all x, y (0, 1). Infact, since 1 ( ) 1 x g(d) < g(1) we have by (8) g( 1) x g(d) = ),

20 20 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic g 1 ( 1 x g(d) ). Hence by equality (24) we have T (x, y) = x y, for all x, y (0, 1), since g(z) (0, ). Remark 3: Note that, in Proposition 3, in the proof of the case when 1 g(d) g(1) if x T (x, y) x y we still have the equivalence, since then T (x, y) x y = 1 x y 1 T (x, y) = 1 = g ( 1) ( g(z) x y g(z) = x y g(z) T (x, y) ) ( ) g(z) g ( 1) T (x, y) ( ) g(z) and hence g ( 1) = 1 and equality (24) holds. T (x, y) Theorem 13: Let g be a g-generator such that g(1) <. Then J g the g-generated implication satisfies the law of importation (LI) if and only if T = T P, the product t-norm. Proof: Let a g-generator be such that g(1) <. As noted earlier we only consider x, y, z (0, 1) and from Lemma 4 we know that T (x, y) 0. Firstly, we note the following: Since g(1) <, we have by (8), g ( 1) g = id but g g ( 1) (x) = x, only if x g(1). 1 x > 0 = 1 y y, for any y [0, ). x Since z (0, 1), g(z) (0, ). We have the following two cases. 1) Let y, z (0, 1) such that 1 g(z) g(1) and T be any t-norm. Then for all x (0, 1), y LHS (LI) RHS (LI) = 1. ( Indeed, ) since g is increasing and g ( 1) g = id, we have 1 1 g(z) g(1) = g( 1) y y g(z) = 1, and ( ( )) ( ) RHS (LI) = J g (x, J g (y, z)) = g ( 1) x g g( 1) y g(z) = g ( 1) x g(1) = 1. Now, let T be any t-norm. Then, T (x, y) y = 1 y 1 T (x, y) = g(1) g(z) g(z) y T (x, y) ( ) g(z) = g ( 1) g(1) g ( 1) T (x, y) = 1 = J g (T (x, y), z)) = LHS (LI)

21 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 21 Hence LHS (LI) RHS (LI) = 1, for any t-norm T. 2) Let us consider the other case when y, z (0, 1) such that 1 g(z) < g(1). Then y ( ) 1 1 g(z) < g(1) = g g( 1) y y g(z) = 1 y g(z). Thus we have, ( ( )) 1 1 RHS (LI) = J g (x, J g (y, z)) = g ( 1) x g g( 1) y g(z) ( ) 1 = g ( 1) x y g(z). (25) ( ) 1 LHS (LI) = J g (T (x, y), z)) = g ( 1) T (x, y) g(z). (26) We see that the equivalence of (25) and (26) under the above assumptions is nothing but the equality (24), which from Proposition 3 holds if and only if T = T P in (26). From the above cases it is clear that the g-implication J g obtained from a g-generator with g(1) < satisfies the law of importation (LI) if and only if T = T P, the product t-norm. IV. THE LAW OF IMPORTATION IN THE SETTING OF UNINORMS AND t-operators In this section we investigate the equivalence (LI) when T is either a uninorm or a t- operator. A. Law of Importation with a Uninorm U instead of a t-norm T In this section we consider the following equality, where U is a uninorm: J(U(x, y), z) = J(x, J(y, z)) (LI:U) Lemma 5: If a neutral fuzzy implication J satisfies (LI:U) then U(0, 1) 1, i.e. U is conjunctive. Proof: Let J be a neutral fuzzy implication, i.e., J(1, x) = x, x [0, 1] and U(0, 1) = 1. Letting x = 0, y = 1, z 1, we have, LHS (LI:U) = J(U(0, 1), z) = J(1, z) = z RHS (LI:U) = J(0, J(1, z)) = J(0, z) = 1 LHS (LI:U) = RHS (LI:U) = z = 1, a contradiction. Since all of the fuzzy implications considered in this work are neutral, in this section, we only consider conjunctive uninorms U for (LI:U).

22 22 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic Theorem 14: An S-implication J S,N, obtained from a t-conorm S and a strong negation N, satisfies (LI:U) with a conjunctive uninorm U only if the identity e of U is 1, or equivalently U = T, the t-norm that is N-dual of S. Proof: Let U be a conjunctive uninorm with the identity element e (0, 1] and J S,N be the S-implication obtained from a t-conorm S and a strong negation N. Letting x = e, y = 1, z = 0 we have LHS (LI:U) = J S,N [U(e, 1), 0] = J S,N (1, 0) = 0. RHS (LI:U) = J S,N [e, J S,N (1, 0)] = J S,N (e, 0) = N(e). LHS (LI:U) = RHS (LI:U) = N(e) = 0 = e = 1 = U = T, a t-norm. Now from Theorem 7 we have that U is the t-norm that is N-dual of S. From the proof of the above theorem and noting that J QL (x, 0) = S(N(x), T (x, 0)) = N(x) for all x [0, 1] we have that a QL-implication J QL satisfies (LI:U) with a conjunctive uninorm U only if the identity e of U is 1, i.e., U is a t-norm. Theorem 15: An R-implication J T obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T satisfies (LI:U) with a conjunctive uninorm U only if the identity e of U is 1, or equivalently U = T, the t-norm from which J T was obtained. Proof: Let U be a conjunctive uninorm with the identity element e (0, 1]. Let J T be an R-implication obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T. We know from (OP) that J T (x, x) = 1, for all x [0, 1]. Letting x = 1, y = z = e in (LI:U), LHS (LI:U) = J T [U(1, e), e] = J T (1, e) = e. RHS (LI:U) = J T [1, J T (e, e)] = J T (1, 1) = 1. Now, LHS (LI:U) = RHS (LI:U) = e = 1, i.e., U = T, a t-norm. Now from Theorem 8 we have that U = T is the t-norm from which J T was obtained. Theorem 16: An f-implication J f satisfies (LI:U) with a conjunctive uninorm U only if the identity element e of U is 1, or equivalently, U is the product t-norm T P. Proof: Let J f be an f-implication obtained from an f-generator. Let x = z = e, y = 1. Then LHS (LI:U) = J f (U(e, 1), e) = J f (1, e) = e; RHS (LI:U) = J f (e, J f (1, e)) = f 1 (e f(e)) J f satisfies (LI:U) only if f 1 (e f(e)) = e = e f(e) = f(e) which implies either e = 1 or f(e) = 0 or f(e) =. Now, f(e) = = e = 0, a contradiction to the fact that U is a

23 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 23 conjunctive uninorm and e (0, 1]. Hence we have e = 1. Now, from Theorem 11 we have that U is the product t-norm T P. Theorem 17: A g-implication J g satisfies (LI:U) with a conjunctive uninorm U only if the identity element e of U is 1, or equivalently U is the product t-norm T P. Proof: Let J g be a g-implication obtained from a g-generator. Let x = z = e, y = 1. Then LHS (LI:U) = J g (U(e, 1), e) = J g (1, e) = e while RHS (LI:U) = J g (e, J g (1, e)) = J g (e, e) = g ( 1) ( 1 e g(e) ). J g satisfies (LI:U) only if g ( 1) ( 1 e g(e) ) = e. Here again we consider the following two cases: Case 1: Let 1 e g(e) < g(1). Then g( 1) ( 1 e g(e) ) = g 1 ( 1 e g(e) ). Hence, g 1 ( 1 e g(e) ) = e = 1 e = 1 e g(e) = g(e) = 1 or g(e) = 0 or g(e) = = e = 1 or e = 0 Now, e = 0 implies U is a t-conorm, contradicting the fact that U is a conjunctive uninorm and so we have e = 1 and U = T, a t-norm. Case 2: Let 1 e g(e) g(1). Then g( 1) ( 1 e g(e) ) = 1 = e and U = T, a t-norm. Now, from Theorems 12 and 13 we have that U is the product t-norm T P. B. Law of Importation with a t-operator F instead of a t-norm T In this section we consider the following equality, where F is a t-operator: J(F (x, y), z) = J(x, J(y, z)) (LI:F) Lemma 6: Let J be a fuzzy implication operator such that J(x, y) = 1 iff either x = 0 or y = 1. Then J satisfies (LI:F) only if k = 0, or equivalently F = T, a t-norm. Proof: Let x = 0, y = 1, z [0, 1). Then LHS (LI:F) = J(F (0, 1), z) = J(k, z) and RHS (LI:F) = J(0, J(1, z)) = 1. Hence for J to satisfy (LI:F) we need J(k, z) = 1, which since z 1 by the hypothesis we have k = 0, or equivalently F = T, a t-norm. Lemma 7: Let J be a fuzzy implication operator such that J(x, 0) = 1 if and only if x = 0. Then J satisfies (LI:F) only if k = 0, or equivalently F = T, a t-norm.

24 24 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic Proof: Let x = 1, y = z = 0. Then LHS (LI:F) = J(F (1, 0), 0) = J(k, 0) and RHS (LI:F) = J(1, J(0, 0)) = 1. Hence for J to satisfy (LI:F) we need J(k, 0) = 1, and from the given condition on J we have k = 0, or equivalently F = T, a t-norm. Theorem 18: Let J be either (i) an S-implication J S,N, or (ii) an R-implication J T obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T, or (iii) an f-implication J f, or (iv) a g-implication J g. Then J satisfies (LI:F) only if the absorption element k of F is 0, i.e., F = T, a t-norm. Proof: Let F be a t-operator with the absorption element F (1, 0) = k. (i) Let J S,N be an S-implication obtained from a t-conorm S and strong negation N. Then J S,N (x, 0) = N(x), the strong negation and hence J S,N (x, 0) = 1 x = 0. Now, by Lemma 7 we have k = 0, i.e., F is a t-norm. (ii) Let J T be an R-implication obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T. We know, from the Ordering Property (OP), that J T (x, x) = 1, x [0, 1]. Now let 0 x < k. Then by definition F (1, x) = k. Let a = 1, b = x = c we have LHS (LI:F) = J T [F (1, x), x] = J T (k, x). RHS (LI:F) = J T [1, J T (x, x)] = J T (1, 1) = 1. Hence LHS (LI:F) = RHS (LI:F) = J T (k, x) = 1 = k x, a contradiction to the fact that x < k. Thus there does not exist any x such that 0 x < k = k = 0, i.e., F is a t-norm. (iii) Let J f be an f-implication. Then the result is obvious from the Lemmas 6 and 1. (iv) Let J g be a g-implication. Then the result is obvious from the Lemmas 7 and 2. Corollary 2: (i) An S-implication J S,N satisfies (LI:F) iff F is the N-dual t-norm of S; (ii) An R-implication J T obtained from a left-continuous t-norm T satisfies (LI:F) iff F = T ; (iii) An f-implication J f satisfies (LI:F) iff F is the product t-norm; (iv) A g-implication J g satisfies (LI:F) iff F is the product t-norm. Once again, from part (i) of the proof of the Theorem 18 and noting that J QL (., 0) = N, a strong negation, we have that a QL-implication J QL satisfies (LI:F) only if the absorption

25 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 25 element k of F is 0, or equivalently F = T, a t-norm. V. HIERARCHICAL CRI In this section we discuss the structure and inference in one of the most established methods of inferencing in Approximate Reasoning, viz., Zadeh s Compositional Rule of Inference (CRI) [52]. After detailing some of the drawbacks of CRI, we propose a novel inferencing scheme called the Hierarchical CRI, which is a modification of the CRI and has many advantages over CRI, most notably computational efficiency. We illustrate these concepts with some numerical examples. Definition 16: A fuzzy set on a non-empty set X, A : X [0, 1], is said to be a fuzzy singleton if there exists an x 0 X such that A has the following representation: 1, if x = x 0 A(x) = (27) 0, if x x 0 We say A attains normality at x 0 X. A. Structure and Inference in CRI The Compositional Rule of Inference (CRI) proposed by Zadeh [52] is one of the earliest implementations of Generalised Modus Ponens. Here, a fuzzy if-then rule of the form: If x is A T hen ỹ is B (28) is represented as a fuzzy relation R(x, y) : X Y [0, 1] as follows: R(x, y) = [A(x) B(y)] = J(A(x), B(y)) (29) where is any fuzzy implication J : [0, 1] [0, 1] [0, 1] and A, B are fuzzy sets on their respective domains X, Y. In this section, unless otherwise explicitly stated x X, y Y and z Z. Then given a fact x is A, the inferred output B is obtained as composition of A (x) and R(x, y), i.e., B (y) = A (x) R(x, y) (30) where is a Sup t-norm composition given by B (y) = A (x) R(x, y) = Sup x X {T [A (x), R(x, y)]} (31) where T can be any t-norm (see Wangming [47]).

26 26 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic In the case when the input A is a singleton (27) attaining normality at an x 0 X then B (y) = A (x) R(x, y) = Sup x X {T [A (x), R(x, y)]} = T [A (x 0 ), R(x 0, y)] = R(x 0, y) (32) In the case of Multi-Input Single-Output (MISO) fuzzy rule given by R : If x is A and ỹ is B T hen z is C. (33) the relation R is given by R(x, y; z) = J[ce(A(x, y)) ce(b(x, y)), C(z)] = J[A(x) B(y), C(z)] (34) where ce(a(x, y)) stands for the Cylindrical Extension of the fuzzy set A with respect to the universe of B, and viceversa, and is the antecedent combiner, which is usually a t-norm. Consider a single MISO rule of the type (33), denoted (A, B) C, for simplicity. Then given a multiple-input (A, B ) the infered output C, taking the Sup T composition, is given by, C = (A, B ) [(A, B) C] (35) C (z) = Sup x,y T {[A (x) B (y)], [A(x) B(y)] C(z)} (36) As in the SISO case, when the inputs are singleton fuzzy sets A and B attaining normality at the points x 0 X, y 0 Y, respectively, we have from (36) C (z) = [A(x 0 ) B(y 0 )] C(z) = R(x 0, y 0 ; z) (37) Once again, is the antecedent combiner which is usually any of the t-norms. Example 1: Let A = [ ], B = [1.6.8] and C = [.1.1.2], where A, B and C are defined on X = {x 1, x 2, x 3, x 4 }, Y = {y 1, y 2, y 3 } and Z = {z 1, z 2, z 3 }, respectively. Let J be the Reichenbach implication J R (x, y) = 1 x + x y and the antecedent combiner be the product t-norm T P (x, y) = x y. Then taking the cylindrical extensions of A and B with respect to T P, we have that A B = T P (A, B) =

27 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic 27 Now, with x y = 1 x + x y, T P (A, B) C from (34) will be given by R(A, B : C) = [C(z 1 ) C(z 2 ) C(z 3 )], where T P (A, B) C = T P (A, B) [z 1 z 2 z 3 ] = T P (A, B) [.1.1.2] and C(z i ) = T P (A, B) z i are given as follows: C(z 1 ) = C(z 2 ) = ; C(z 3 ) = Let A = [ ], B = [0 1 0] be the given fuzzy singleton inputs. Then A B = T P (A, B ) = (38) Taking the Sup min composition, we have C = T P (A, B ) [T P (A, B) C] = [ ] (39) B. Drawbacks of CRI Despite its prevalent use CRI is not without its drawbacks, chiefly: Computational Complexity: The calculation of the supremum in (36) is a time consuming process. When X = m and Y = n, the complexity of a single inference amounts to O(m n). Explosion in Dimensions: For an n-input 1-output system (A 1, A 2,..., A n ) B with the cardinality of the base sets X i of each of the inputs A i being n i, we have an n- dimensional matrix having n i=1 n i entries. Expensive Storage: As noted above, we need to store n-dimensional matrices for every fuzzy if-then rule. The many works proposing modifications to Zadeh s CRI can be broadly categorised into works that attempt to improve the accuracy of inferencing in CRI and those that intend to enhance the efficiency in its inferencing. Some works relating to the former approach are those of Ying [51] who investigated the reasonableness of CRI and proposed a suitable modification of the CRI, Wangming [47] who was one of the earliest to employ the Sup T composition and has studied the suitability of pairs (T, J) - of the t-norm T

28 28 BALASUBRAMANIAM: On the Law of Importation in fuzzy logic used for composition and the fuzzy implication J - that satisfy some appropriate criteria for Generalised Modus Ponens (GMP) and Generalised Modus Tollens (GMT). In [11] necessary and sufficient conditions on operators involved in CRI inferencing are investigated to fit the CRI into the analogical scheme. For works relating to computation of CRI and exact formulae see the works by Fullér and his group [22], [23], [21]. For some recent works see Moser and Navara [32], [33], [34]. In the case when there are more than two antecedents involved in fuzzy inference, Ruan and Kerre [37] have proposed an extension to Zadeh s CRI, wherein starting from a finite number of fuzzy relations of an arbitrary number of variables but having some variables in common, one can infer fuzzy relations among the variables of interest. As noted above, because of the multi-dimensionality of the fuzzy relation (34) inferencing in CRI (35) is difficult to perform. To overcome this difficulty, Demirli and Turksen [15] proposed a Rule Break-up method and showed that rules with two or more independent variables in their premise can be simplified to a number of inferences of rule bases with simple rules (only one variable in their premise). For further modification of this method see [24]. In the following we propose a modified but novel form of CRI to address the drawbacks noted above. C. Hierarchical CRI In the field of fuzzy control, Hierarchical Fuzzy Systems (HFS) hold a center stage, since, where applicable, they help to a large extent in breaking down the complexity of the system being modeled, both in terms of efficiency and understandability. For a good survey of HFS see Torra [42] and the references therein. In this section, we propose a new modified form of CRI termed Hierarchical CRI owing to the way in which multiple antecedents of a fuzzy rule are operated upon in the inferencing. A distinction should be made between the method proposed in this work - which uses the given MISO fuzzy rules as is - and typical inferencing in HFS which is dictated by the hierarchical structure that exists among the modeled system variables. It should be emphasised that the term Hierarchical CRI, as employed here, refers to the modifications in the inferencing procedure of CRI and does not impose a hierarchical architecture on the MISO fuzzy rules. From the law of importation (LI), we see that (34) can be rewritten as, using a t-norm T

Kybernetika. Michał Baczyński; Balasubramaniam Jayaram Yager s classes of fuzzy implications: some properties and intersections

Kybernetika. Michał Baczyński; Balasubramaniam Jayaram Yager s classes of fuzzy implications: some properties and intersections Kybernetika Michał Baczyński; Balasubramaniam Jayaram Yager s classes of fuzzy implications: some properties and intersections Kybernetika, Vol. 43 (2007), No. 2, 57--82 Persistent URL: http://dml.cz/dmlcz/35764

More information

On the Intersections of QL-Implications with (S, N)- and R-Implications

On the Intersections of QL-Implications with (S, N)- and R-Implications On the Intersections of QL-Implications with (S, N)- and R-Implications Balasubramaniam Jayaram Dept. of Mathematics and Computer Sciences, Sri Sathya Sai Institute of Higher Learning, Prasanthi Nilayam,

More information

Continuous R-implications

Continuous R-implications Continuous R-implications Balasubramaniam Jayaram 1 Michał Baczyński 2 1. Department of Mathematics, Indian Institute of echnology Madras, Chennai 600 036, India 2. Institute of Mathematics, University

More information

(S, N)- and R-implications: A state-of-the-art survey

(S, N)- and R-implications: A state-of-the-art survey Fuzzy Sets and Systems 159 (2008) 1836 1859 www.elsevier.com/locate/fss (S, N)- and R-implications: A state-of-the-art survey Michał Baczyński a,, Balasubramaniam Jayaram b a Institute of Mathematics,

More information

Kybernetika. Margarita Mas; Miquel Monserrat; Joan Torrens QL-implications versus D-implications. Terms of use:

Kybernetika. Margarita Mas; Miquel Monserrat; Joan Torrens QL-implications versus D-implications. Terms of use: Kybernetika Margarita Mas; Miquel Monserrat; Joan Torrens QL-implications versus D-implications Kybernetika, Vol. 42 (2006), No. 3, 35--366 Persistent URL: http://dml.cz/dmlcz/3579 Terms of use: Institute

More information

A Deep Study of Fuzzy Implications

A Deep Study of Fuzzy Implications A Deep Study of Fuzzy Implications Yun Shi Promotor: prof. dr. Etienne E. Kerre Copromotor: prof. dr. Da Ruan Dissertation submitted to Faculty of Science of Ghent University in fulfillment of the requirements

More information

This article was originally published in a journal published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier for the author s benefit and for the benefit of the author s institution, for non-commercial

More information

Directional Monotonicity of Fuzzy Implications

Directional Monotonicity of Fuzzy Implications Acta Polytechnica Hungarica Vol. 14, No. 5, 2017 Directional Monotonicity of Fuzzy Implications Katarzyna Miś Institute of Mathematics, University of Silesia in Katowice Bankowa 14, 40-007 Katowice, Poland,

More information

The problem of distributivity between binary operations in bifuzzy set theory

The problem of distributivity between binary operations in bifuzzy set theory The problem of distributivity between binary operations in bifuzzy set theory Pawe l Drygaś Institute of Mathematics, University of Rzeszów ul. Rejtana 16A, 35-310 Rzeszów, Poland e-mail: paweldr@univ.rzeszow.pl

More information

Left-continuous t-norms in Fuzzy Logic: an Overview

Left-continuous t-norms in Fuzzy Logic: an Overview Left-continuous t-norms in Fuzzy Logic: an Overview János Fodor Dept. of Biomathematics and Informatics, Faculty of Veterinary Sci. Szent István University, István u. 2, H-1078 Budapest, Hungary E-mail:

More information

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019

Fuzzy Sets. Mirko Navara   navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 28, 2019 The notion of fuzzy set. Minimum about classical) sets Fuzzy ets Mirko Navara http://cmp.felk.cvut.cz/ navara/fl/fset printe.pdf February 8, 09 To aviod problems of the set theory, we restrict ourselves

More information

Bandler-Kohout Subproduct with Yager s classes of Fuzzy Implications

Bandler-Kohout Subproduct with Yager s classes of Fuzzy Implications Bandler-Kohout Subproduct with Yager s classes of Fuzzy Implications Sayantan Mandal and Balasubramaniam Jayaram, Member, IEEE Abstract The Bandler Kohout Subproduct BKS inference mechanism is one of the

More information

Fuzzy logic Fuzzyapproximate reasoning

Fuzzy logic Fuzzyapproximate reasoning Fuzzy logic Fuzzyapproximate reasoning 3.class 3/19/2009 1 Introduction uncertain processes dynamic engineering system models fundamental of the decision making in fuzzy based real systems is the approximate

More information

Aggregation and Non-Contradiction

Aggregation and Non-Contradiction Aggregation and Non-Contradiction Ana Pradera Dept. de Informática, Estadística y Telemática Universidad Rey Juan Carlos. 28933 Móstoles. Madrid. Spain ana.pradera@urjc.es Enric Trillas Dept. de Inteligencia

More information

Fuzzy Implications: Some Recently Solved Problems

Fuzzy Implications: Some Recently Solved Problems Fuzzy Implications: Some Recently Solved Problems M. Baczyński and B. Jayaram Abstract. In this chapter we discuss some open problemsrelated to fuzzy implications, which have either been completely solved

More information

The General Nilpotent System

The General Nilpotent System The General Nilpotent System József Dombi 1,2 Orsolya Csiszár 1 1 Óbuda University, Budapest, Hungary 2 University of Szeged, Hungary FSTA, Liptovský Ján, 2014 csiszar.orsolya@nik.uni-obuda.hu The General

More information

Chapter 1 Similarity Based Reasoning Fuzzy Systems and Universal Approximation

Chapter 1 Similarity Based Reasoning Fuzzy Systems and Universal Approximation Chapter 1 Similarity Based Reasoning Fuzzy Systems and Universal Approximation Sayantan Mandal and Balasubramaniam Jayaram Abstract In this work, we show that fuzzy inference systems based on Similarity

More information

Interval Valued Fuzzy Sets from Continuous Archimedean. Triangular Norms. Taner Bilgic and I. Burhan Turksen. University of Toronto.

Interval Valued Fuzzy Sets from Continuous Archimedean. Triangular Norms. Taner Bilgic and I. Burhan Turksen. University of Toronto. Interval Valued Fuzzy Sets from Continuous Archimedean Triangular Norms Taner Bilgic and I. Burhan Turksen Department of Industrial Engineering University of Toronto Toronto, Ontario, M5S 1A4 Canada bilgic@ie.utoronto.ca,

More information

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017

2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary. Aaron Tan August 2017 2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary Aaron Tan 21 25 August 2017 1 2. The Logic of Compound Statements 2.1 Logical Form and Logical Equivalence Statements; Compound Statements; Statement Form (Propositional

More information

Homomorphisms on The Monoid of Fuzzy Implications

Homomorphisms on The Monoid of Fuzzy Implications Homomorphisms on The Monoid of Fuzzy mplications Nageswara Rao Vemuri and Balasubramaniam Jayaram Department of Mathematics ndian nstitute of Technology Hyderabad Yeddumailaram, A.P 502 205 Email: {ma10p001,

More information

GENERATED FUZZY IMPLICATIONS IN FUZZY DECISION MAKING

GENERATED FUZZY IMPLICATIONS IN FUZZY DECISION MAKING BRNO UNIVERSITY OF TECHNOLOGY Faculty of Electrical Engineering and Communication Department of Mathematics Mgr. Vladislav Biba GENERATED FUZZY IMPLICATIONS IN FUZZY DECISION MAKING GENEROVANÉ FUZZY IMPLIKÁTORY

More information

Approximation Capability of SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems Based on Fuzzy Implications

Approximation Capability of SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems Based on Fuzzy Implications Approximation Capability of SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems Based on Fuzzy Implications Sayantan Mandal and Balasubramaniam Jayaram Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology Hyderabad

More information

Analysis of additive generators of fuzzy operations represented by rational functions

Analysis of additive generators of fuzzy operations represented by rational functions Journal of Physics: Conference Series PAPER OPEN ACCESS Analysis of additive generators of fuzzy operations represented by rational functions To cite this article: T M Ledeneva 018 J. Phys.: Conf. Ser.

More information

Computational Intelligence Winter Term 2017/18

Computational Intelligence Winter Term 2017/18 Computational Intelligence Winter Term 2017/18 Prof. Dr. Günter Rudolph Lehrstuhl für Algorithm Engineering (LS 11) Fakultät für Informatik TU Dortmund Plan for Today Fuzzy relations Fuzzy logic Linguistic

More information

TRIANGULAR NORMS WITH CONTINUOUS DIAGONALS

TRIANGULAR NORMS WITH CONTINUOUS DIAGONALS Tatra Mt. Math. Publ. 6 (999), 87 95 TRIANGULAR NORMS WITH CONTINUOUS DIAGONALS Josef Tkadlec ABSTRACT. It is an old open question whether a t-norm with a continuous diagonal must be continuous [7]. We

More information

COMP 182 Algorithmic Thinking. Proofs. Luay Nakhleh Computer Science Rice University

COMP 182 Algorithmic Thinking. Proofs. Luay Nakhleh Computer Science Rice University COMP 182 Algorithmic Thinking Proofs Luay Nakhleh Computer Science Rice University 1 Reading Material Chapter 1, Section 3, 6, 7, 8 Propositional Equivalences The compound propositions p and q are called

More information

Averaging Operators on the Unit Interval

Averaging Operators on the Unit Interval Averaging Operators on the Unit Interval Mai Gehrke Carol Walker Elbert Walker New Mexico State University Las Cruces, New Mexico Abstract In working with negations and t-norms, it is not uncommon to call

More information

Fuzzy Expert Systems Lecture 6 (Fuzzy Logic )

Fuzzy Expert Systems Lecture 6 (Fuzzy Logic ) Fuzzy Expert Systems Lecture 6 (Fuzzy Logic ) Unlike Classical Logic, Fuzzy Logic is concerned, in the main, with modes of reasoning which are approximate rather than exact L. A. Zadeh Lecture 6 صفحه Summary

More information

Characterizations of fuzzy implications satisfying the Boolean-like law y I(x, y)

Characterizations of fuzzy implications satisfying the Boolean-like law y I(x, y) Characterizations of fuzzy implications satisfying the Boolean-like law y I(x, y) Anderson Cruz, Benjamín Bedregal, and Regivan Santiago Group of Theory and Intelligence of Computation - GoThIC Federal

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making

Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making Edurne Barrenechea a, Javier Fernandez a, Miguel Pagola

More information

CONSERVATIVE AND DISSIPATIVE FOR T-NORM AND T-CONORM AND RESIDUAL FUZZY CO-IMPLICATION

CONSERVATIVE AND DISSIPATIVE FOR T-NORM AND T-CONORM AND RESIDUAL FUZZY CO-IMPLICATION Bulletin of Mathematical Analysis and Applications ISSN: 1821-1291, URL: http://www.bmathaa.org Volume 8 Issue 4(2016), Pages 78-90. CONSERVATIVE AND DISSIPATIVE FOR T-NORM AND T-CONORM AND RESIDUAL FUZZY

More information

SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems based on Fuzzy Implications are Universal Approximators

SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems based on Fuzzy Implications are Universal Approximators The final version of this work can be found at doi:10.1016/j.fss.2014.10.003. SISO Fuzzy Relational Inference Systems based on Fuzzy Implications are Universal Approximators Sayantan Mandal and Balasubramaniam

More information

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof

Chapter 1. Logic and Proof Chapter 1. Logic and Proof 1.1 Remark: A little over 100 years ago, it was found that some mathematical proofs contained paradoxes, and these paradoxes could be used to prove statements that were known

More information

The Domination Relation Between Continuous T-Norms

The Domination Relation Between Continuous T-Norms The Domination Relation Between Continuous T-Norms Susanne Saminger Department of Knowledge-Based Mathematical Systems, Johannes Kepler University Linz, Altenbergerstrasse 69, A-4040 Linz, Austria susanne.saminger@jku.at

More information

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation

Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation Extending the Monoidal T-norm Based Logic with an Independent Involutive Negation Tommaso Flaminio Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Siena Pian dei Mantellini 44 53100 Siena (Italy) flaminio@unisi.it

More information

2.2: Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic

2.2: Logical Equivalence: The Laws of Logic Example (2.7) For primitive statement p and q, construct a truth table for each of the following compound statements. a) p q b) p q Here we see that the corresponding truth tables for two statement p q

More information

Comparison of two versions of the Ferrers property of fuzzy interval orders

Comparison of two versions of the Ferrers property of fuzzy interval orders Comparison of two versions of the Ferrers property of fuzzy interval orders Susana Díaz 1 Bernard De Baets 2 Susana Montes 1 1.Dept. Statistics and O. R., University of Oviedo 2.Dept. Appl. Math., Biometrics

More information

Towards Formal Theory of Measure on Clans of Fuzzy Sets

Towards Formal Theory of Measure on Clans of Fuzzy Sets Towards Formal Theory of Measure on Clans of Fuzzy Sets Tomáš Kroupa Institute of Information Theory and Automation Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic Pod vodárenskou věží 4 182 08 Prague 8 Czech

More information

AN ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURE FOR INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY LOGIC

AN ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURE FOR INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY LOGIC Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems Vol. 9, No. 6, (2012) pp. 31-41 31 AN ALGEBRAIC STRUCTURE FOR INTUITIONISTIC FUZZY LOGIC E. ESLAMI Abstract. In this paper we extend the notion of degrees of membership

More information

Implication functions in interval-valued fuzzy set theory

Implication functions in interval-valued fuzzy set theory Implication functions in interval-valued fuzzy set theory Glad Deschrijver Abstract Interval-valued fuzzy set theory is an extension of fuzzy set theory in which the real, but unknown, membership degree

More information

Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation

Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation Arch. Math. Logic (2000) 39: 103 124 c Springer-Verlag 2000 Residuated fuzzy logics with an involutive negation Francesc Esteva 1, Lluís Godo 1, Petr Hájek 2, Mirko Navara 3 1 Artificial Intelligence Research

More information

Applied Logic. Lecture 3 part 1 - Fuzzy logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

Applied Logic. Lecture 3 part 1 - Fuzzy logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw Applied Logic Lecture 3 part 1 - Fuzzy logic Marcin Szczuka Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw Monographic lecture, Spring semester 2017/2018 Marcin Szczuka (MIMUW) Applied Logic 2018 1

More information

Conjunction: p q is true if both p, q are true, and false if at least one of p, q is false. The truth table for conjunction is as follows.

Conjunction: p q is true if both p, q are true, and false if at least one of p, q is false. The truth table for conjunction is as follows. Chapter 1 Logic 1.1 Introduction and Definitions Definitions. A sentence (statement, proposition) is an utterance (that is, a string of characters) which is either true (T) or false (F). A predicate is

More information

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION B Sc (MATHEMATICS) I Semester Core Course. FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS (MODULE I & ii) QUESTION BANK

UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION B Sc (MATHEMATICS) I Semester Core Course. FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS (MODULE I & ii) QUESTION BANK UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION B Sc (MATHEMATICS) (2011 Admission Onwards) I Semester Core Course FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS (MODULE I & ii) QUESTION BANK 1) If A and B are two sets

More information

(T; N) and Residual Fuzzy Co-Implication in Dual Heyting Algebra with Applications

(T; N) and Residual Fuzzy Co-Implication in Dual Heyting Algebra with Applications Preprints (www.preprints.org) O PEER-REVIEWED Posted: 3 August 2016 Article (; ) Residual Fuzzy Co-Implication in Dual Heyting Algebra with Applications Iqbal H. ebril Department of Mathematics cience

More information

Fundamentals of Fuzzy Logics

Fundamentals of Fuzzy Logics Fundamentals of Fuzzy Logics George Metcalfe University of Technology, Vienna, Austria metcalfe@logic.at 1 Introduction Logics come in many guises. Classical logic, to take the most obvious example, may

More information

Logic, Sets, and Proofs

Logic, Sets, and Proofs Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Operators. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that can be assigned a value either true or false.

More information

Continuity. Chapter 4

Continuity. Chapter 4 Chapter 4 Continuity Throughout this chapter D is a nonempty subset of the real numbers. We recall the definition of a function. Definition 4.1. A function from D into R, denoted f : D R, is a subset of

More information

Fuzzy Systems. Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic

Fuzzy Systems. Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic Fuzzy Systems Fuzzy Sets and Fuzzy Logic Prof. Dr. Rudolf Kruse Christoph Doell {kruse,doell}@ovgu.de Otto-von-Guericke University of Magdeburg Faculty of Computer Science Institute of Intelligent Cooperating

More information

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL 1 MINXIA LUO, 2 NI SANG, 3 KAI ZHANG 1 Department of Mathematics, China Jiliang University Hangzhou, China E-mail: minxialuo@163.com ABSTRACT

More information

Continuity. Chapter 4

Continuity. Chapter 4 Chapter 4 Continuity Throughout this chapter D is a nonempty subset of the real numbers. We recall the definition of a function. Definition 4.1. A function from D into R, denoted f : D R, is a subset of

More information

CSC Discrete Math I, Spring Propositional Logic

CSC Discrete Math I, Spring Propositional Logic CSC 125 - Discrete Math I, Spring 2017 Propositional Logic Propositions A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false Propositional Variables A propositional variable (p, q, r, s,...)

More information

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya

HANDOUT AND SET THEORY. Ariyadi Wijaya HANDOUT LOGIC AND SET THEORY Ariyadi Wijaya Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics and Natural Science Yogyakarta State University 2009 1 Mathematics Education Department Faculty of Mathematics

More information

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL

THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL 10 th February 013. Vol. 48 No.1 005-013 JATIT & LLS. All rights reserved. ISSN: 199-8645 www.jatit.org E-ISSN: 1817-3195 THE FORMAL TRIPLE I INFERENCE METHOD FOR LOGIC SYSTEM W UL 1 MINXIA LUO, NI SANG,

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Fuzzy Does Not Lie! Can BAŞKENT. 20 January 2006 Akçay, Göttingen, Amsterdam Student No:

Fuzzy Does Not Lie! Can BAŞKENT. 20 January 2006 Akçay, Göttingen, Amsterdam   Student No: Fuzzy Does Not Lie! Can BAŞKENT 20 January 2006 Akçay, Göttingen, Amsterdam canbaskent@yahoo.com, www.geocities.com/canbaskent Student No: 0534390 Three-valued logic, end of the critical rationality. Imre

More information

Comparison of Fuzzy Operators for IF-Inference Systems of Takagi-Sugeno Type in Ozone Prediction

Comparison of Fuzzy Operators for IF-Inference Systems of Takagi-Sugeno Type in Ozone Prediction Comparison of Fuzzy Operators for IF-Inference Systems of Takagi-Sugeno Type in Ozone Prediction Vladimír Olej and Petr Hájek Institute of System Engineering and Informatics, Faculty of Economics and Administration,

More information

Domination of Aggregation Operators and Preservation of Transitivity

Domination of Aggregation Operators and Preservation of Transitivity Technical Report FLLL TR 0207 SCCH TR 0237 Domination of Aggregation Operators and Preservation of Transitivity Susanne Saminger Fuzzy Logic Laboratorium Linz-Hagenberg saminger@flll.uni-linz.ac.at Radko

More information

n Empty Set:, or { }, subset of all sets n Cardinality: V = {a, e, i, o, u}, so V = 5 n Subset: A B, all elements in A are in B

n Empty Set:, or { }, subset of all sets n Cardinality: V = {a, e, i, o, u}, so V = 5 n Subset: A B, all elements in A are in B Discrete Math Review Discrete Math Review (Rosen, Chapter 1.1 1.7, 5.5) TOPICS Sets and Functions Propositional and Predicate Logic Logical Operators and Truth Tables Logical Equivalences and Inference

More information

From fuzzy dependences to fuzzy formulas and vice versa, for Kleene-Dienes fuzzy implication operator

From fuzzy dependences to fuzzy formulas and vice versa, for Kleene-Dienes fuzzy implication operator From fuzzy dependences to fuzzy formulas and vice versa, for Kleene-Dienes fuzzy implication operator NEDŽAD DUKIĆ, DŽENAN GUŠIĆ, AMELA MURATOVIĆ-RIBIĆ, ADIS ALIHODŽIĆ, EDIN TABAK, HARIS DUKIĆ University

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018 arxiv:1808.10324v1 [math.lo] 30 Aug 2018 Real coextensions as a tool for constructing triangular norms Thomas Vetterlein Department of Knowledge-Based Mathematical Systems Johannes Kepler University Linz

More information

Convex Functions and Optimization

Convex Functions and Optimization Chapter 5 Convex Functions and Optimization 5.1 Convex Functions Our next topic is that of convex functions. Again, we will concentrate on the context of a map f : R n R although the situation can be generalized

More information

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction

Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement. sentential connectives. negation. conjunction. disjunction Copyright & License Copyright c 2007 Jason Underdown Some rights reserved. statement sentential connectives negation conjunction disjunction implication or conditional antecedant & consequent hypothesis

More information

Preservation of t-norm and t-conorm based properties of fuzzy relations during aggregation process

Preservation of t-norm and t-conorm based properties of fuzzy relations during aggregation process 8th Conference of the European Society for Fuzzy Logic and Technology (EUSFLAT 2013) Preservation of t-norm and t-conorm based properties of fuzzy relations during aggregation process Urszula Dudziak Institute

More information

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets - An Alternative Look

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets - An Alternative Look Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets - An Alternative Look Anna Pankowska and Maciej Wygralak Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Adam Mickiewicz University Umultowska 87, 61-614 Poznań, Poland e-mail: wygralak@math.amu.edu.pl

More information

Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, and Fuzzy Systems

Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, and Fuzzy Systems Fuzzy Sets, Fuzzy Logic, and Fuzzy Systems SSIE 617 Fall 2008 Radim BELOHLAVEK Dept. Systems Sci. & Industrial Eng. Watson School of Eng. and Applied Sci. Binghamton University SUNY Radim Belohlavek (SSIE

More information

Compound Propositions

Compound Propositions Discrete Structures Compound Propositions Producing new propositions from existing propositions. Logical Operators or Connectives 1. Not 2. And 3. Or 4. Exclusive or 5. Implication 6. Biconditional Truth

More information

On (Weighted) k-order Fuzzy Connectives

On (Weighted) k-order Fuzzy Connectives Author manuscript, published in "IEEE Int. Conf. on Fuzzy Systems, Spain 2010" On Weighted -Order Fuzzy Connectives Hoel Le Capitaine and Carl Frélicot Mathematics, Image and Applications MIA Université

More information

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC

CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC CHAPTER 2. FIRST ORDER LOGIC 1. Introduction First order logic is a much richer system than sentential logic. Its interpretations include the usual structures of mathematics, and its sentences enable us

More information

ASSOCIATIVE n DIMENSIONAL COPULAS

ASSOCIATIVE n DIMENSIONAL COPULAS K Y BERNETIKA VOLUM E 47 ( 2011), NUMBER 1, P AGES 93 99 ASSOCIATIVE n DIMENSIONAL COPULAS Andrea Stupňanová and Anna Kolesárová The associativity of n-dimensional copulas in the sense of Post is studied.

More information

Discrete Structures of Computer Science Propositional Logic III Rules of Inference

Discrete Structures of Computer Science Propositional Logic III Rules of Inference Discrete Structures of Computer Science Propositional Logic III Rules of Inference Gazihan Alankuş (Based on original slides by Brahim Hnich) July 30, 2012 1 Previous Lecture 2 Summary of Laws of Logic

More information

Computational Intelligence Lecture 13:Fuzzy Logic

Computational Intelligence Lecture 13:Fuzzy Logic Computational Intelligence Lecture 13:Fuzzy Logic Farzaneh Abdollahi Department of Electrical Engineering Amirkabir University of Technology Fall 2011 arzaneh Abdollahi Computational Intelligence Lecture

More information

Fuzzy relation equations with dual composition

Fuzzy relation equations with dual composition Fuzzy relation equations with dual composition Lenka Nosková University of Ostrava Institute for Research and Applications of Fuzzy Modeling 30. dubna 22, 701 03 Ostrava 1 Czech Republic Lenka.Noskova@osu.cz

More information

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Winter CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH Winter 2017 http://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/wi17/cse20-ab/ Today's learning goals Distinguish between a theorem, an axiom, lemma, a corollary, and a conjecture. Recognize direct proofs

More information

Conditionally distributive real semirings

Conditionally distributive real semirings Conditionally distributive real semirings Dragan Jočić Department of Mathematics and Informatics, Faculty of Science, University of Novi Sad Trg D. Obradovića 4, 21000 Novi Sad, Serbia and Montenegro e-mail:drjocic@ptt.yu

More information

Multi-Criteria Optimization - an Important Foundation of Fuzzy System Design

Multi-Criteria Optimization - an Important Foundation of Fuzzy System Design University of Texas at El Paso DigitalCommons@UTEP Departmental Technical Reports (CS) Department of Computer Science 1-1-1997 Multi-Criteria Optimization - an Important Foundation of Fuzzy System Design

More information

Packet #1: Logic & Proofs. Applied Discrete Mathematics

Packet #1: Logic & Proofs. Applied Discrete Mathematics Packet #1: Logic & Proofs Applied Discrete Mathematics Table of Contents Course Objectives Page 2 Propositional Calculus Information Pages 3-13 Course Objectives At the conclusion of this course, you should

More information

Preservation of graded properties of fuzzy relations by aggregation functions

Preservation of graded properties of fuzzy relations by aggregation functions Preservation of graded properties of fuzzy relations by aggregation functions Urszula Dudziak Institute of Mathematics, University of Rzeszów, 35-310 Rzeszów, ul. Rejtana 16a, Poland. e-mail: ududziak@univ.rzeszow.pl

More information

Math 350 Fall 2011 Notes about inner product spaces. In this notes we state and prove some important properties of inner product spaces.

Math 350 Fall 2011 Notes about inner product spaces. In this notes we state and prove some important properties of inner product spaces. Math 350 Fall 2011 Notes about inner product spaces In this notes we state and prove some important properties of inner product spaces. First, recall the dot product on R n : if x, y R n, say x = (x 1,...,

More information

Logic Synthesis and Verification

Logic Synthesis and Verification Logic Synthesis and Verification Boolean Algebra Jie-Hong Roland Jiang 江介宏 Department of Electrical Engineering National Taiwan University Fall 2014 1 2 Boolean Algebra Reading F. M. Brown. Boolean Reasoning:

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Interval based Uncertain Reasoning using Fuzzy and Rough Sets

Interval based Uncertain Reasoning using Fuzzy and Rough Sets Interval based Uncertain Reasoning using Fuzzy and Rough Sets Y.Y. Yao Jian Wang Department of Computer Science Lakehead University Thunder Bay, Ontario Canada P7B 5E1 Abstract This paper examines two

More information

Chapter 1 Elementary Logic

Chapter 1 Elementary Logic 2017-2018 Chapter 1 Elementary Logic The study of logic is the study of the principles and methods used in distinguishing valid arguments from those that are not valid. The aim of this chapter is to help

More information

Fundamentals. 2.1 Fuzzy logic theory

Fundamentals. 2.1 Fuzzy logic theory Fundamentals 2 In this chapter we briefly review the fuzzy logic theory in order to focus the type of fuzzy-rule based systems with which we intend to compute intelligible models. Although all the concepts

More information

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1.

Sequences. Chapter 3. n + 1 3n + 2 sin n n. 3. lim (ln(n + 1) ln n) 1. lim. 2. lim. 4. lim (1 + n)1/n. Answers: 1. 1/3; 2. 0; 3. 0; 4. 1. Chapter 3 Sequences Both the main elements of calculus (differentiation and integration) require the notion of a limit. Sequences will play a central role when we work with limits. Definition 3.. A Sequence

More information

UPPER AND LOWER SET FORMULAS: RESTRICTION AND MODIFICATION OF THE DEMPSTER-PAWLAK FORMALISM

UPPER AND LOWER SET FORMULAS: RESTRICTION AND MODIFICATION OF THE DEMPSTER-PAWLAK FORMALISM Int. J. Appl. Math. Comput. Sci., 2002, Vol.12, No.3, 359 369 UPPER AND LOWER SET FORMULAS: RESTRICTION AND MODIFICATION OF THE DEMPSTER-PAWLAK FORMALISM ISMAIL BURHAN TÜRKŞEN Knowledge/Intelligence Systems

More information

CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter p. 1/33

CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter p. 1/33 CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer Science (Arkoudas and Musser) Chapter 4.1-4.8 p. 1/33 CSCI.6962/4962 Software Verification Fundamental Proof Methods in Computer

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH Fall 2017 http://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/fa17/cse20-ab/ Today's learning goals Distinguish between a theorem, an axiom, lemma, a corollary, and a conjecture. Recognize direct proofs

More information

Commutative Banach algebras 79

Commutative Banach algebras 79 8. Commutative Banach algebras In this chapter, we analyze commutative Banach algebras in greater detail. So we always assume that xy = yx for all x, y A here. Definition 8.1. Let A be a (commutative)

More information

ON T-FUZZY GROUPS. Inheung Chon

ON T-FUZZY GROUPS. Inheung Chon Kangweon-Kyungki Math. Jour. 9 (2001), No. 2, pp. 149 156 ON T-FUZZY GROUPS Inheung Chon Abstract. We characterize some properties of t-fuzzy groups and t-fuzzy invariant groups and represent every subgroup

More information

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10 Inductive sets (used to define the natural numbers as a subset of R) (1) Definition: A set S R is an inductive

More information

FURTHER DEVELOPMENT OF CHEBYSHEV TYPE INEQUALITIES FOR SUGENO INTEGRALS AND T-(S-)EVALUATORS

FURTHER DEVELOPMENT OF CHEBYSHEV TYPE INEQUALITIES FOR SUGENO INTEGRALS AND T-(S-)EVALUATORS K Y BERNETIK VOLUM E 46 21, NUMBER 1, P GES 83 95 FURTHER DEVELOPMENT OF CHEBYSHEV TYPE INEQULITIES FOR SUGENO INTEGRLS ND T-S-EVLUTORS Hamzeh gahi, Radko Mesiar and Yao Ouyang In this paper further development

More information

Proof. We indicate by α, β (finite or not) the end-points of I and call

Proof. We indicate by α, β (finite or not) the end-points of I and call C.6 Continuous functions Pag. 111 Proof of Corollary 4.25 Corollary 4.25 Let f be continuous on the interval I and suppose it admits non-zero its (finite or infinite) that are different in sign for x tending

More information

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections

Foundations of mathematics. 5. Galois connections Foundations of mathematics 5. Galois connections Sylvain Poirier http://settheory.net/ The notion of Galois connection was introduced in 2.11 (see http://settheory.net/set2.pdf) with its first properties.

More information

THE INTERVAL CONSTRUCTOR ON CLASSES OF ML-ALGEBRAS

THE INTERVAL CONSTRUCTOR ON CLASSES OF ML-ALGEBRAS FEDERAL UNIVERSITY OF RIO GRANDE DO NORTE CENTER OF EXACT AND EARTH SCIENCES DEPARTMENT OF INFORMATICS AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS PROGRAM OF POST GRADUATION IN SYSTEMS AND COMPUTATION THE INTERVAL CONSTRUCTOR

More information

software design & management Gachon University Chulyun Kim

software design & management Gachon University Chulyun Kim Gachon University Chulyun Kim 2 Outline Propositional Logic Propositional Equivalences Predicates and Quantifiers Nested Quantifiers Rules of Inference Introduction to Proofs 3 1.1 Propositional Logic

More information

Logic Overview, I. and T T T T F F F T F F F F

Logic Overview, I. and T T T T F F F T F F F F Logic Overview, I DEFINITIONS A statement (proposition) is a declarative sentence that can be assigned a truth value T or F, but not both. Statements are denoted by letters p, q, r, s,... The 5 basic logical

More information