Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall"

Transcription

1 Topics in relational Hrushovski constructions - Fall Omer Mermelstein UW-Madison Fall Notation Denote by P(X) the set of subsets of X and by Fin(X) the set of finite subsets of X. Write Y fin X for Y Fin(X). For X, Y sets and c, d elements, when there is no confusion we may abuse notation and omit the union operation: Xc = X {c}, cy d = Y {c, d}, XY = X Y, cd = {c, d}, and so on. Similarly, for tuples ā = (a 1,..., a n ), b = (b 1,..., b k ) abuse notation and write ā b for (a 1,..., a n, b 1,..., b k ). 2 Combinatorial Pregeometries Definition 2.1. A matroid is a pair (M, cl), where M is a set and cl : P(M) P(M) satisfies, for all X, Y M and a, b M, C1. X cl(x) C2. X Y = cl(x) cl(y ) C3. cl(cl(x)) = cl(x) C4. a cl(xb) \ cl(x) = b cl(xa) (Exchange) Definition 2.2. A combinatorial pregeometry is a finitary matroid, i.e. a matroid satisfying the additional requirement C5. cl(x) = X 0 fin X cl(x 0) (Finite character) Exercise 2.3. Show the following naturally occurring closure operators give rise to combinatorial pregeometries i. A set M with the trivial closure operator cl(x) = X. ii. A vector space V over a field F with cl(x) = Span(X). 1

2 iii. An algebraically closed field with the algebraic closure operator cl(k) = K alg. Many of the phenomena we are familiar with from the examples above, e.g. linear independence and linear dimension, can be generalized to any combinatorial pregeometry. Independence: A point a is said to depend on X if a cl(x). A set X is said to be independent if whenever a X, then a does not depend on X \ {a}. For Y X, Y is said to be a base for X if Y is independent and X cl(y ). Dimension: Define r(x), the rank of a set X, to be the cardinality of any base for X. This does not depend on the choice of the base. Proposition 2.4. If Y 1, Y 2 are bases for X, then Y 1 = Y 2. Proof. We prove by induction. Enumerate Y 1 = {a i : i < Y 1 }. For some n < Y 1, denoting A n = {a i : i < n}, assume that there is an injection f <n : A n Y 2 such that B := A n (Y 2 \ f <n [A n ]) is a base for X. Since a n cl(b), there is some B 0 fin B, minimal under inclusion, such that a n cl(b 0 ). As a n / cl(a n ), there is some y B 0 \ A n. By exchange, y B 0 := (B 0 \{y}) {a n }. Moreover, cl(b 0 ) = cl(b 0). In particular, cl(ab 0 ) = cl(ab 0) for any set A. Thus, letting B = (B \ {y}) {a n }, we have that cl(b ) = X. So B is a base for X. Proceed inductively by extending f <n to f n = f <n {(a n, y)}. Taking the ascending union of the functions we have constructed, we get an injection f : Y 1 Y 2 such that Y 1 (Y \ f[y 1 ]) is a base for X (note that this assertion uses finite character). By independence, it must be that (Y \f[y 1 ]) = and f is bijective. Corollary 2.5. The following are equivalent: 1. B is a base for X 2. B is a maximal independent subset of X 3. B is a minimal subset of X such that X cl(b). Observation 2.6. A combinatorial pregeometry (M, cl) is uniquely determined by either of i. Its collection of finite independent subsets ii. The restriction of its rank function to finite sets For the first item, note that a cl(x) if and only if there is some independent X 0 fin X such that X 0 a is not independent. For the second, note a finite set X is independent if and only if r(x) = X. One can define the notion of a combinatorial pregeometry by imposing conditions on its declared collection of independent sets. For I P(M) consider the following axioms: 2

3 I1. I I2. If Y X and X I, then Y I I3. Whenever X, Y I with Y < X, then there is some a X \ Y such that Y a I. I4. For any X M, X is an element of I if and only if every X 0 fin X is an element of I. Similarly, combinatorial pregeometries can be defined via rank functions. For r : P(M) N { } consider the following axioms: R1. For all X M, r(x) X R2. For all X M and a M r(x) r(xa) r(x) + 1 R3. For all X, Y M, (Submodular) r(x Y ) + r(x Y ) r(x) + r(y ) R4. If X M is such that r(x 0 ) = X 0 for any X 0 fin X, then r(x) = X. Let us show the equivalence of all three definitions. Lemma 2.7. If cl : P(M) P(M) satisfies C1-C5, then I, the collection of independent sets according to cl, satisfies I1-I4. Proof. Axioms I1-I2 clearly hold by definition of I. Axiom I4 immediately follows from C5. We show that I3 holds. Let X, Y I be such that Y < X, and assume for a contradiction that there is no a X \ Y such that Y a I. Fix some a X \ Y. For any b Y, if b cl(y a \ {b}), then by Y I and exchange we have a cl(y ). Since Y a / I, by what we have shown it must be that a cl(y ). As a was arbitrary, X cl(y ), so cl(x) = cl(y ). So X, Y are bases for the same set and as we have shown previously Y = X, in contradiction. Lemma 2.8. Let I P(M) be a collection satisfying I1-I4. For every X let r(x) = sup{ X : X P(X) I}. Then r satisfies axioms R1-R4. Proof. Axioms R1-R2 clearly hold by definition of r. If X is a set as in R4, then I4 guarantees that X I, and so r(x) = X. We show that R3 holds. First, observe that I3 guarantees that there is always some X P(X) I such that r(x) = X. Taking a sequence (X i ) i<r(x) of sets X i P(X) I with sup{ X i : i < r(x)}, by iterating I3 we may assume that the sequence is ascending, and so i<r(x) X i P(X) I. 3

4 Choose I 0 P(X Y ) I such that I 0 = r(x). By I3, choose I 1 P(X) I extending I 0 with I 1 = r(x). Similarly, choose I 2 P(X Y ) I extending I 1 with I 2 = r(x Y ). So r(x Y ) + r(x Y ) = I 2 + I 0 = I 1 + (I 2 \ I 1 ) I 0 I 1 + I 2 = r(x) + r(y ) Lemma 2.9. Let r : P(M) N { } satisfy axioms R1-R4. For every X M let cl(x) = {a M : X 0 fin X such that r(x 0 a) = r(x 0 )}. Then cl : P(M) P(M) satisfies axioms C1-C5. Proof. Axiom C5 is by the definition of cl. Axioms C1-C2 are easy to prove. Observe that for any X Y M, iterating R2 gives r(x) r(y ). We show C3. Let a cl(cl(x)), and choose some B := {b 1,..., b n } fin cl(x) such that r(ab) = r(b). We may assume a / B. For each i n choose some Y i fin X such that r(y i b i ) = r(y i ). Let Y = n i=1 Y i. Without loss of generality, by reordering, assume B Y = {b 1,..., b j }, for j = B Y. Then by submodularity, for any j < i n, r(y b i ) + r(y i ) r(y ) + r(y i b i ). So r(y b i ) r(y ) and by R2 equality holds. Again by submodularity r(y b j... b i ) + r(y ) r(y b j... b i 1 ) + r(y b i ) hence r(y b j... b i ) r(y b j... b i 1 ) and by R2 equality holds. Since this holds for all j < i n, we get r(y B) = r(y ). Another application of submodularity yields r(y Ba) + r(b) r(y B) + r(ba) so r(y Ba) r(y ). But also r(y ) r(y a) r(y Ba), so r(y a) = r(y ) and a cl(x). We show C4. Let a cl(xb) \ cl(x). It cannot be that b cl(x), since then by C3 we d have a cl(x). Let X 0 fin X be such that r(x 0 ba) = r(x 0 b). Since a, b / cl(x 0 ), r(x 0 a) = r(x 0 b) = r(x 0 ) + 1. So r(x 0 ab) = r(x 0 a) and b cl(xa). Remark The axioms C5, I4, R4 are only relevant in the case of a matroid of infinite rank, and they guarantee its finite character. The axiom sets C1-C4, I1-I3, R1-R3 are equivalent (and sufficient) for matroids of finite rank. We may think of a combinatorial pregeometry (M, cl) as a first order structure in the language L PG = {I n : n ω} by interpreting I i as the set of independent n-tuples of elements of M. An isormorphism of combinatorial pregeometries is an isomorphism between their first order representations. By what we have shown, it suffices to show that a bijection respects either the independent subsets, the rank function, or the closure operator. 4

5 Definition Say that a combinatorial pregeometry (M, cl) is a combinatorial geometry if every point in M is closed. i.e. cl(x) = {x} for any x M. Remark For convenience, from now on omit the combinatorial from combinatorial pregeometry and combinatorial geometry. To each pregeometry (M, cl) there is a canonically associated geometry. Denote M = M \cl( ) and define the equivalence relation x y cl(x) = cl(y) on the elements of M. For any X M let cl ({[x] : x X}) = {[y] : y cl(x) M }. Then (M, cl ) is the geometry gotten from M by taking every closed set of rank 1 to be a point, and removing all points of rank 0. This process is analogous to the construction of the projective space P n (F ) from the vector space F n+1 over F. Definition Say that a pregeometry (M, cl) is n-trivial 1, if n is maximal such that every subset of cardinality n or less is closed. If no such n exists because every set is closed in (M, cl) is closed, say that (M, cl) is trivial. With the definition of n-triviality, we can redefine a geometry as a pregeometry that is n-trivial for some n > 0. The above association of a geometry to a pregeometry can be seen as a two-staged process. First we associate canonically to an arbitrary pregeometry a 0-trivial pregeometry by removing all the dependent points. Then, to the resulting 0-trivial pregeometry we associate canonically a 1-trivial pregeometry (geometry) by replacing each closed set of rank 1 with a single point. Observe that the first stage cannot be skipped, since then we are left with a dependent point (the closure of the empty set). Observation If two pregeometries (M 1, cl 1 ), (M 2, cl 2 ) are such that cl i (X) is countably infinite for any X M i, and their associated geometries are isomorphic, then (M 1, cl 1 ) = (M 2, cl 2 ). Question Is there a canonical procedure that associates to each 1-trivial geometry a 2-trivial geometry? Namely, a canonical association such that if (M 1, cl 1 ) and (M 2, cl 2 ) are geometries with isomorphic associated 2-trivial geometries according to this procedure, and every closed set of rank 2 in either pregeometry is countably infinite, then (M 1, cl 1 ) = (M 2, cl 2 ). Definition For (M, cl) a pregeometry and A M, define the localization of (M, cl) in A to be to be the pregeometry (M, cl A ) where cl A (X) = cl(a X). Example Let A be some affine space over a field F. The affine span operator (the affine span of a set of vectors S is the collection of linear combinations s S α s s such that s S α s = 1) is a closure operator defining a geometry on A. Localizing this geometry at any one point produces the pregeometry of a vector space over F of dimension n 1, where n is the dimension of A. Localizing by a point essentially makes that point into the origin. 1 If you are familiar with the notion of a trivial pregeometry, we will call these disintegrated or degenerate 5

6 Definition Say that pregeometries (M 1, cl 1 ), (M 2, cl 2 ) are locally isomorphic if there exist finite sets A i M i such that (M 1, cl 1 A 1 ) = (M 2, cl 2 A 2 ). 3 The algebraic closure operator in minimal structures We wish to see how combinatorial pregeometries arise naturally in model theory. Definition 3.1. Fix some first order L-structure M with universe M. For each ϕ(x) L(M) (L-formulas with parameters from M) say that ϕ(x) is an algebraic formula if there are only finitely many a M such that M = ϕ(a). Say that a is algebraic over A M if there is some algebraic formula ϕ(x) L(A) such that M = ϕ(a). For every X M define acl M (X), the algebraic closure of X in M to be the set of elements algebraic over X. Exercise 3.2. In any structure M, the operator acl M : P(M) P(M) satisfies axioms C1-C3 and C5. Hint: ϕ(x) has exactly k solutions is expressible in first order logic. Example 3.3. Let us see that C4 need not necessarily hold. Let G be the countable ω-regular connected tree. Then acl G (xy) is the set of vertices forming the unique path between x and y. Let (x 1, x 2, x 3 ) be a path in G, then x 2 acl G (x 1 x 3 ) \ acl G (x 1 ), but x 3 / acl G (x 1 x 2 ). Definition 3.4. Say that a model M is minimal if for any ϕ(x) L(M), either ϕ(x) is algebraic or ϕ(x) is algebraic. Equivalently, every definable set is either finite or cofinite in M. Say that a model (a theory) is strongly minimal if every model of T h(m) is minimal. Lemma 3.5. If M is minimal, then acl := acl M satisfies C4. Proof. Let a acl(ab) \ acl(a), note that this implies a / acl(a). Then there is some formula ϕ(x, y) L(A) such that a ϕ(m, b) and ϕ(m, b) = k for some k N. Let ψ(y) be the L(A)-formula stating that ϕ(m, y) = k. As b / acl(a), it must be that ψ(m) is cofinite. For each c M consider the definable set D c = {y M : ϕ(c, y) ψ(y)}. Then b D a, and so if D a is finite, then b acl(aa). So we may assume that D a is cofinite, hence M \ D a l for some natural fixed l. Consider now the A-definable set E = {x M : M \ D x l}, that is the set of x M such that there are at most l solutions to (ϕ(x, y) ψ(y)). Since a / acl(x), the set E must be cofinite. In particular, E > k, so choose some distinct a 1,..., a k+1 E. For each i k+1, the set D ai is cofinite, hence D = k+1 i=1 D a i is cofinite, and in particular non-empty. Let d D, then k+1 i=1 ϕ(a i, d). But this is a contradiction to ψ(d), which is asserted by d D ai. 6

7 Remark 3.6. In strongly minimal structures, the rank function associated to the acl operator is exactly the Morley Rank. Remark 3.7. In the setting of a minimal structure, localizing the pregeometry in a set A is synonymous with adding the parameter set A as constants to the language. The examples of Exercise 2.3 are all strongly minimal sets. The pregeometries of these examples increase in complexity, in a quantifiable way. Definition 3.8. i. Say that a pregeometry is disintegrated or degenerate if its associated geometry is trivial. Equivalently, cl(x) = x X cl(x) for every X. ii. Say that a pregeometry is modular if for any closed X, Y r(x Y ) = r(x) + r(y ) r(x Y ) iii. Say that a pregeometry is locally modular if its localization by any one point is modular An example of a strongly minimal theory with a disintegrated pregeometry is the theory of Z with the successor function s, or similarly the theory of an infinite path in the language of graphs. The equality in the definition of modularity is precisely the dimension theorem of linear algebra. The theory of a vector space over a fixed field has a modular pregeometry. As in Example 2.17, an affine space has a locally modular pregeometry. Fact 3.9. The pregeometry of an algebraically closed field of infinite transcendence degree is not locally modular. Maybe-an-example: Consider C[x, y, z] with x, y, z transcendental over each other. Look at the sets {x, y}, {z, x(y + z)}. Zilber s trichotomy conjecture Zilber famously conjectured that pregeometries of strongly minimal structures come in one three distinct flavours of increasing complexity 2 : 1. Disintegrated (essentially binary, or less) 2. Locally modular (essentially a linear space) 3. Field-like (essentially an algebraically closed field) The guiding principle is that geometrical complexity comes from algebraic complexity. This is where Hrushovski comes in: 2 Disclaimer: This is a very simplistic, inaccurate statement of the conjecture. It is purposefully not made precise, as this formulation suits our needs. 7

8 Theorem 3.10 (Hrushovski). There exists a strongly minimal structure not interpreting an infinite group, whose geometry is not locally modular (in particular not disintegrated). In the next few sections we will cover the construction of such a structure. 4 Hrushovski s construction method The hypergraph δ Notation. A hypergraph (V, E) is a set of verices V and an arbitrary set of finite edges E Fin V. For a hypergraph A = (V, E), we often (always) abuse notation and write A to mean the set of vertices of A. Write R A for the set of edges of A and write r(a) := R A. If B A, write r(a/b) := R A \ R B. Definition 4.1. For a finite hypergraph A define δ(a) := A r(a) For A B such that B \ A is finite, write δ(b/a) := B \ A r(b/a) where if B is finite this equals δ(b) δ(a). If A, B D, write δ(b/a) := δ(b A/A). Observation 4.2. If A, B D then δ(b/a) δ(b/a B), i.e. δ is submodular. Proof. Observe that R B R A = R A B, so R B \ R A B R A B \ R A. Also, (A B) \ A = B \ A = B \ (A B). Therefore, δ(b/a) = B A \ A r(b A/A) B \ A B r(b/a B) = δ(b/a B) Note that in the above observation equality holds if and only if R A B = R A R B. Remark 4.3. The next few portions we will do on arbitrary predimension functions, but there is no real harm in always assuming δ is the function defined above. 8

9 Predimension Definition 4.4. For a class of finite structures C closed under isomorphism and substructures, say that δ : C Z is a predimension function for C if 1. δ( ) = 0 2. δ(x) X 3. δ is preserved under isomorphism 4. δ is submodular Lemma 4.5. Let A be some structure and let δ be an integer valued submodular function defined on the age of A. Define for each B fin A: d(b) = inf{δ(x) : B X fin A} Then d is submodular. If δ is a predimension function, then R1 R3 hold for d. If additionally δ only takes non-negative values, then d is the rank function of a pregeometry. Proof. Let X 1, X 2 fin A, we may assume d(x 1 X 2 ) >. Choose X i fin A realizing d(x i ). Then X 1 X 2 X 1 X 2 and X 1 X 2 X 1 X 2. Hence, d(x 1 X 2 ) δ( X 1 X 2 ) and d(x 1 X 2 ) δ( X 1 X 2 ). So d(x 1 X 2 ) + d(x 1 X 2 ) δ( X 1 X 2 ) + δ( X 1 X 2 ) δ( X 1 ) + δ( X 2 ) = d(x 1 ) + d(x 2 ) For the additional part, assume that δ is a predimension function on age(a). Then d(x) δ(x) X, so by submodularity d(xa) d(x) + 1, and by definition d(x) d(xa). Lastly, if δ only takes non-negative values, then the same is true of d. Self-sufficiency Fix some class of finite structures C closed under isomorphism and substructures and fix δ a predimension function for C. Denote by C the class of all countable structures M with age(m) C. Assume that whenever X M C then d M (X) >. Definition 4.6. For N M C, say that N M if for every X fin M, δ(x/x N) 0. Observation 4.7. For N fin M, the following are equivalent: 1. N M 2. δ(n) = d M (N) 3. For every N X fin M, δ(x/n) 0. 9

10 Proof. 1 2: If δ(n) d M (N) then δ(n) > d M (N). So there is N X fin M with δ(x) < δ(n), hence δ(x/x N) = δ(x/n) < : If δ(x/n) < 0 then d M (N) δ(x) < δ(n). 3 1: By submodularity δ(x N/N) δ(x/x N), so if the right is negative, the same is true for the left. Lemma 4.8. N M if and only if d N = d M P(N). Proof. Assume N M, then δ(x/x N) < 0. Choose some X N Y N realizing δ(y ) = d N (X N), so Y N. By submodularity 0 > δ(x/x N) δ(x Y/Y ), so d M (Y ) < d N (Y ). Assume d N (X) d M (X) for some finite X, then for Y a realization of d N (X), δ(y/y N) < 0. Corollary 4.9. The relation is transitive. Observation N M if and only if whenever Y M, then Y N Y. Corollary If X, Y M then X Y M. Proof. If X M, then X Y Y. If additionally Y M, by transitivity X Y M. Now we see that whenever X M C, there is a unique minimal (under inclusion) X M containing X. Call X the self-sufficient closure of X (not to be confused with the geometric closure). Note that if X is finite, then also X is finite. Definition A strong-embedding is an embedding f : N M such that f[n] M. Since δ is preserved under isomorphism, every isomorphism is a strong embedding. By transitivity of, the strong embeddings are closed under composition. Flatness Recall that our goal is to find a strongly minimal structure whose geometry does not fall into Zilber s classification. In order to do that, we define the property of flatness. We will see that a strongly minimal structure whose acl-pregeometry is flat, cannot interpret an infinite group, i.e. not (essentially) a vector space nor ACF. Notation. Whenever we list E 1,..., E k sets in some ambient pregeometry (M, cl M ): For any s [k] which is not empty, E s = i s E i. E = k i=1 E i Est M ({E 1,..., E k }) = =s [k] ( 1) s +1 d M (E s ) 10

11 Diff M ({E 1,..., E k }) = s [k] ( 1) s +1 d M (E s ) We omit M if it is clear from context. Definition Say that a pregeometry (M, cl) is flat if whenever E 1,... E k are closed of finite dimension, then Diff M ({E 1,..., E k }) 0. Proposition If M is a saturated strongly minimal structure whose aclpregeometry is flat, then any group interpretable in M is finite. Proof. Assume for a contradiction that G is an infinite group interpreted in M. Denote the dimension of G (Morley rank) by g. Let a 1, a 2, a 3 be generic elements of G. For i = 1, 2, 3 let E i = cl({a 1, a 2, a 3 } \ {a i }) and let E 4 = cl(a 1 1 a 2, a 1 1 a 3). Then the dimension of the union is 3, the dimension of each E i is 2, the dimension of each intersection E i E j is 1, and intersection of three of the E i is empty. By flatness, 0 Diff({E 1,..., E 4 }) = (4 2g 6 g) 3g = g So g = 0 in contradiction to G being infinite. We will show that for the case of hypergraphs and δ of before, the pregeometries that arise are flat. Exercise An intersection of closed sets is closed. Lemma A closed set in M is self-sufficient in M. Proof. If N M then there is some X N such that d N (X) > d M (X). Letting Y realize d M (X), there is some a Y \ N. So d M (Xa) = d(x) but a / X. Definition Define C to be the class of finite hypergraphs A with A. By Lemma 4.5, for every M C the d M defined using delta is the rank of a predimension. Proposition For any M C, the pregeometry given by d M is flat. Proof. Let E 1,..., E k be closed subsets. For each = s [k] let B s be a base for E s, and let B be the self-sufficient closure of s [k] B s in M. Let F s = B E s and note δ(f s ) = d(e s ), and finally denote F = k i=1 F i. Est({E 1,..., E k }) = ( 1) s +1 δ(f s ) =s [k] = =s [k] ( 1) s +1 F s F R F = δ(f) =s [k] Since F contains a base for E, in particular δ(f) d(e ). ( 1) s +1 R Fs 11

12 Remark In the above proof we get equality if and only if R E k = i=1 REi and E M. So in order to refute Zilber s conjecture, it will suffice to come up with a hypergraph that is strongly minimal such that its Morley rank coincides with the dimension d. Fraïssé s Theorem For some language L, fix some class of finite L-structures C, and a class of distinguished embeddings of L-structures, closed under isomorphism and composition, such that if A C then there is some A C with A A. Definition For (C, ), define the following properties: Hereditary Property If B C and A B, then A C. Joint Embedding Property If A, B C, then there is some C C such that A, B C. Amalgamation Property If A B 1, B 2 are in C, then there is some D C and strong embeddings f i : B i D such that f[b i ] D and f 1 A = f 2 A. If (C, ) has HP, JEP and AP, then we say it is an amalgamation class. Remark AP implies JEP if there is a prime structure in C, embedding into any element of C. This is not always the case, for example consider the class of countable ACF, which has AP but not JEP (take fields of different characteristics). Definition Say that M is a generic structure for (C, ) if age (M) := {A M} = C, whenever A fin M there is some A A M finite, and Whenever A M is finite and A B C, there exists some strong embedding f : B M such that f A = Id. Proposition If M 1, M 2 are countable generic structures for (C, ), then any finite partial isomorphism f : A 1 A 2 with A i M i extends to an isomorphism between M 1 and M 2. In particular, if C then there is at most one countable (up to isomorphism) generic structure for (C, ). Proof. We show that f can be extended by any one point b 1 M 1 and proceed by back-and-forth. Let B M 1 be finite such that A 1 b 1 B 1, In particular B 1 C. Letting B 2 be the structure B 1 after renaming the elements of A 1 using f, we have A 2 B 2. By genericness of M 2 there is some strong embedding g : B 2 M 2 over A 2. Extending f by g (B 2 \ A 2 ), we are done. Theorem 4.24 (Fraïssé). If (C, ) is a countable (up to isomorphism) amalgamation class with HP,JEP and AP, then there exists a generic model for (C, ). 12

13 Proof. Let M be a countable infinite set this will end up being our universe. Let A be a countable subset of C, closed under substructures and containing a set of representatives of the countably many isomorphism classes of C. Let F = {f : A M : A A} and note that it is countable. Consider T, the family of tuples (f, A, B) where A B A and f F with dom(f) = A. As T F A A, T it is also countable. Let {(f i, A i, B i ) : i ω} be an enumeration of T such that each tuple of T is repeated infinitely many times. We inductively build an ascending chain of structures M 0 M 1 M 2... such thatm i A for every i N. Given M i, if f i is not a strong embedding of A i into M i, by JEP choose some M i+1 C to which both M i and B i strongly embed. Otherwise, by AP choose some D C with strong embeddings g 1 : M i D and g 2 : B i D such that g 1 f i = g 2 A. Without loss of generality, we may assume that g 1 is the identity, hence M i D. Since M \ M i is infinite, we may assume that D M \ M i. Define M i+1 = D. Choose arbitrarily some M 0 C and produce M = i<ω M i. We need to check that 1. M has the extension property 2. whenever A fin M there exists some finite A A M 3. age (M) = C. Assume A M and A B C, then there is some large enough i < ω such that A M i and (f i, A i, B i ) is such that A i = A, B i = B. Then by construction B strongly embeds into M i+1, and so into M (1). Whenever A fin M, there is some i < ω such that A M i M (2). In particular, if A M then A M i C so by HP A C. For the other direction of inclusion, for any B C there is some i < ω such that B i = B, so by construction B embeds strongly into M i+1 M (3). Remark If you are careful, the theorem will also works when replacing finite by finitely generated and all the structures are countable. Exercise For M the countable generic structure for C, if A M is finite and A N C, then there is a strong embedding of N into M over A. Exercise Given a class C of relational structures and a notion of strong embedding, decide whether (C, ) is an amalgamation class and, if it is, describe its generic structure 1. The class of all finite graphs with =. 2. The class of all finite trees (forests) with A B if for any b B \ A there is at most one a A such that (a, b) is an edge in B. 3. The class of all finite linear orders with =. 4. The class of all finite linear orders with A B if A is an interval in B. 13

14 Non-collapsed construction We now return to C, the class of hypergraphs with A and the δ we defined for that class. Definition For hypergraphs B 1,..., B k with B i B j = A for all i j, define their free join over A to be the hypergraph with vertex set k i=1 B i and edges k i=1 RBi. Observation If D is the free join of B 1,..., B k over A, then for any X D k δ(x/x A) = δ(x B i /X A) i=1 Corollary The class (C, ) has AP. Proof. Let A C strongly embed into B 1, B 2 C. By renaming elements we may assume A B 1, B 2, B 1 B 2 = A. Then the last observation, letting D be the free join of B 1, B 2 over A we have that B 1, B 2 D. In particular, since B 1 D and B 1 C, also D C. By Fraïssé s Theorem, there is a unique (up to isomorphism) countable generic structures M C such that whenever A M, A B C, then B embeds into M over A. We call this construction Hrushovski s non-collapsed construction. It is not strongly minimal, but it is very similar to the strongly minimal (collapsed) version we will soon see. Lemma Every countable hypergraph N for which M1. age(n) = C M2. Whenever A fin N and A B C, then there is an embedding of B into N over A. M3. There is an infinite independent set under d N then N is a generic structure for C. Proof. We only need to show self-sufficient extension. Let A N and A B C. Let X be a basis of B such that X A is a basis of A. Let n := X \ A and choose arbitrarily b 1,..., b n N independent over A in N. By M2 we may embed B into N over Ab 1... b n, and this must be a strong embedding because d N (B) X and δ(b) = X. Corollary Every countable elementary extension of M is isomorphic to M. In particular, M is saturated. Proof. The properties M1-M3 hold for M, and they are all preserved under elementary extensions. M1-M2 are given by T h(m), whereas M3 is a realized 14

15 ω-type. Thus, an elementary extension is also a generic for C, so isomorphic to M. To see that M is saturated let p(x) be some type over a finite set A. We may assume that A M by taking its self-sufficient closure. Then p(x) is realized by b in some countable elementary extension M M. The identity on A is a finite partial isomorphism between strong substructures of M and M, so extends to an isomorphism f : M M. Then f(b) M realizes the type p(x). Proposition The theory of M has quantifier elimination to the level of boolean combinations of existential formulas Proof. Let A 1, A 2 M be such that for any existential formula ϕ( x), M = ϕ(a 1 ) ϕ(a 2 ). The isomorphism type of the self-sufficient closure of A i is the ismorphism type of the largest hypergraph A i B i fin M such that δ(b i /A i ) < 0 and for any A i X B i, δ(x/a i ) > δ(b i /A i ). So the self-sufficient closures of A 1 and A 2, say Ā1 and Ā2, are isomorphic strong substructures of M, so there is some f automorphism of M with f(ā1) = Ā2. In particular, f(a 1 ) = A 2, so tp M (A 1 ) = tp M (A 2 ). As M is saturated, this is enough to prove the statement. The collapse What we d like to do now, is construct a structure similar to M, that is strongly minimal, with Morley Rank being d. So in other words, dependent means algebraic. So for each minimal isomorphism type of d-dependency, we will assign a uniform bound. Definition For A B finite, say that B \ A is simply algebraic over A if: δ(b/a) = 0 For any A X B, δ(x/a) > 0. Say that B \ A is minimally simply algebraic over A if there is no A A such that B \ A is simply algebraic over A. Example Here s a non-trivial example of A B such that B \ A is minimally simply algebraic over A. Let A = {a 1, a 2, a 3 }, R A = {{a 1, a 2, a 3 }}. Let B = A {b 1,..., b 4 }, R B = R A {{a i, b i, b i+1 } : i 3} {{b 1, a 2, b 4 }}. It is easy to extend this example so that B is of any finite size. Lemma If B 1,..., B n are simply algebraic over A and distinct such that A A n i=1 B i, then the B i are pairwise disjoint. Moreover, A n i=1 B i is a free join over A. 15

16 Proof. Denote B 0 := B 1 B 2. As δ(b i /AB 0 ) = δ(b 0 /A), we have δ(b 1 B 2 /AB 0 ) = δ(b 1 /AB 2 ) + δ(b 2 /AB 0 ) δ(b 1 /AB 0 ) + δ(b 2 /AB 0 ) = 2δ(B 0 /A). So δ(b 1 B 2 /A) δ(b 0 /A). If B 0, then by simple algebraicity of B 1 over A, δ(b 0 /A) > 0. This will contradict A B 1 B 2. Exercise Show that if B is simply algebraic over A, then B is either contained in the self-sufficient closure of A or disjoint from it. Definition Let A M C and A B C. The multiplicity of B over A in M is the maximal number of disjoint realizations of atp(b/a) in D. Call a function µ : C C N { } a µ-function or a multiplicity function if it is preserved under isomorphism, i.e., if A i B i, B 1 = B2 such that the restriction to A 1, A 2 is also an isomorphism, then µ(a 1, B 1 ) = µ(a 2, B 2 ). Definition Let C µ be the class of finite hypergraphs A C such that whenever F C A with C \ F minimally simply algebraic over F, then the multiplicity of C over F in A is at most µ(f, C). Clearly C µ has HP and JEP for any µ. It is not clear exactly for which µ amalgamation works. We will see that if µ is large enough, things work out. The setup: Fix some A 1, A 2 C, denote A 0 := A 1 A 2, and let D be the free join of A 1, A 2 over A 0. We want to see how multiplicity behaves in a a free join. Keep in mind that later we will expect A 0 A 1, A 2, since we are doing self-sufficient amalgamation. Later, we will see it is sufficient to assume that either A 1 \ A 2 or A 2 \ A 0 is simply algebraic over A 0. Fix some F D and C D minimally simply algebraic over F, and let C 1,..., C k be all the realizations of atp(c/f ) in D. For every X D, denote X i = X A i. Note that X is a free join of X 1 and X 2 over X 0. We will categorize the copies of C according to which parts of the Venndiagram of D they intersect. Label the parts of the diagram A 0, A 1 \ A 0, A 2 \A 0 by 0,1,2 respectively. Say that C i is a type-ijk copy if it intersects the parts of the diagram listed in ijk. e.g., if C i is type-01, then C i 0, C i 1\C i 0, and C i 2 \ C i 0 =. We will make a series of observation regarding different possible configurations of F and the C i. Claim 1. It cannot be that C is type-12. Proof. As D is a free join, we d have δ(c 1 /F C 2 ) = δ(c 1 /F ). But C is simply algebraic over F, so δ(c 1 /F C 2 ) = δ(c 2 /F ) < 0 and δ(c 1 /F ) > 0. Claim 2. If C is type-1, then F A 1. The statement is symmetric in 1 and 2. Proof. Since D is a free join and C A 2 =, we have δ(c/f 1 ) = δ(c/f ). But C is minimally simply algebraic over F, so F = F 1. 16

17 Claim 3. Let b 1 the number of type-02/012 copies of C, and assume these are exactly C 1,..., C b. Then δ(c 1... C b /A 1 ) + b 1 δ(f 2 /A 0 ). In particular, if A 0 A 2, then b 1 δ(f 2 /A 0 ). Proof. For every such C i, by simple algebraicity over F, δ(c i /F C i 1) < 0. By submodularity, this gives δ(c i /F A 1 ) δ(c i /F C i 1) < 0. Applying submodularity for all bad C i at once, we have δ(c 1... C b /F A 1 ) b δ(c i /F A 1 ) b 1. i=1 As D is a free join, δ(f/a 1 ) = δ(f 2 /A 0 ). Adding δ(f/a 1 ) + b 1 to both sides of the inequality above, we get the inequality of the statement. For the additional part, note that for any X, δ(x/a 1 ) = δ(x A 2 /A 0 ), because D is a free join. So A 0 A 2 implies δ(c 1... C b /A 1 ) 0. Claim 4. If F A 1, denoting by b 2 the number of i such that C i A 1, we have b 2 δ(f 2 /F 0 ) δ(f 2 /A 0 ) Proof. For every C i A 1, since F 1 F and C i is minimally simply algebraic over F, δ(c i /F 1 ) > δ(c i /F ). This means r(c i /F 1 ) < r(c i /F ), so there exists some relation r i involving both an element from C i and an element from F 2 \ F 0. Since D is a free join, all the elements of C i appearing in r i must come from C i 0. By disjointedness of the C i, if i j then r i r j. Hence, As a free join, δ(f 2 /F 1 ) = δ(f 2 /F 0 ). δ(f 2 /A 0 ) δ(f 2 /F 1 ) b 2. Proposition If A 0 A 2, one of the following conditions holds: 1. Everything happens inside A i for some i = 1, 2. i.e., F, C 1,..., C k A i. 2. F A 0 and there is some type-2 copy of C. 3. There are no type-2 copies and k δ(f ). 4. There is some type-2 copy of C, and there is some type-01/012 C i such that δ(c i 1/C i 0F 0 ) < 0. In particular, A 0 A 1. Proof. Assume condition 1 does not hold. Consider the case F A 1. As condition 1 does not hold, choose some C i A 1. By claims 1,3 and the fact δ(f/a 1 ) = 0, it must be that C i is type-2. By Claim 2, F A 2 so in particular F A 0, and condition 2 holds. So assume from now that F A 1. Assume there exists some type-2 copy of C. Then F A 2, by Claim 2. Condition 1 does not hold, so choose C i such that C i A 2. As F A 1, by Claim 2 C i is not type-1, so it is either type-01 or type-012. In particular, by simple algebraicity, δ(c1/c i 2F i ) < 0. As D is a free join, δ(c1/c i 2F i ) = δ(c1/c i 0F i 0 ). Condition 4 holds. So assume there are no type-2 copies of C. 17

18 Then we are left only with type-02/012 copies, of which there are at most b 1 δ(f 2 /A 0 ), and type-0/01 copies, of which there are at most b 2 δ(f 2 /F 0 ) δ(f 2 /A 0 ). Over all, k δ(f 2 /F 0 ) δ(f ). Corollary Let A 0 A 1 C µ and A 2 \ A 0 simply algebraic over A 0, where µ(f, C) δ(f ) for any F, C. Then the free join of A 1 and A 2 over A 0 is in C µ, unless A 2 \ A 0 is minimally simply algebraic over some F A 0 and the multiplicity of A 2 \ A 0 over F in A 1 is µ(f, A 2 \ A 0 ). Proof. Let D be the free join of A 1 and A 2 over A 0. Let F, C 1,..., C k D be such that C 1 is minimally simply algebraic over F and C i = F C j for all i, j k. We know that one of the conditions of the above proposition must hold. By A 0 A 1, we know that condition 4 fails. If condition 1 holds, then k µ(f, C 1 ) since A i C µ. If condition 3 holds, then by choice of µ we are okay. Then assume condition 2 holds F A 0 and for some i k C := C k A 2 \ A 0. Since C is simply minimally algebraic over F A 0, A 0 A 0 C, A 0 C =, C is simply algebraic over A 0. So it must be that A 2 \ A 0 = C. The only way for k > µ(f, C) is to have k 1 = µ(f, C) copies of C in A 1. Theorem If µ is a multiplicity function such that µ(a, B) δ(a), then C µ has AP with respect to. Proof. We prove by induction on A 2 \ A 0. Case 0: A 2 \ A 0 = {x} and δ(a 2 ) > δ(a 0 ). In the free join, the point x is not involved in any instance of minimal simple algebraicity. Case 1: There exists some A 0 X A 2 such that X A 2. By induction, amalgamate A 1 with X over A 0 to receive D. As X strongly embeds into D and into A 2, again by induction, amalgamate D with A 2 over X to receive D. Case 2: Cases 0, 1 fail. Then A 2 \ A 0 is simply algebraic over A 0. By Corollary 4.41, if the free join of A 1 and A 2 is not in C µ, then for F A over which A 2 \A 0 is minimally simply algebraic, in A 1 there are µ(f, A 2 \A 0 ) copies of A 2 \A 0. By Exercise 4.37, since A 0 A 1, each of these copies is either contained in A 0 or in A 1 \ A 0. It cannot be that all copies are in A 0, for then A 2 will have µ(f, A 2 \ A 0 ) + 1 copies, in contradiction to A 2 C µ. So there is some copy C A 1 \ A 0. Then CA 0 A 1, and by identifying A 2 \ A 0 with C, we can see A 1 C µ as an amalgam of A 1 and A 2 over A 0. For a multiplicity function µ, if C µ has AP, we denote by M µ its generic countable structure. From now on assume that µ only takes integer values (no ), and that µ(a, B) δ(a). We show that the theory of M µ is model complete Lemma Every model of T := T h(m µ ) is existentially closed. i.e., T is model complete and has QE up to existential statements. 18

19 Proof. Fix A, B with B minimally simply algebraic over A. Fix some (F, Q) with Q minimally simply algebraic over F such that F Q AB. Note that there are only finitely many options for F,Q. For every M, some finite hypergraph containing A such that in the free amalgam of B and M over A there are Q 1,..., Q µ(a,b)+1 disjoint copies of Q over F, let T M ( v, A) be the atomic type of Q i M over A. Enumerating over all M, note that there exist only finitely many distinct T M, since these are atomic types on (µ(a, B)+1) Q + A points. Let θ (F,Q) ( x) be the disjunction over all formulas of the form ȳ T M ( x, ȳ) for some M. One should read θ (F,Q) ( x) as saying the reason A cannot be extended freely by a copy of B is that this will introduce too many copies of Q over F. Now let Φ (A,B) ( x) be the disjunction of all θ (F,Q) ( x) for F Q AB. We have seen in Proposition 4.40 that failure of the free amalgam to be in C µ is a result of some Q B having too large a multiplicity over some F AB. So Φ (A,B) ( x) enumerates all the reasons that A cannot be extended freely by a copy of B. So T = x ( A( x) Φ (A,B) ( x) ) where A( x) means x realizes the atomic type of A. Now let P N both be models of T. We wish to show P is existentially closed in N. Let ɛ be quantifier-free with set of parameters A fin P, satisfied by some B N. We may assume ɛ is an atomic type over A pass to DNF and reduce to the conjunctive clause that B satisfies. We may also assume B N \ P by replacing A with A (B P ). Let B B be minimal non-empty such that δ(b /A) 0, if such a B exists. Then B is minimally simply algebraic over some A A. But A, by virtue of P = Φ (A,B )(A ), has exhausted the amount of copies of B it is allowed over it by some reason found in P. This reason is also in N \ B, and N is bound by C µ. So there is no such B. In fact, we have shown that P is closed in N. Then δ(b /A) > 0 for any non-empty B B. By examining Proposition 4.40 we see that the free amalgam of any extension of A and B over A is in C µ. So the existence of a copy of B over Ā in P is guaranteed by T in Mµ one can (strongly) embed a copy of B over the self-sufficient closure of any copy of A, so in particular strongly embed B over any copy of A. Corollary M µ is saturated. Proof. As before (Lemma 4.32), any countable elementary extension of M µ will be generic for C µ. For fun, let s faff about this time around: Let M µ N. Then N C µ, so embeds into M µ. Call the embedded copy N, then by model completeness N M µ, in particular N M µ. Let A N, A B C µ, then B embeds strongly into M µ over A. By existential closedness of N, there is a copy of B over A inside N. Since N contains an infinite independent set, we can make sure the embedding of B into N is strong, with the trick of

20 Lemma In M µ, the algebraic closure operator and the closure operator given by d are equivalent. Proof. Let A M µ be finite and let x cl(a), we will show x acl(a). Let Ax D fin cl(a) with δ(d) = d(a). Choose A B D minimal such that B D. Then B is simply algebraic over A, and therefore algebraic, since every element of B solves an existential equation with at most µ(a, B) solutions in M µ. If x B, we are done. Otherwise, Repeat the process, replacing A with B, until D is exhausted. If A fin M µ (not necessarily strong) and x cl(a), then there is some A A independent such that x cl(a ). Being independent, A M µ so x acl(a ) acl(a). For the converse assume that A M µ and x 1, x 2 / cl(a). Letting Ā be the self-sufficient closure of A, we have Āx i M µ and Āx 1 = Āx 2. So there is an isomorphism of M µ over A taking x 1 to x 2. Therefore, there is a unique type independent over A with infinite orbit, so any point outside cl(a) is not algebraic over A. Corollary M µ is strongly minimal. Proof. There is a unique independent type over A, whose orbit is infinite. Any other type is algebraic over A, so has a finite orbit. Since M µ is saturated, that implies every formula not in the independent type has finitely many realizations. If not, say ϕ is not in the independent type and defines an infinite set, take the type containing ϕ and diagonalizing over all algebraic formulas over A. This type is realized in M µ, not the unique independent type, but also not algebraic, hence not dependent on A. Exercise Going back to M, the non-collapsed construction: Show that if B M is simply algebraic over A M then MR(B/A) = 1. Show that if x depends on A then its Morley Rank over A is finite. In particular, MR(x/A) is the minimal length of a chain of simply algebraic extensions leading up from A to x. Show that the Morley Rank of the generic (independent) type over A is exactly ω. Conclude that M is ω-stable. Remark Note that µ(a, B) > 0 does not guarantee there are any realizations of B over A, even if A is self sufficient. It is possible that B itself already violates µ(f, C) for some F B. Continuum many non-isomorphic (pre)geometries Observation It is enough that µ(f, C) δ(f ) whenever C 2 for C µ to be an amalgamation class. 20

21 Proof. Recalling the conditions of Proposition 4.40, note that if C = 1 then C is type-0/1/2. We need to check that k δ(f ) can be omitted from condition 3 without anything breaking. If there are no type-2 copies, all copies of C are in A 1. If F A 1 then condition 1 holds, so assume F A 1. By Claim 2, all copies of C are type- 0. By simple algebraicity δ(c/f 1 ) > δ(c/f ), so F 2 and C are related, hence δ(c/f 2 ) C 1 = 0 so C is simply algebraic over F 2. By minimality of F, F A 2 and again condition 1 holds. If there is a type-2 copy of C, then by Claim 2 F A 2. If condition 1 doesn t hold, there is a type-1 copy of C, implying F A 0, so condition 2 holds. Exercise In the proof above we used explicitly our definition of δ. Assuming all copies of C are type-0, continue the proof using only that δ is a predimension and C = 1. (this is straightforward, but can be a bit tricky). Definition Fix n. Let C n be the class of finite n-regular hypergraphs A, such that whenever X [A] n, then X A. Observation For A C n, a set X [A] n is dependent if and only if it is an edge. Otherwise, δ(x) = X but d(x) < X, hence X A. C n is the class C νn for the multiplicity function ν such that - ν(f, C) = 0 whenever F n and F C is not an edge - ν(e \ {a}, a) = 1 when E is an edge - ν(f, C) = whenever F > n. The pregeometry of any A C µ is (n 2)-trivial. In particular, if n 3 (and it is), then the pregeometry of any A C µ is a geometry. Remark It may seem from the above observation that setting things to zero does not disturb amalgamation. This is not true. Consider A 1 = {c 1, c 2, c 3, f 1, f 2 }, A 2 = {c 1, c 2, c 4, f 3, f 4 } R 1 = {(c 1, f 1, c 3 ), (c 2, f 2, c 3 )}, R 2 = {(c 1, f 3, c 4 ), (c 2, f 4, c 4 )} Then C = {c 1,..., c 4 } is minimally simply algebraic over F = {f 1,..., f 4 }. Setting µ(f, C) = 0 forbids this configuration, but it forms whenever µ allows edges. Proposition There are continuum many amalgamation classes C µ whose associated (pre)geometries are not isomorphic. Proof. Choose some integer-valued µ such that µ(f, C) = ν(f, C) whenever F n, and µ(f, C) δ(c) otherwise. Then C µ is an amalgamation class with generic structure M µ. 21

22 We know that a set X [M µ ] n is an edge if and only if it is dependent, so the structure M µ can be read off of its pregeometry. Hence, multiplicity functions giving rise to non-isomorphic structures also give rise to non-isomorphic pregeometries. Finding pairs (F i, C i ) i<ω such that µ 1 (F i, C i ) µ 2 (F i, C i ) = µ 1 µ 2 is left as an exercise to the reader. Remark We can vary C, our notion of an acceptable hypergraph, in several ways such that all the proofs we ve done go through: Symmetry: Consider a directed hypergraph where edges are tuples instead of sets. One can also choose an intermediate level of symmetry for every arity for arity n quotient out the n-tuples by a subgroup of S n. Irreflexivity: For the undirected case, one can allow or disallow repetition of elements in the same tuple. Arity: Restrict the arity of the edges of the hypergraph. n-triviality: Only consider hypergraphs whose pregeometry is n-trivial. Colored edges: Have several sets of edges, each representing a different color. (Need to be careful if introducing infinitely many, some things may break) 5 Isomorphism of pregeometries For this section fix (C 1, 1 ) and (C 2, 2 ), two strong amalgamation classes which we will use for general statements. Assume both have finite closures and A i for any A i C i. Omit the subscript from i when it is clear from context. Assume that for any A C i there is a canonically associated pregeometry, invariant under isomorphism. Denote that pregeometry by PG i (A), or PG(A) when i is clear from context. Assume further that if A B C i, then PG i (A) PG i (B). Write PG(C) for the pregeometry of the generic structure for C. Definition 5.1. Say that C 1 C2 if, given structures A i C i such that PG 1 (A 1 ) = PG 2 (A 2 ), Whenever A 1 B 1 C 1, there exist D 1 C 1 and A 2 D 2 C 2 such that PG 1 (D 1 ) = PG 2 (D 2 ) (extending the isomorphism PG(A 1 ) = PG(A 2 )). Write C 1 C 2 if an addition one may always choose D 1 = B 1. Exercise 5.2. Assume that is in all classes and strongly embeds into everything (under all notions of ). Then: 1. Is transitive? 2. Is transitive? 3. C 1 C 2 C3? = C 1 C3 4. C 1 C2 C 3? = C 1 C3 22

23 5. Show that the relation is an equivalence relation such that is well defined on the quotient induces. Proposition 5.3. Assume C 1 C2 and C 2 C1. Let f 0 : PG(A 1 ) PG(A 2 ) be a finite partial isomorphism of pregeometries for A 1 M 1 and A 2 M 2. Then f 0 extends to an isomorphism of pregeometries f : PG(M 1 ) PG(M 2 ). In particular, PG(M 1 ) = PG(M 2 ) Proof. By back and forth. We show the forth direction, with the back being symmetric. Choose arbitrarily some x M 1 and let B 1 be the self-sufficient closure of A 1 x in M 1. Then by C 1 C2 there exist some B 1 D 1 C 1 and A 2 D 2 C 2 such that PG(D 1 ) = PG(D 2 ), extending f 0. As a generic structure, embed D 1 strongly into M 1 over B 1. Similarly, embed D 2 strongly into M 2 over A 2. Since D i M i, we have PG(D i ) PG(M i ). Then we have extended the isomorphism of pregeometries so that x is in the domain. Taking the union of our nested isomorphisms, we have an isomorphism of pregeometries with domain M 1 and image M 2. Since M 1, M 2, we may start with f 0 = to receive PG(M 1 ) = PG(M 2 ). We now go over some variants of the (non-collapsed) construction, and show that the changes do not affect the pregeometry. Fix some natural n. Definition 5.4. C the class of all n-regular undirected (edges are sets of size n) hypergraphs A with A. C the class of all n-regular irreflexive directed (edges are tuples of length n without repeating elements) hypergraphs A with A C the class of all n-regular directed (edges are arbitrary tuples of length n) hypergraphs A with A In all of the above δ is adjusted accordingly: #vertices - #edges. Notation. If A is a structure and X is a subset of the universe of A, write A[X] for the substructure of A induced on X. Lemma 5.5. i. C C r ii. C C Proof. i. Let A 1 B 1 C, A 2 C r such that PG(A 1) = PG(A 2 ). assume the universes of A 1 and A 2 are identical, say the set A. We may Let B 2 be the structure obtained from B 1 by replacing A 1 with A 2. i.e., the universe of B 2 is the universe of B 1, call it B, and R B2 = (R B1 \R A1 ) R A2. Then B 2 is a directed hypergraph, and for any X B δ r (B 2 [X]/A 2 [X A]) = δ (B 1 [X]/A 1 [X A]). 23

24 So A 2 B 2, and PG(B 1 ) = PG(B 2 ) via the identity. ii. Let A 1 B 1 C, A 2 C r such that PG(A 1) = PG(A 2 ). Again assume the universe of A 1, A 2 is A. For each set r R B1 \R A1 choose some ordered r tuple whose elements are exactly those of r. Let B 2 be the directed hypergraph with the same set of vertices as B 1 and set of (directed) edges R A2 {r : r R B1 \ R A1 }. As in the previous item, A 2 B 2 and PG(B 1 ) = PG(B 2 ). Exercise 5.6. Let C Rainbow be the class of all colorful n-regular undirected (an edge carries with it one of countably many colors) hypergraphs A with A. Show that C Rainbow C and C C Rainbow. Showing the converse directions to those of Lemma 5.5 is not so difficult, but requires a bit of technical detail. Also, a weakening to is necessary. Observation 5.7. If C 1 C 2, then {PG(A 1 ) : A 1 C 1 } {PG(A 2 ) : A 2 C 2 }. Just think of A 1 C 1 as extending the empty set, then there is some A 2 C 2 with PG(A 1 ) = PG(A 2 ). Corollary 5.8. C C, C C. Proof. Consider A C with vertex set {a 1,..., a n } and set of edges R A = {(a 1,..., a n ), (a n,..., a 1 )}. Then A = n and d A (A) = n 2. No such structure exists in C, because on n points one can have at most one relation in C. So PG(A) / {PG(A ) : A C }. For the second statement apply the same trick, this time noting that, unless n = 1 (which it is not), for A = a with R A = A n we have A = 1, d A (A) = 0 which cannot happen in C because every set of size < n has no relations on it. Lemma 5.9. Assume (C i, i ) and its associated scheme of pregeometries come from a predimension function δ i (for i = 1, 2). Let B i C i have universe B and let A B be such that B i [A] := A i B i. Assume that PG(A 1 ) = PG(A 2 ). For any X B, denote X i := B i [X], δ i (X) := δ i (X i ) and d i (X) := d i (X i ). Then: 1. If Y B is d 1 -closed in B 1, then δ 1 (Y A) = δ 2 (Y A) 2. If Y B is d 1 -closed in B 1 and δ 1 (Y/Y A) δ 2 (Y/Y A), then for any X B such that cl 1 (X) = Y, it holds that d 1 (X) d 2 (X). 3. If δ 1 (Y/Y A) = δ 2 (Y/Y A) for any d 1 -closed or d 2 -closed Y B, then PG(B 1 ) = PG(B 2 ). Proof. 1. Then Y A is d 1 -closed in A 1, and since PG(A 1 ) = PG(A 2 ) also Y A is d 2 -closed in A 2, with d 1 (Y A) = d 2 (Y A). A closed set is self-sufficient, so A i [Y A] A i and d i (Y A) = δ i (Y A). 24

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set Martin Ziegler Barcelona, July 2011 In [5] E. Hrushovski proved the following theorem: Theorem 0.1 (Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set). There

More information

Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions

Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions David Evans, School of Mathematics, UEA, Norwich, UK Algebra, Combinatorics and Model Theory, Koç University, Istanbul August 2011. ACMT () August 2011

More information

A New Spectrum of Recursive Models Using An Amalgamation Construction

A New Spectrum of Recursive Models Using An Amalgamation Construction A New Spectrum of Recursive Models Using An Amalgamation Construction Uri Andrews September 1, 2010 Abstract We employ an infinite-signature Hrushovski amalgamation construction to yield two results in

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minimal Structures BPGMT 2013 Definition - Strongly Minimal In this talk, when we say a set is definable in a model M, we mean it is definable in the language

More information

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007 Modern Model Theory Begins Theorem (Morley 1965) If a countable first order theory is categorical in one uncountable cardinal it is categorical in all uncountable cardinals. Outline 1 2 3 SELF-CONSCIOUS

More information

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries Marko Djordjevi bstract We prove, by a probabilistic argument, that a class of ω-categorical structures, on which algebraic closure

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Hrushovski s Fusion. A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007

Hrushovski s Fusion. A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007 Hrushovski s Fusion A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007 Abstract We present a detailed and simplified exposition of Hrushovki s fusion of two strongly minimal theories. 1 Introduction

More information

Semimatroids and their Tutte polynomials

Semimatroids and their Tutte polynomials Semimatroids and their Tutte polynomials Federico Ardila Abstract We define and study semimatroids, a class of objects which abstracts the dependence properties of an affine hyperplane arrangement. We

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Charles Steinhorn, Vassar College Katrin Tent, University of Münster CIRM, January 8, 2018 The three lectures Introduction to basic model theory Focus on Definability More

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background. Model Theory II. 80824 22.10.2006-22.01-2007 (not: 17.12) Time: The first meeting will be on SUNDAY, OCT. 22, 10-12, room 209. We will try to make this time change permanent. Please write ehud@math.huji.ac.il

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Pregeometries and minimal types

Pregeometries and minimal types Pregeometries and minimal types Enrique Casanovas Universidad de Barcelona May 9, 2006. Revised November 11, 2008 1 Pregeometries Definition 1.1 Let Ω be a set (more generally, a class) and let cl be a

More information

A MATROID EXTENSION RESULT

A MATROID EXTENSION RESULT A MATROID EXTENSION RESULT JAMES OXLEY Abstract. Adding elements to matroids can be fraught with difficulty. In the Vámos matroid V 8, there are four independent sets X 1, X 2, X 3, and X 4 such that (X

More information

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Gabriel Conant UIC Graduate Student Conference in Logic University of Notre Dame April 28-29, 2012 Gabriel Conant (UIC) Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs April

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY

INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY ARTEM CHERNIKOV Lecture notes for the IMS Graduate Summer School in Logic, National University of Singapore, Jun 2017. The material is based on a number of sources including:

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin large and large and March 3, 2015 Characterizing cardinals by L ω1,ω large and L ω1,ω satisfies downward Lowenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward Lowenheim Skolem. Definition sentence

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis

Foundations. September 4, Foundations. A Model Theoretic Perspective. John T. Baldwin. sociology. Thesis I. Thesis II. A Concept Analysis September 4, 2009 Outline 1 2 3 4 A Data point for PBPL Practice based philosophy of logic Are model theorists logicians? They do not analyze methods of reasoning. A Data point for PBPL Practice based

More information

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS AARON LANDESMAN CONTENTS 1. Introduction to finite fields 2 2. Definition and constructions of fields 3 2.1. The definition of a field 3 2.2. Constructing field extensions by adjoining

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 14, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be stably embedded. Let P be P with

More information

Disjoint n-amalgamation

Disjoint n-amalgamation October 13, 2015 Varieties of background theme: the role of infinitary logic Goals 1 study n- toward 1 existence/ of atomic models in uncountable cardinals. 2 0-1-laws 2 History, aec, and Neo-stability

More information

THE DEGREES OF CATEGORICAL THEORIES WITH RECURSIVE MODELS

THE DEGREES OF CATEGORICAL THEORIES WITH RECURSIVE MODELS PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S 0002-9939(XX)0000-0 THE DEGREES OF CATEGORICAL THEORIES WITH RECURSIVE MODELS URI ANDREWS (Communicated by Julia Knight)

More information

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

ω-stable Theories: Introduction ω-stable Theories: Introduction 1 ω - Stable/Totally Transcendental Theories Throughout let T be a complete theory in a countable language L having infinite models. For an L-structure M and A M let Sn

More information

THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE

THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE RHIANNON HALL, JAMES OXLEY, AND CHARLES SEMPLE Abstract. A 3-connected matroid M is sequential or has path width 3 if its ground set E(M) has a

More information

Hrushovski s Amalgamation Construction

Hrushovski s Amalgamation Construction Amalgamation Frank O Wagner Institut Camille Jordan Université Claude Bernard France 1 August Plan 1 2 3 In 1986, Ehud Hrushovski modified construction of a universial homogeneous countable relational

More information

INTERPRETING HASSON S EXAMPLE

INTERPRETING HASSON S EXAMPLE INTERPRETING HASSON S EXAMPLE CHARLES K. SMART Abstract. We generalize Ziegler s fusion result [8] by relaxing the definability of degree requirement. As an application, we show that an example proposed

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

The number of countable models

The number of countable models The number of countable models Enrique Casanovas March 11, 2012 1 Small theories Definition 1.1 T is small if for all n < ω, S n ( ) ω. Remark 1.2 If T is small, then there is a countable L 0 L such that

More information

Continuum Harvard. April 11, Constructing Borel Models in the. Continuum Harvard. John T. Baldwin. University of Illinois at Chicago

Continuum Harvard. April 11, Constructing Borel Models in the. Continuum Harvard. John T. Baldwin. University of Illinois at Chicago April 11, 2013 Today s Topics 1 2 3 4 5 6 Pseudo-minimal 7 Further Applications Section 1: { Models in L ω1,ω L ω1,ω satisfies downward Löwenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward

More information

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES VC-DENSITY FOR TREES ANTON BOBKOV Abstract. We show that for the theory of infinite trees we have vc(n) = n for all n. VC density was introduced in [1] by Aschenbrenner, Dolich, Haskell, MacPherson, and

More information

Simple homogeneous structures

Simple homogeneous structures Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Logic Colloquium, 3-8 August 2015, Helsinki Introduction Homogeneous structures have interesting properties from a model theoretic point of view. They also

More information

What is... Fraissé construction?

What is... Fraissé construction? What is... Fraissé construction? Artem Chernikov Humboldt Universität zu Berlin / Berlin Mathematical School What is... seminar at FU Berlin, 30 January 2009 Let M be some countable structure in a fixed

More information

On the Effectiveness of Symmetry Breaking

On the Effectiveness of Symmetry Breaking On the Effectiveness of Symmetry Breaking Russell Miller 1, Reed Solomon 2, and Rebecca M Steiner 3 1 Queens College and the Graduate Center of the City University of New York Flushing NY 11367 2 University

More information

Algebras with finite descriptions

Algebras with finite descriptions Algebras with finite descriptions André Nies The University of Auckland July 19, 2005 Part 1: FA-presentability A countable structure in a finite signature is finite-automaton presentable (or automatic)

More information

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Joint work with: W. Boney, S. Friedman, C. Laskowski, M. Koerwien, S. Shelah, I. Souldatos University of Illinois at Chicago AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Cantor s Middle Attic Uncountable

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space.

Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space. MAT 90 // 0 points Exam Solutions Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space..(0) Prove: a central arrangement A in V is essential if and only if the dual projective

More information

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018 Lecture 2: Syntax January 24, 2018 We now review the basic definitions of first-order logic in more detail. Recall that a language consists of a collection of symbols {P i }, each of which has some specified

More information

Automorphism groups of wreath product digraphs

Automorphism groups of wreath product digraphs Automorphism groups of wreath product digraphs Edward Dobson Department of Mathematics and Statistics Mississippi State University PO Drawer MA Mississippi State, MS 39762 USA dobson@math.msstate.edu Joy

More information

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ NICOLAS FORD Abstract. The goal of this paper is to present a proof of the Nullstellensatz using tools from a branch of logic called model theory. In

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs Europ. J. Combinatorics (2002) 23, 257 274 doi:10.1006/eujc.2002.0574 Available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs ANTHONY BONATO, PETER

More information

Model Theory and Differential Algebraic Geometry

Model Theory and Differential Algebraic Geometry Model Theory and Differential Algebraic Geometry David Marker Mathematics, Statistics, and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago January 6, 2012 Dave Marker (UIC) Model Theory and Diff Alg

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

ZILBER S PSEUDO-EXPONENTIAL FIELDS. The goal of this talk is to prove the following facts above Zilber s pseudoexponential

ZILBER S PSEUDO-EXPONENTIAL FIELDS. The goal of this talk is to prove the following facts above Zilber s pseudoexponential ZILBER S PSEUDO-EXPONENTIAL FIELDS WILL BONEY The goal of this talk is to prove the following facts above Zilber s pseudoexponential fields (1) they are axiomatized in L ω1,ω(q) and this logic is essential.

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Fifty Years in the Model Theory of Differential Fields. ASL Winter Meeting 2019 JMM Baltimore

Fifty Years in the Model Theory of Differential Fields. ASL Winter Meeting 2019 JMM Baltimore Fifty Years in the Model Theory of Differential Fields ASL Winter Meeting 2019 JMM Baltimore David Marker Mathematics, Statistics, and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago January 20, 2019

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness.

What is the right type-space? Humboldt University. July 5, John T. Baldwin. Which Stone Space? July 5, Tameness. Goals The fundamental notion of a Stone space is delicate for infinitary logic. I will describe several possibilities. There will be a quiz. Infinitary Logic and Omitting Types Key Insight (Chang, Lopez-Escobar)

More information

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3. ABSTRACT BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 123 3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3.1. Abstract Boolean Algebra. Definition 3.1.1. An abstract Boolean algebra is defined as a set B containing two distinct elements 0 and 1,

More information

Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC

Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Martin Koerwien KGRC April 20, 2016 Michael C. Laskowski University of Maryland Abstract We introduce the concept

More information

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE D-MAXIMAL SETS PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE Abstract. Soare [23] proved that the maximal sets form an orbit in E. We consider here D-maximal sets, generalizations of maximal sets introduced

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

Elements of Geometric Stability Theory

Elements of Geometric Stability Theory Elements of Geometric Stability Theory May 2003 1 Completeness and quantifier elimination for some classical theories We first work out a basic example, with a proof that demonstrates geometroalgebraic,

More information

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures Roman Wencel 1 Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wroc lawskiego ABSTRACT We consider a class of weakly o-minimal structures admitting

More information

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u.

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u. 5. Fields 5.1. Field extensions. Let F E be a subfield of the field E. We also describe this situation by saying that E is an extension field of F, and we write E/F to express this fact. If E/F is a field

More information

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B).

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.24 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. Then L(A B) = L(A) L(B). It is worth noting that you can t replace union

More information

Diskrete Mathematik und Optimierung

Diskrete Mathematik und Optimierung Diskrete Mathematik und Optimierung Winfried Hochstättler Michael Wilhelmi: Sticky matroids and Kantor s Conjecture Technical Report feu-dmo044.17 Contact: {Winfried.Hochstaettler, Michael.Wilhelmi}@fernuni-hagen.de

More information

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY VICTOR ZHANG Abstract. We demonstrate how several problems of algebraic geometry, i.e. Ax-Grothendieck, Hilbert s Nullstellensatz, Noether- Ostrowski, and Hilbert s

More information

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Peter J. Cameron and D. Lockett School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary, University of London Mile End Road London E1 4NS, U.K. Abstract Jarik Nešetřil suggested

More information

Contribution of Problems

Contribution of Problems Exam topics 1. Basic structures: sets, lists, functions (a) Sets { }: write all elements, or define by condition (b) Set operations: A B, A B, A\B, A c (c) Lists ( ): Cartesian product A B (d) Functions

More information

Model Theory and Forking Independence

Model Theory and Forking Independence Model Theory and Forking Independence Gabriel Conant UIC UIC Graduate Student Colloquium April 22, 2013 Gabriel Conant (UIC) Model Theory and Forking Independence April 22, 2013 1 / 24 Types We fix a first

More information

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM NICK RAMSEY Abstract. A theory is called κ-categorical, or categorical in power κ, if it has one model up to isomorphism of cardinality κ. Morley s Categoricity Theorem states

More information

GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET

GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET GEOMETRIC STRUCTURES WITH A DENSE INDEPENDENT SUBSET ALEXANDER BERENSTEIN AND EVGUENI VASSILIEV Abstract. We generalize the work of [13] on expansions of o-minimal structures with dense independent subsets,

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

Meta-logic derivation rules

Meta-logic derivation rules Meta-logic derivation rules Hans Halvorson February 19, 2013 Recall that the goal of this course is to learn how to prove things about (as opposed to by means of ) classical first-order logic. So, we will

More information

Forcing and Group Theory

Forcing and Group Theory Senior Thesis Forcing and Group Theory Submitted to the Department of Mathematics on 15 April 2013 in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with Honors Senior Thesis. A. James Schmidt

More information

Preliminaries. Introduction to EF-games. Inexpressivity results for first-order logic. Normal forms for first-order logic

Preliminaries. Introduction to EF-games. Inexpressivity results for first-order logic. Normal forms for first-order logic Introduction to EF-games Inexpressivity results for first-order logic Normal forms for first-order logic Algorithms and complexity for specific classes of structures General complexity bounds Preliminaries

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS

MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS MODEL THEORY OF DIFFERENCE FIELDS MOSHE KAMENSKY Lecture 1, Aug. 28, 2009 1. Introduction The purpose of this course is to learn the fundamental results about the model theory of difference fields, as

More information

Weight and measure in NIP theories

Weight and measure in NIP theories Weight and measure in NIP theories Anand Pillay University of Leeds September 18, 2011 Abstract We initiate an account of Shelah s notion of strong dependence in terms of generically stable measures, proving

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions

Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions Sergei Ovchinnikov San Francisco State University, Mathematics Department, 1600 Holloway Ave., San Francisco, CA 94132 Abstract Partial cubes

More information

Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures

Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures Douglas Cenzer 1, Valentina Harizanov 2 and Jeffrey B. Remmel 3 Abstract We study computability theoretic properties of computable injection structures

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 Index Page 1 Topology 2 1.1 Definition of a topology 2 1.2 Basis (Base) of a topology 2 1.3 The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3 1.4 Basic topology concepts: limit points, closed sets,

More information

Axioms for Set Theory

Axioms for Set Theory Axioms for Set Theory The following is a subset of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms for set theory. In this setting, all objects are sets which are denoted by letters, e.g. x, y, X, Y. Equality is logical identity:

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that:

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: Equivalence MA Relations 274 and Partitions Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: (1) is reflexive. That is, (2) is

More information

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs

Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs Mathematical Reasoning & Proofs MAT 1362 Fall 2018 Alistair Savage Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0

More information

Characterizations of the finite quadric Veroneseans V 2n

Characterizations of the finite quadric Veroneseans V 2n Characterizations of the finite quadric Veroneseans V 2n n J. A. Thas H. Van Maldeghem Abstract We generalize and complete several characterizations of the finite quadric Veroneseans surveyed in [3]. Our

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 944 955 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Types directed by constants

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

Classifying classes of structures in model theory Classifying classes of structures in model theory Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel, and Rutgers University, NJ, USA ECM 2012 Saharon Shelah (HUJI and Rutgers) Classifying classes

More information

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability 16.2. MINIMAL ARITHMETIC AND REPRESENTABILITY 207 If T is a consistent theory in the language of arithmetic, we say a set S is defined in T by D(x) if for all n, if n is in S, then D(n) is a theorem of

More information

Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 94 First-Order Logic. Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 6.5 The Semantic Game 93

Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 94 First-Order Logic. Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 6.5 The Semantic Game 93 65 The Semantic Game 93 In particular, for every countable X M there is a countable submodel N of M such that X N and N = T Proof Let T = {' 0, ' 1,} By Proposition 622 player II has a winning strategy

More information

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS

UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS UMASS AMHERST MATH 300 SP 05, F. HAJIR HOMEWORK 8: (EQUIVALENCE) RELATIONS AND PARTITIONS 1. Relations Recall the concept of a function f from a source set X to a target set Y. It is a rule for mapping

More information

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE D-MAXIMAL SETS PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE Abstract. Soare [20] proved that the maximal sets form an orbit in E. We consider here D-maximal sets, generalizations of maximal sets introduced

More information

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS

3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS 3 COUNTABILITY AND CONNECTEDNESS AXIOMS Definition 3.1 Let X be a topological space. A subset D of X is dense in X iff D = X. X is separable iff it contains a countable dense subset. X satisfies the first

More information

ON THE ALGEBRAIC INDEPENDENCE OF GENERIC PAINLEVÉ TRANSCENDENTS.

ON THE ALGEBRAIC INDEPENDENCE OF GENERIC PAINLEVÉ TRANSCENDENTS. ON THE ALGEBRAIC INDEPENDENCE OF GENERIC PAINLEVÉ TRANSCENDENTS. JOEL NAGLOO 1, ANAND PILLAY 2 Abstract. We prove that if y = f(y, y, t, α, β,...) is a generic Painlevé equation from among the classes

More information

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 ON SETS WITH RANK ONE IN SIMPLE HOMOGENEOUS STRUCTURES OVE AHLMAN AND VERA KOPONEN arxiv:1403.3079v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 Abstract. We study definable sets D of SU-rank 1 in M eq, where M is a countable

More information

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. Every complete first order theory has a corresponding complete theory in continuous logic, called the randomization theory.

More information

Dynamical properties of the Automorphism Groups of the Random Poset and Random Distributive Lattice

Dynamical properties of the Automorphism Groups of the Random Poset and Random Distributive Lattice Dynamical properties of the Automorphism Groups of the Random Poset and Random Distributive Lattice Alexander S. Kechris and Miodrag Sokić Abstract: A method is developed for proving non-amenability of

More information

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 125 Chapter 5. Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections. 5.1. Semilattices and lattices. Many of the partially ordered sets P we have seen have a further valuable property: that for any two

More information