RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING"

Transcription

1 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU Abstract. We study the strengths of various notions of higher randomness: (i) strong Π -ML-randomness is separated from Π -ML-randomness; (ii) the hyperdegrees of Π -random reals are closed downwards (except for the trivial degree); (iii) the reals z in NCR Π are precisely those satisfying z L ω z ; and (iv) lowness for -randomness is strictly weaker than that for Π -randomness.. Introduction Randomness in the higher setting refers to the study of algorithmic randomness properties of reals from the point of view of effective descriptive set theory. Until recently, the study of algorithmic randomness has been focused on reals in the arithmetical hierarchy. The only exception was a paper by Martin-Löf [3], in which he showed the intersection of a sequence of -sets of reals to be Σ (Sacks [9] introduced the notion of Π and -randomness in two exercises). The first systematic study of higher randomness appeared in Hjorth and Nies [0] where the notion of Π -Martin-Löf randomness was defined and the key properties investigated. The paper also studied the stronger notion of Π -randomness and showed the existence of a universal test for Π -random reals. In Chong, Nies and Yu [2] the authors examined the relative strengths of Π -Martin-Löf randomness, Π and -randomness, as well as their associated notions of lowness. Effective descriptive set theory offers a natural and different platform for the study of algorithmic randomness. Since the Gandy-Spector Theorem injects a new perspective to Π -sets of natural numbers, viewing them as Σ -definable subsets of L ω CK and therefore recursively enumerable (r.e.) in the larger universe, the tools of hyperarithmetic theory are readily available for the investigation of random reals in the generalized setting. Just as arithmetical randomness has drawn new insights into the structure of Turing degrees below 0 (n) (for n < ω), the study of higher randomness properties has enhanced our understanding of hyperdegrees and Π -sets of reals, a point which we hope results presented in this paper will convey. We consider several basic notions of randomness (see the next section for the definitions). In [2] it was shown that Π -Martin-Löf randomness, Π and -randomness 200 Mathematics Subject Classification. 03D30,03D32,68Q30. We thank the referee for helpful comments and suggestions, as well as for a very careful reading of the manuscript. We also thank André Nies for useful discussions and comments. Most of the results in the paper were presented in Logic blog 202 maintained by Nies. Yu s research was partially supported by National Natural Science Fund of China, No. 074 and Chong s research was partially supported by NUS Grant C

2 2 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU are equivalent for reals x if and only if ω x = ω CK. In [5], Nies introduced another notion called strong Π -Martin- Löf randomness which is an analog of weak 2-randomness in the literature. We prove (Theorem 3.5) that every hyperdegree greater than or equal to the hyperdegree of Kleene s O contains a real that is Π but not strongly Π - Martin-Löf random, thus separating these two notions of randomness. In Theorem 4.4, we show that every nontrivial hyperdegree below the hyperdegree of a Π -random real contains a Π -random real. Such a downward closure property is not shared by weaker notions such as Π -Martin-Löf randomness. In fact, every nontrivial real below a Π -random is Π -random relative to a measure (Corollary 4.5), so that such reals are still essentially random. This result is strengthened in Theorem 5.: We characterize the class NCR Π of reals x which are not Π -random relative to any representation of a continuous measure to be precisely those which satisfy x L ω x. Our final result (Theorem 6.5) separates the notion of low for -randomness from that of low for Π -randomness. To obtain this, we prove a general theorem about hyperdegrees (Theorem 6.3) which states that any two uncountable Σ -set of reals generate the cone of hyperdegrees with base the hyperdegree of Kleene s O. The latter has its root in a result of Martin [2] that every uncountable -set of reals contains a member of each hyperdegrees greater than or equal to the degree of O. The paper concludes with a list of questions. 2. Preliminaries We assume that the reader is familiar with hyperarithmetic theory and randomness theory. For a general reference, refer to [6], [5], [9] or [3]. The notations adopted are standard. Reals are denoted x, y, z,... A tree T is a subset of 2 <ω or ω <ω. [T ] denotes the set of infinite paths on T. By abuse of notation, we also write x T (or x U for U 2 <ω ) if the context is clear. We use k n to express the fact that the number k is much bigger than n. If λ is a measure on the Cantor space 2 ω, and σ 2 <ω, denote λ(σ) to be the measure of λ on the basic open set {x σ x}. We also let [σ] denote the set of binary strings extending σ. Definition 2.. Given a measure λ on 2 ω, a real ˆλ represents λ if for any σ 2 <ω and rational numbers p, q, σ, p, q ˆλ p < λ(σ) < q. Given a representation ˆλ of a measure λ, one may define the notion of a ˆλ-Martin- Löf test as usual. More details can be found in [6]. We use µ to denote the Lebesgue measure throughout this paper. Definition 2.2. (i) A Π -ML-test is a sequence {U m } m ω of uniformly Π -open sets such that m(µ(u m ) < 2 m ). We say that x is Π -ML random if x / m U m for every such collection {U m }, i.e. if x passes every Π -ML test. (ii) ([5, Problem 9.2.7]) {U m } is a Π -generalized ML test if {U m } is a sequence of uniformly Π -open sets and lim m µ(u m ) = 0. We say that x is strongly Π -MLrandom if x passes every generalized Π -ML-test. Definition 2.2 (ii) is an analog of the notion of weak-2-randomness for reals, where Π is replaced by r.e. One may refine Definition 2.2 (i) as follows. A -ML-test is

3 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 3 obtained when Π in the definition is replaced by. Indeed, if {U n } n ω is a - ML-test, then there is a recursive ordinal α such that {U n } n ω is uniformly (α) -r.e. We call such a test a (α) -ML-test. A real x is -ML-random if it passes every - ML-test. If x is not -ML-random, then there is an α < ω CK and an (α) -ML-test in which x fails. This fact will be used in Section 4. Definition 2.3. (Hjorth and Nies in [0]) A real x is Π -random if it does not belong to any null Π -set of reals. Clearly m ω U m is Π for any uniformly Π -collection of Π -open sets, so that Π - randomness implies strong Π -ML-randomness. We say that a real x is -dominated if every function hyperarithmetic in x is dominated by a hyperarithmetic function. As usual, ω x is the least ordinal which is not an x-recursive ordinal, and Church-Kleene ω is ω which is always denoted ω CK. By a result in [2], we have the following proposition. Proposition 2.4 (Chong, Nies and Yu). If ω x = ω CK, then x is Π -ML-random if and only if it is Π -random. Moreover, each Π -random real is -dominated. The Gandy Basis Theorem plays an important role in our present study: Theorem 2.5 (Gandy [8]). If A 2 ω is a nonempty Σ -set, then there is an x A such that ω x = ω CK. Let L α be the Gödel constructibility hierarchy at level α. The following is a settheoretic characterization of Π -sets. Theorem 2.6 (Spector[2], Gandy [9]). A set A 2 ω is Π if and only if there is a Σ -formula ϕ such that x A L ω x [x] = ϕ. We use h to denote hyperarithmetic reduction. A(ω CK, x) is the structure for the ramified analytical hierarchy relative to x. For more details concerning the ramified analytical hierarchy, see [9]. If T is a tree that is Π (L ω CK )-definable, then there is an effective enumeration over L ω CK of the nodes not in T. For any γ < ω CK, let T [γ] be the -tree which is an approximation of T at stage γ. Then T = γ<ω T [γ]. CK In Nies [5], Problem asks 3. Strong Π -ML-randomness Question 3.. Is strong Π -ML-randomness equivalent to Π -ML-randomness? The question was motivated by the following consideration. In the standard argument separating weak 2-randomness from ML-randomness, one exploits the fact that the rate of convergence of µ(u n ) to 0 can be coded by the size of the space available to U n, where {U n } n ω is a test designed to exhibit the separation (the technical details can be found in [5]). Such an approach is no longer possible in the present setting, since U n is now enumerated in ω CK, instead of ω, -many stages. The following result leads to a negative solution.

4 4 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU Theorem 3.2. If x is the leftmost path of a Σ -closed set of reals, then x is not strongly Π -ML-random. The proof is measure-theoretic. More than separating the two notions of randomness, a measure-theoretic proof extracts useful information about the distribution of strong Π -ML random reals in the hyperdegrees. We first give a criterion for a uniformly Π -sequence of open sets to be a generalized Π -Martin-Löf test. This lemma will also be applied to show Theorem 3.5. Lemma 3.3. Suppose that {U n } n ω is a uniformly Π -sequence of open sets. If there is a Σ (L ω CK ) enumeration {Ûn,γ} n<ω,γ<ω CK of the sequence with two numbers k and m such that for every n, U n = γ<ω Û CK n,γ and for every γ < ω CK : (a) Ûn+,γ Ûn,γ and each string in Ûn has length at least k n, (b) σ 2 k n m (µ(ûn,γ [σ]) < 2 +m k n ), and (c) For γ < ω CK and any real z, if z Ûn,<γ \ Ûn,γ, where Ûn,<γ = β<γ Ûn,β, then z Ûn,β for any β γ. Then {U n } n ω is a generalized Π -ML-test. Proof. Note that by (c) the enumeration {Ûn,γ} of U n is not cumulative. Assume µ( n ω U n) > 0 for a contradiction. We will exhibit an infinite descending sequence of ordinals {γ n } n<ω for a contradiction. First of all, by the Lebesgue Density Theorem, the assumption implies that there is a σ 0 such that µ( n ω U n [σ 0 ]) > 2 σ 0 ( 2 3 ) = σ 0. Moreover, we may assume that k divides σ 0 + m. Let n 0 = σ 0 +m. Then there is a k least γ 0 < ω CK such that By (b), µ(ûn 0, γ 0 [σ 0 ]) > σ 0. µ((ûn 0,<γ 0 \ Ûn 0,γ 0 ) [σ 0 ]) > 2 σ 0 ( ) = σ 0. By (a) and (c), the set of strings which appear after the ordinal γ 0 is contained in the complement of (Ûn 0,<γ 0 \ Ûn 0,γ 0 ) [σ 0 ], and so µ( n>n 0 Û n,<γ0 [σ 0 ]) > ( ) 2 σ0 = 4 2 σ0. Hence there is a σ σ 0 such that µ( n>n 0 Û n,<γ0 [σ ]) > σ0. Bienvenu, Greenberg and Monin [] have a shorter proof of this theorem.

5 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 5 We may assume that k divides σ + m and σ σ 0. Let n = σ +m k n 0. Then there is a least γ < γ 0 such that µ(ûn, γ [σ ]) > σ. Repeating the argument, we obtain an infinite descending sequence γ 0 > γ >, which is not possible. Proof. (of Theorem 3.2). Let T 2 <ω be a Σ -tree. For any n < ω and γ < ω CK, let and Define Û n,γ = {z n + z is the leftmost path in T [γ]}. Û n,<γ = β<γ Û n,β U n = The following facts are immediate. γ<ω CK Û n,γ. () For any n and γ < ω CK, Ûn+,γ Ûn,γ and every string in Ûn has length at least n; (2) σ 2 n (µ(ûn,γ [σ]) 2 n < 2 n ); (3) For any n, γ < ω CK and real z, if z Ûn,<γ \ Ûn,γ, then z Ûn,β for any β γ. Clearly {U n } n ω is uniformly Π. By () (3) and setting k = m = in Lemma 3.3, i {U n } n ω is a generalized Π -ML-test. Obviously x n ω U n. We conclude that x is not strongly Π -ML-random. Corollary 3.4. Π -ML-randomness is strictly weaker than strong Π -ML-randomness. Proof. By a result in [0], there is a Σ -tree T such that [T ] is not empty and consists entirely of Π -ML-random reals. According to Theorem 3.2, the leftmost path in T is not strongly Π -ML-random. We give another application of Lemma 3.3. The following theorem may be proved by combining results in [] and [0]. We give a direct proof here. Theorem 3.5. For any real x h O, there is a Π -ML-random y h x which is not strongly Π -ML-random. Proof. Given a tree T, let T (T ) be the smallest subtree of T such that T (T ), and For σ T (T ), let V σ = {ν ν σ ν = σ + 4 [ν] T is infinite}. If τ is the leftmost or rightmost string in V σ, then τ T (T ). Now let T 2 <ω be a Σ -tree of positive measure so that [T ] consists entirely of Π -ML-random reals. Note that T has no isolated infinite paths.

6 6 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU and For any γ < ω CK, let Define Û n,γ = σ T (T [γ]) σ =4n+4 Û n,<γ = β<γ Û n,β U n = The following facts are immediate. γ<ω CK ([σ] T (T [γ])). Û n,γ. () For any n and γ < ω CK, Ûn+,γ Ûn,γ and every string in Ûn,γ has length at least 4n (in fact 4n + 4); (2) σ 2 4n (µ(ûn,γ [σ]) 2 2 4n 4 < 2 4n ); (3) For any n, γ < ω CK and real z, if z Ûn,<γ \ Ûn,γ, then z Ûn,β for any β γ. By () (3) and Lemma 3.3 by setting k = 4 and m = 0, {U n } n<ω is a generalized Π -ML-test. It is obvious that n ω U n contains a perfect subset of [T ]. Furthermore, O hyperarithmetically computes a perfect tree S with [S] n ω U n so that no path in S is strongly Π -ML-random. Hence no path in S is Π -random and by Proposition 2.4, any y [S] satisfies ω y > ω CK and so O h y. Such a y exists in every hyperdegree above the degree of O. Theorem 3.5 is proved. 4. Hyperdegrees of Π -random reals While the hyperdegrees of -random reals cover the cone of hyperdegrees above the hyperjump, it is not difficult to see that the situation is quite different outside this cone: Proposition 4.. If x is -random and ω x = ω CK, then there is a real y h x with ω y = ω CK whose hyperdegree contains no -random real. Proof. Suppose that x is -random and ω x = ω CK. Let H(x) = {y y T x f T y g h x(g is dominated by f)}. By Theorem 2.6, H(x) is Σ (x). Since O x H(x), H(x) is not empty. Relativizing Gandy s Basis Theorem 2.5 to x, there is a real y H(x) with ω y = ω x = ω CK. Thus y is not -dominated and so by Proposition 2.4, no real z h y is -random. By contrast, the hyperdegrees of Π -random reals are downward closed. Lemma If x is Π -random and y h x, then there is a recursive ordinal γ such that y T x (γ). 2 The lemma was also proved by Bienvenu, Greenberg and Monin [] independently.

7 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 7 Proof. Suppose that x is Π -random and y h x. Then ω x formula ϕ(ẋ, n) with rank α 0 < ω CK such that n y A(ω CK, x) = ϕ(x, n). = ω CK and there is a Recall that for a ranked sentence ψ, the relation µ({z A(ω CK, z) = ψ) > 0 is Π (Theorem.3.IV of [9]). Hence by the admissibility of ω CK, there is a recursive ordinal β > α 0 such that A α0 = { ψ ψ has rank at most α 0 µ({z A(ω CK, z) = ψ}) > 0} is recursive in (β). Then there is a recursive α β such that for any natural number i and formula ψ of rank at most β, there is a formula ψ of rank at most α such that {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ } is a Π 0 ( (α) )-subset of {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ} and the difference in measure between these two sets is less than 2 i. Repeating this, we obtain a -definable ω-sequence of ordinals α 0 < α < in L ω CK whose supremum γ = i<ω α i satisfies the following two properties: for any β < γ, (i) The set A β = { ϕ ϕ has rank at most β µ({z A(ω CK, z) = ϕ}) > 0} is recursive in (γ) ; and (ii) For any natural number i and formula ψ with rank at most β, there is a formula ψ of rank less than γ such that for some β < γ, {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ } is a Π 0 ( (β ) )-subset of {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ} and the difference in measure between these two sets is less than 2 i. Note that by Π -randomness, for any ranked formula ψ, if x P ψ = {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ}, then P ψ has positive measure. By Proposition 2.4, x is -dominated and so there is a hyperarithmetic function f : ω ω such that for any n O with n < γ and any e for which Φ ( n ) e computes a tree T e,n, if x [T e,n ], then x f( e, n ) T e,n. This allows us to implement the following construction. Recursively in x (γ) f, first find a ψ 0 with rank less than γ such that P 0 = {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ 0 } contains x, has positive measure, and is a closed subset of either {z A(ω CK, z) = ϕ(z, 0)} or {z A(ω CK, z) = ϕ(z, 0)}. Since x is Π -random, by (ii), such a ψ 0 exists. Note that x (γ) f is able to decide if x P 0. In general, for any n recursively in x (γ) f choose the formula ψ n+ with rank less than γ such that P n+ = {z A(ω CK, z) = ψ n+ } contains x, has positive measure, and is a closed subset of either P n {z A(ω CK, z) = ϕ(z, n)} or P n {z A(ω CK, z) = ϕ(z, n)}. Since x is Π -random, by (ii) there is such a ψ n+. Thus y T x (γ) f. Without loss of generality, we may assume that f T (γ). Then y T x (γ). Corollary 4.3. For any Π -random x and y h x, there is a recursive ordinal α, a function f T (α) and an oracle function Φ such that for every n, y(n) = Φ x (α) f(n) (n)[f(n)]. In other words, x (α) Turing computes y via the function Φ with both use and time bounded by f.

8 8 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU Proof. Suppose that x is Π -random and y h x. By Lemma 4.2, there is a recursive ordinal γ and an oracle function Φ such that for every n, y(n) = Φ x (γ) (n). Let g < h x such that for every n, y(n) = Φ x (γ) g(n) (n)[g(n)]. Since x is -dominated, there is a hyperarithmetic h such that for all n, h(n) > g(n). Hence there is a recursive ordinal α γ such that h is many-one reducible to (α). Then it is not difficult to define an f T (α) and an oracle function Ψ such that for every n, y(n) = Ψ x (α) f(n) (n)[f(n)]. Theorem 4.4. If x is Π -random and < h y h x, then there is a Π -random z h y. Proof. Suppose that x is Π -random and y h x is not hyperarithmetic. Then there is a recursive ordinal α, a nondecreasing function f T (α) and an oracle function Ψ such that lim n f(n) = and for every n, y(n) = Ψ x (α) f(n) (n)[f(n)]. We use a technique which is essentially due to Demuth [4]. For any τ 2 <ω, let C(τ) = {σ σ 2 f( τ ) Ψ σ (α) f( τ ) [f( τ )] τ}. In other words, C(τ) is the clopen set of strings of length f( u ), which output extensions of τ via Ψ. For strings τ and u, let τ < l u mean τ is to the left of u. Define (α) -recursive functions: l(u) = ( 2 σ ) and τ 2 u τ< l u σ C(τ) r(u) = l(u) + σ C(u) 2 σ. Intuitively l(u) is the measure of the set of strings of length f( u ) which output strings at the left of u and r(u) is the l(u) plus the measure of the set of strings of length f( u ) which outputs extensions of u. One may view σ C(τ) 2 σ as a measure of τ, see Demuth [4]. For each n, let l n = l(y n), and r n = r(y n). Then l n l n+ r n+ r n for every n. Since y is not hyperarithmetic, then by Sacks s result in [8] that the hyperarithmetic degree upper cone of any nonhyperarithmetic real is null, we have that lim n r n = 0. Hence there is a unique real z = n ω(l n, r n ). Obviously z T y (α). To prove z h y, note that for any n, (α) -recursively find a string u of length n such that z lies in the interval (l(u), r(u)). Then it must be the case that u = y n. So y T z (α). And thus z h y. We claim that z is -random.

9 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 9 Suppose otherwise. Then there is a recursive ordinal β < ω CK and a (β) -ML-test {V n } n ω such that z n ω V n. Let ˆV n = {u ν k(ν is the k-th string in V n p, q Q(p < l(u) < r(u) < q [ν] (p, q) q p < 2 n k ν ))}. Since z V n, we have y ˆV n for every n. Note that { ˆV n } n ω is (β++α) -r.e. 3 Let U n = {σ τ ˆV n ( σ = f( τ ) Φ σ (α) f( τ ) [f( τ )] τ)} = u ˆV n C(u). Then {U n } n ω is (β++α) -r.e and x n ω U n. Note that for every n, µ(u n ) 2 τ = r(u) l(u) µ(v n )+ 2 n k 2+ < 2 n +2 n = 2 n+. u ˆVn τ C(u) u ˆV n k ω Then {U n+ } n ω is a (β++α) -ML-test. So x is not a -random, a contradiction. If we define λ(τ) = σ C(τ) 2 σ, then λ can be viewed as a continuous measure over 2 ω. Then the following is an immediate consequence of the proof of Theorem 4.4: Corollary 4.5. For any Π -random x, if < h y h x then y is Π -random relative to the hyperarithmetic continuous measure λ. A further result on continuous measures is discussed in Theorem 5.. Remark: Together with the argument used in the proof of Proposition 2.7 in [6], one can show that the converse of the Corollary 4.5 is also true. In other words, for any x, x is hyperarithmetically equivalent to a Π -random real if and only if x is Π -random relative to the hyperarithmetic continuous measure λ. 5. On NCR Π This section is inspired by the work of Reimann and Slaman in [6] and [7], where they investigated reals not Martin-Löf random relative to any continuous measure. They prove that NCR, the collection of such reals, is countable. In fact their proof shows that for any recursive ordinal α, the collection NCR α of reals not (α) -MLrandom relative to any continuous measure is countable. Hence a natural question to ask is how far the countability property extends. We set an upper limit for this by proving Theorem 5.. Given a representation ˆλ of a measure λ over 2 ω, define a real x to be Π -random relative to ˆλ if it does not belong to a λ-null set which is Π (ˆλ). Define 3 If let λ(τ) = σ C(τ) 2 σ, then λ can be viewed as a measure over 2 ω. Then λ( ˆV n+ ) = u ˆV n+ σ C(u) 2 σ µ(v n+ ) + k ω 2 n k 2+ 2 n + 2 n 2 n. In other words, { ˆV n } n is a (β) -ML-test relative to λ.

10 0 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU NCR Π = {x x is not Π -random relative to any representation ˆλ of a continuous measure}. Let C = {x 2 ω x L ω x }. It is known that C is the largest Π -thin set. Theorem 5.. NCR Π = C. We decompose the proof of Theorem 5. into a sequence of lemmas. Lemma 5.2. NCR Π does not contain a perfect subset. Proof. The proof is essentially due to Reimann and Slaman [6]. Suppose that there is a perfect tree T 2 <ω such that every member of [T ] is NCR Π. Define a measure λ as follows: λ( ) =, and { λ([σ]) If σ λ([σ i]) = ( i) T ; λ([σ]) Otherwise. 2 Then λ is a continuous measure so that λ([t ]) =. Π -random relative to any representation ˆλ of λ. Lemma 5.3. NCR Π is a thin Π -set, and hence NCR Π C. Thus [T ] must contain a Proof. By Lemma 5.2, NCR Π does not contain a perfect subset. Relative to any representation ˆλ of a continuous measure λ, we may perform the same proofs as in [8] so that all the results remain valid upon replacing Lesbegue measure µ by ˆλ. Then the set {z ω z ˆλ > ωˆλ } is Π (ˆλ) and λ-null. Hence as in [2], there is a Π set Q (2 ω ) 2 such that for each real ˆλ representing a continuous measure, the set Qˆλ = {y (ˆλ, y) Q} is the largest Π (ˆλ) λ-null set. Then, as in Reimann and Slaman [7], z NCR Π ˆλ(ˆλ represents a continuous measure z Qˆλ). Thus NCR Π is Π. Lemma 5.4. If x L ω x and z h x, then z x h O z. Proof. Suppose that x L ω x and z h x. Then ω z < ω. x So ω x z > ω. z Thus z x h O z. Lemma 5.5. If x C, then x NCR Π. Proof. Let λ be a continuous measure with representation ˆλ and x C. If x h ˆλ, then x is clearly not Π -random relative to ˆλ. Otherwise, by Lemma 5.4, x ˆλ h Oˆλ. But {z z ˆλ Oˆλ} is a Π (ˆλ) λ-null set. This implies that x is not Π -random relative to ˆλ.

11 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 6. Separating lowness for higher randomness notions In [2], Chong, Nies and Yu investigated lowness properties for and Π -randomness. It is unknown whether there is a nonhyperarithmetic real low for Π -random. However, there is a characterization of reals which are low for Π -randomness. Proposition 6. (Harrington, Nies and Slaman [2]). Being low for Π -randomness is equivalent to being low for -randomness and not cuppable above O by a Π -random. We may apply Proposition 6. to separate lowness for -randomness from lowness for Π -randomness. Recall that given a class of sets of reals Γ, a real x is Γ-Kurtz random if it does not belong to any Γ-closed null set. In [], Kjos-Hanssen, Nies, Stephan and Yu investigated lowness for -Kurtz randomness and lowness for Π -Kurtz randomness. They proved that lowness for Π - Kurtz randomness implies lowness for -randomness. We show that the implication cannot be reversed. In [22], Yu gave a new proof of the following theorem. Theorem 6.2 (Martin [2] and Friedman). Every Σ -tree T with uncountably many infinite paths has a member of each hyperdegree h O as a path. We apply the technique introduced in [22] to prove the following result. Theorem 6.3. Let A 0 and A be uncountable Σ -sets of reals. For any z h O, there are reals x 0 A 0 and x A such that x 0 x h z. Proof. Fix a real z h O and two uncountable Σ -sets A 0 and A. Then there are two recursive trees T 0, T 2 <ω ω <ω such that for i, A i = {x f n(x n, f n) T i }. We may assume that neither A 0 nor A contains a hyperarithmetic real. Also assume that if (σ, τ) T i, i, then σ = Dom(τ). Let T 2 ω <ω be recursive so that [T 2 ] is uncountable and does not contain a hyperarithmetic infinite path. Let f O be the leftmost path in T 2. Then f O h O. For i, let [T i ] = {(x, f) n((x n, f n) T i )}. Our plan is to define x i A i such that z h x 0 x. To this end, a procedure of coding z and f O into x 0 and decoding them from x 0 x will be introduced. Construction of x i will be carried out in L ω CK [z] on the recursive tree T i, hence hyperarithmetically in z (since z h O). Since A i is Σ, x i will code in the function f i which is the leftmost path in the second component of [T i ] serving as a witness to x i being in A i (i.e. (x i, f i ) [T i ] and for any f, if (x i, f) [T i ] then f(n) f i (n) for all n). Since A i has no hyperarithmetic member, for any (σ, τ) T i, if σ x and τ f for some (x, f) [T i ], then there exist incompatible extensions σ and σ of σ, and (possibly compatible) extensions τ, τ of τ, so that (σ, τ ) and (σ, τ ) both have extensions in [T i ]. This splitting property of [A i ] allows the coding of z, f and f O in x 0 and the coding of f 0 in x. More specifically, the branch to be selected by x 0 at a splitting node when z(s) is to be coded (at stage s + of the construction) will follow the value of z(s), so that a left turn is taken if z(s) = 0 and a right turn is taken if z(s) =. The coding at stage s + of τ,s, which denotes the initial segment of f defined at the end of stage s, is accomplished by taking τ,s (t)-many consecutive left turns at splitting nodes, for

12 2 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU each t Dom(τ,s ). The coding of f O (s) at stage s + of the construction is carried out by taking left turns at f O (s)-many consecutive splitting nodes. For the purpose of decoding, one has to delineate different types of action taken during the coding phase. Since τ,s is a finite function, the end of coding the value τ,s (t) and the beginning of coding the value τ,s (t+), for t < Dom(τ,s ), is separated by a right turn at the splitting node between the two codings (of course since the construction is executed stage by stage, one may assume that at the beginning of stage s +, the coding of τ,s is already completed. This means that at stage s +, one only needs to code the values τ,s (t) for t Dom(τ,s ) \ Dom(τ,s )). A right turn is chosen at the next splitting node to signify the end of coding τ,s, and the beginning of the coding of f O (s). Finally, a right turn is taken at the next splitting node after coding f O (s) to mark the end of the coding action for x 0 at stage s +. This initial segment of x 0 coded at stage s + is denoted σ 0,s+. Then τ 0,s+ f 0 is a finite string in ω <ω such that Dom(τ 0,s+ ) = σ 0,s+, τ 0,s+ extends τ 0,s, and is the leftmost such string (meaning taking a left turn at every splitting node during coding). The coding of the initial segment τ 0,s+ of f 0 in x at stage s +, denoted σ,s+, proceeds in a similar fashion. The definition of τ,s+, an initial segment of f constructed at stage s +, follows the same format. We now describe the construction of x 0 and x and the associated strings in detail. For i and (σ, τ) T i, let T i (σ, τ) be the set of strings in T i compatible with (σ, τ), i.e. T i (σ, τ) = {(σ, τ ) T i (σ, τ ) (σ, τ) (σ, τ ) (σ, τ)}. We say that a string (or node) σ 2 <ω is splitting over (σ, τ) in T i if σ σ and for j, T i,σ j(σ, τ) = {(σ, τ ) σ σ j τ τ (σ, τ ) T i } contains an infinite path. T i,σ j(σ, τ) is the subtree of T i with root (σ j, τ) (note that σ σ). Since A i has no hyperarithmetic path, for each j, there is a string that splits over some (σ, τ ) in T i,σ j(σ, τ). Note that σ does not lie on T i but some pair (σ, τ ) does and we call (σ, τ ) a splitting node on T i. For each i, we construct a sequence (σ i,0, τ i,0 ) (σ i,, τ i, ) on T i and let x i = j σ i,j. Again, the idea is to apply a mutual coding technique so that x 0 codes the leftmost witness function f = s τ.s (in the Σ -definition) for x and x codes the leftmost witness function f 0 = s τ 0,s for x 0. In addition, we also assign x 0 the responsibility of coding z as well as f O. More precisely, for each s ω we use σ 0,s to code z(s), f O (s) and τ,s, and use σ,s to code τ 0,s. At stage 0, let (σ i,0, τ i,0 ) = (, ) for i. Without loss of generality, assume that (, ) is a splitting node in both T 0 and T. The construction at stage s + proceeds as follows: Substage (i). First let σ be the shortest splitting node over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) in T 0. Thus T 0,σ j(σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) contains an infinite path for j. Let σ0,s+ 0 be the leftmost splitting node over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) extending σ z(s) in T 0. Thus z(s) is coded here. Next we code τ,s. Let n 0 s+ = Dom(τ,s ) Dom(τ,s ) (let Dom(τ,s ) = 0 if s = 0). Inductively, for any k [, n 0 s+], let σ0,s+ k be the leftmost splitting node over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) extending (σ0,s+) k in T 0 so that there are τ,s (k + Dom(τ,s ) )-many

13 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 3 splitting nodes over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) in T 0 between σ0,s+ k and σ0,s+. k This completes the coding of τ,s. To code f O (s), let σ n0 s+ + 0,s+ be the leftmost splitting node extending (σ n0 0,s+) over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) in T 0 so that there are f O (s)-many splitting nodes in T 0 over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) between σ n0 s+ 0,s+ and σ n0 s+ + 0,s+. For j, let σ n0 s+ ++j+ 0,s+ be the next splitting node in T 0 over (σ 0,s, τ 0,s ) extending (σ n0 s+ ++j 0,s+ ). This coding tells us that the action at this substage for the x 0 side is completed. Define σ 0,s+ = σ n0 s+ +3 0,s+. Let τ 0,s+ extend τ 0,s so that Dom(τ 0,s+ ) = σ 0,s+ and τ 0,s+ is the leftmost node such that the tree T 0,(σ0,s+,τ 0,s+ ) has an infinite path. Substage (ii). Let σ 0,s+ = σ,s and n s+ = Dom(τ 0,s+ ) Dom(τ 0,s ). Inductively for any k [, n s+], let σ k,s+ be the leftmost splitting node over (σ,s, τ,s ) extending (σ k,s+) so that in T there are τ 0,s+ (k + Dom(τ 0,s ) )-many splitting nodes over (σ,s, τ,s ) between σ,s+ k and σ,s+. k Hence τ 0,s+ is coded. For j, let σ n s+ +j+,s+ be the next splitting node over (σ,s, τ,s ) in T extending (σ n s+ +j,s+ ). This coding tells us that the action of coding τ 0,s+ at this substage for the x side is completed. Define σ,s+ = σ n s+ +2,s+. Thus we have coded τ 0,s+ into σ,s+. Let τ,s+ extend τ,s so that Dom(τ,s+ ) = σ,s+ and τ,s+ is the leftmost finite string such that the tree T,(σ,s+,τ,s+ ) has an infinite path. This ends the construction at stage s +. Let x i = s<ω σ i,s for i. Note that the construction is carried out over L ω CK +[z] since O L ω CK + and whether (σ, τ) T i has an infinite path extension in T i is decided by stage L ω CK +. As z h O we have ω z > ω CK and so z h x 0 x. Now we use x 0 and x to decode the coding construction and hence O and z. The decoding is achieved via a finite injury method quite similar to that used in [22] to prove Theorem 6.2. We point out the key steps and leave the details to the reader. Construct a sequence of ordinals {α s } s<ω which is -definable in L x ω 0 x [x 0 x ] so that lim s ω α s = ω CK, and use it as a parameter to decode the reals z and f 0, thereby concluding that x 0 x h z. As in [22], we may fix a Σ -enumeration {T i [α]} i 2,α<ω CK over L ω CK such that for i 2, T i [0] = T i T i [α] T i [β] if α β T i [ω CK ] = α<ω T CK i [α] T i [ω CK ] has no dead end nodes, and A i = {x f n(x n, f n) T i [ω CK ]}. Since [T i ] does not contain a hyperarithmetic infinite path, we have [T i [ω CK ]] = [T i ] to be a perfect tree (which as noted earlier enabled the coding procedure to be implemented). Clearly (x i, f i ) is an infinite path in T i [α] for each α. As was the case for T i, i, for each α < ω CK one may define the notion of a string σ being a splitting node over (σ, τ) in T i [α]. In particular, for (σ, τ) T i [α] such that σ x i, it makes sense to say that x i n splits over (σ, τ) in T i [α]. This means that there

14 4 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU is a τ τ such that (x i n.τ ) T i [α] and there are numbers n 0, n so that (x i n 0, τ n 0 ), (x i n, τ n ) T i [α]. In this case we also say that (x i n, τ ) is a splitting node over (σ, τ) in T i [α]. Note that this splitting is local in the sense that there is no guarantee that (x i n j, τ n j ) has an infinite extension in T i [α[ for j = 0,. Since for each i and α < ω CK, x i, f i is a path on T i [α], one may use x 0 x to approximate the values of f O (s) and f i (s) by simulating the construction of x i in T i [α]. This is achieved by attempting to retrieve the sequences {(σ i,s, τ i,s )} s ω, i, using x 0 x. Of course, since it is yet to be established that z and f O are hyperarithmetic in x 0 x, the retrieval is only by way of approximating the original construction. Using x 0 x, one may mimic the construction of {(σ i,s, τ i,s )} s ω to define {(σ i,s [α], τ i,s [α])} s ω, for i, so that σ i,s [α] is an initial segment of x i (in ascending order of length) and (σ i,s+ [α], τ i,s+ [α]) is a splitting node over (σ i,s [α], τ i,s [α]) in T i [α]. Furthermore, for each i, τ i,s [α] codes an approximation of f i s at stage α. We leave the details of defining (σ i,s, τ i,s ) to the reader. The algorithm we adopt for decoding, applying the idea in [22], proceeds as follows. Let f O,0 (0) = f O (0) and α 0 = 0. Suppose t > 0. We say that x 0 x computes f O correctly up to j at stage α if the approximation to f O via T 2 at stage α is consistent with that via {σ 0,s [α]} s ω up to the decoding of f O j. Note that at any stage α, x 0 x always computes f O correctly up to 0. Similarly, z is correctly computed up to j between α and α if the decoding of z j in {σ 0,s [α]} s ω agrees with that in {σ 0,s [α ]} s ω. Let j(t ) = Dom(f O,t ) where f O,t is correctly computed by x 0 x at stage α t. If z is correctly computed up to j(t ) between α t and α t +, let α t = α t +. Increase the computation of f O,s by one bit. To do this, let f O,t (j) = f O,t (j) for j j(t ) and let f O,t (j(t ) + ) be the value of f O (j(t ) + ) as decoded by {σ 0,s [α t ]} s ω. Otherwise, initialize the values of f O and z defined at step t which are incorrect. Let j j(t ) be the least j that is initialized. Search for a stage α > α t such that x 0 x correctly computes f O up to j at stage α. Note that such an α and j must exist (in the worst case, j = 0). This completes the construction at step t. Let γ = t ω α t. Clearly γ ω CK and is a limit ordinal. Furthermore γ < ω x 0 x. If γ = ω CK, then ω x 0 x > ω CK and this would imply that O h x 0 x and then z h x 0 x since the values of z j can be read off from {σ 0,s [ω CK ]} s ω by checking the (valid) splitting nodes in T 0 [ω CK ] along x 0. Otherwise, γ < ω CK. Since neither x 0 nor x is hyperarithmetic, as in [22] one argues that lim t f O,t (j) exists for every j. If not, choose the (least) j such that f O,t (j) f O,t+ (j) at infinitely many α t s. Then it must be the case that lim t f O,t (j) =. This implies that infinitely many left turns were selected at splitting nodes in T 0 [α t ] during the decoding phase to approximate f O (j), guided by σ 0,t [α t ] as t (recall that σ 0,t [α t ] mimics substage (i) at stage t in the construction

15 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 5 of x 0 ). Then there exist σ, τ so that x 0 is the leftmost real in the set X defined as {x σ n β < γ β τ τ(β β < γ Dom(τ ) = n (x n, τ ) T 0 [β ])}. Now X is a closed subset of 2 ω, implying that x 0 is hyperarithmetic which is a contradiction. Hence γ = ω CK. It remains for us to decode f i using the τ i,t [α t ] s. This follow the same approach discussed above and the detail is omitted. Thus for any n, there is a t n such that x 0 x correctly computes f O up to n at any stage α α tn. In other words, f O,tn (n) = f O,t (n) for t t n. Hence f O is the leftmost path of T 2 [γ]. Since [T 2 [γ]] = [T 2 ], we have lim t f O,t = f O. Hence O h f O h x 0 x. With this, we conclude that z h x 0 x and this completes the proof of the Theorem. Let F be the collection of all finite subsets of ω. A real x is -traceable if for any function f h x, there is a -function g : ω F such that for every n, g(n) = n and f(n) g(n). Lemma 6.4. There is an uncountable Σ -set A in which every member is - traceable. Proof. This is precisely what was proved in Theorem 4.7 of [20]. By [2] and [], each -traceable real is low for -randomness and hence low for -Kurtz randomness. By [0], the Π -random reals form a Σ -set. Then by Lemma 6.4 and Theorem 6.3, there is an x which is low for -randomness and x y h O for some Π -random y. So y is a Π (x)-singleton. We thus conclude: Theorem 6.5. Lowness for -randomness does not imply lowness for Π -randomness. And lowness for -Kurtz-randomness does not imply lowness for Π -Kurtz-randomness. Remark. Theorem 6.3 may be used to answer Question 58 in [7] and Question 3 in [20], whose solutions were announced by Friedman and Harrington but have remain unpublished. We end this paper with two problems. It is still unknown whether strong Π -ML-randomness coincides with Π -randomness. To separate these two notions, one way is to investigate the Borel ranks of different notions of randomness. Obviously the collection of Π 0 -ML-random reals is 3 and it 0 can be shown that it is not Π 3 (see Part 2, [23]). Moreover, it is not hard to see that the collection of Π Σ 0 0 -random reals is neither 2 nor 2. Its exact Borel rank remains unknown. We have the following conjecture. Σ Π Conjecture The collection of Π -random reals is not Π The conjecture was refuted by Monin [4] recently by showing that the collection of Π -random reals is proper Π 0 3.

16 6 C. T. CHONG AND LIANG YU Also the question whether lowness for Π -randomness coincides with hyperarithmeticity remains open. In view of Theorem 6., we have the following question. Question 6.7. Is it true that for any nonhyperarithmetic x and uncountable Σ -set A 2 ω, there is a y A such that x y h O? References [] Laurent Bienvenu, Noam Greenberg, and Benoit. Monin. Some higher randomness results. communication., 3, 2 [2] C. T. Chong, Andre Nies, and Liang Yu. Lowness of higher randomness notions. Israel J. Math., 66:39 60, 2008., 2, 5, 6, 6., 6 [3] Chong CT and Yu L. Recursion Theory: The Syntax and Structure of Definability. yuliang/course.pdf. 2 [4] Osvald Demuth. Remarks on the structure of tt-degrees based on constructive measure theory. Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin., 29(2): , [5] Rod Downey, Andre Nies, Rebecca Weber, and Liang Yu. Lowness and Π 0 2 nullsets. J. Symbolic Logic, 7(3): , [6] Rodney G. Downey and Denis R. Hirschfeldt. Algorithmic randomness and complexity. Theory and Applications of Computability. Springer, New York, [7] Harvey Friedman. One hundred and two problems in mathematical logic. J. Symbolic Logic, 40:3 29, [8] R. O. Gandy. On a problem of Kleene s. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., 66:50 502, [9] R. O. Gandy. Proof of Mostowski s conjecture. Bull. Acad. Polon. Sci. Sér. Sci. Math. Astronom. Phys., 8:57 575, [0] Greg Hjorth and André Nies. Randomness via effective descriptive set theory. J. Lond. Math. Soc. (2), 75(2): , 2007., 2.3, 3, 6 [] Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen, André Nies, Frank Stephan, and Liang Yu. Higher Kurtz randomness. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 6(0): , , 6 [2] Donald A. Martin. Proof of a conjecture of Friedman. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 55():29, 976., 6.2 [3] Per Martin-Löf. On the notion of randomness. In Intuitionism and Proof Theory (Proc. Conf., Buffalo, N.Y., 968), pages North-Holland, Amsterdam, 970. [4] Benoit. Monin. Higher randomness and forcing with closed sets. Stacs 204, to appear. 4 [5] André Nies. Computability and randomness, volume 5 of Oxford Logic Guides. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009., 2, 2.2, 3 [6] Jan Reimann and Theodore A. Slaman. Measures and their random reals , 4, 5, 5 [7] Jan Reimann and Theodore A. Slaman. Randomness for continuous measures , 5 [8] Gerald E. Sacks. Measure-theoretic uniformity in recursion theory and set theory. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 42:38 420, , 5 [9] Gerald E. Sacks. Higher recursion theory. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 990., 2, 2, 4 [20] Stephen G. Simpson. Minimal covers and hyperdegrees. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 209:45 64, , 6 [2] Clifford Spector. Hyperarithmetical quantifiers. Fund. Math., 48:33 320, 959/ [22] Liang Yu. A new proof of Friedman s conjecture. Bull. Symbolic Logic, 7(3):455 46, 20. 6, 6, 6 [23] Liang Yu. Higher randomness. Logic Blog,

17 RANDOMNESS IN THE HIGHER SETTING 7 Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, National University of Singapore, Singapore address: chongct@math.nus.eud.sg Institute of Mathematical Science, Nanjing University, Jiangsu Province 20093, P. R. of China address: yuliang.nju@gmail.com

ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE

ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE C. T. CHONG, WEI LI, WEI WANG, AND YUE YANG Abstract. A set X 2 ω with positive measure contains a perfect subset. We study such perfect

More information

The Metamathematics of Randomness

The Metamathematics of Randomness The Metamathematics of Randomness Jan Reimann January 26, 2007 (Original) Motivation Effective extraction of randomness In my PhD-thesis I studied the computational power of reals effectively random for

More information

INDEPENDENCE, RELATIVE RANDOMNESS, AND PA DEGREES

INDEPENDENCE, RELATIVE RANDOMNESS, AND PA DEGREES INDEPENDENCE, RELATIVE RANDOMNESS, AND PA DEGREES ADAM R. DAY AND JAN REIMANN Abstract. We study pairs of reals that are mutually Martin-Löf random with respect to a common, not necessarily computable

More information

THE K-DEGREES, LOW FOR K DEGREES, AND WEAKLY LOW FOR K SETS

THE K-DEGREES, LOW FOR K DEGREES, AND WEAKLY LOW FOR K SETS THE K-DEGREES, LOW FOR K DEGREES, AND WEAKLY LOW FOR K SETS JOSEPH S. MILLER Abstract. We call A weakly low for K if there is a c such that K A (σ) K(σ) c for infinitely many σ; in other words, there are

More information

Randomness Beyond Lebesgue Measure

Randomness Beyond Lebesgue Measure Randomness Beyond Lebesgue Measure Jan Reimann Department of Mathematics University of California, Berkeley November 16, 2006 Measures on Cantor Space Outer measures from premeasures Approximate sets from

More information

Effective Randomness and Continuous Measures

Effective Randomness and Continuous Measures Effective Randomness and Continuous Measures Theodore A. Slaman (on joint work with Jan Reimann) C University of California, Berkeley Review Let NCR n be the set of X 2 2! such that there is no (representation

More information

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS ASHER M. KACH AND ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We study the connection between the number of ascending and descending cuts of a linear order, its classical size, and its effective

More information

A Basis Theorem for Perfect Sets

A Basis Theorem for Perfect Sets A Basis Theorem for Perfect Sets Marcia J. Groszek Theodore A. Slaman November 17, 2000 Abstract We show that if there is a nonconstructible real, then every perfect set has a nonconstructible element,

More information

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS C. T. CHONG, STEFFEN LEMPP, AND YUE YANG Abstract. We show that the principle PART from Hirschfeldt and Shore

More information

PROBABILITY MEASURES AND EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS

PROBABILITY MEASURES AND EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS PROBABILITY MEASURES AND EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS JAN REIMANN AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN ABSTRACT. We study the question, For which reals x does there exist a measure µ such that x is random relative to µ? We

More information

TT-FUNCTIONALS AND MARTIN-LÖF RANDOMNESS FOR BERNOULLI MEASURES

TT-FUNCTIONALS AND MARTIN-LÖF RANDOMNESS FOR BERNOULLI MEASURES TT-FUNCTIONALS AND MARTIN-LÖF RANDOMNESS FOR BERNOULLI MEASURES LOGAN AXON Abstract. For r [0, 1], the Bernoulli measure µ r on the Cantor space {0, 1} N assigns measure r to the set of sequences with

More information

EFFECTIVE BI-IMMUNITY AND RANDOMNESS

EFFECTIVE BI-IMMUNITY AND RANDOMNESS EFFECTIVE BI-IMMUNITY AND RANDOMNESS ACHILLES A. BEROS, MUSHFEQ KHAN, AND BJØRN KJOS-HANSSEN Abstract. We study the relationship between randomness and effective biimmunity. Greenberg and Miller have shown

More information

Aspects of the Turing Jump

Aspects of the Turing Jump Aspects of the Turing Jump Theodore A. Slaman University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-3840, USA slaman@math.berkeley.edu 1 Introduction Definition 1.1 The Turing Jump is the function which

More information

STRUCTURES WITH MINIMAL TURING DEGREES AND GAMES, A RESEARCH PROPOSAL

STRUCTURES WITH MINIMAL TURING DEGREES AND GAMES, A RESEARCH PROPOSAL STRUCTURES WITH MINIMAL TURING DEGREES AND GAMES, A RESEARCH PROPOSAL ZHENHAO LI 1. Structures whose degree spectrum contain minimal elements/turing degrees 1.1. Background. Richter showed in [Ric81] that

More information

MEASURES AND THEIR RANDOM REALS

MEASURES AND THEIR RANDOM REALS MEASURES AND THEIR RANDOM REALS JAN REIMANN AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We study the randomness properties of reals with respect to arbitrary probability measures on Cantor space. We show that every

More information

Ten years of triviality

Ten years of triviality Ten years of triviality André Nies U of Auckland The Incomputable, Chicheley Hall, 2012 André Nies (U of Auckland) Ten years of triviality The Incomputable 1 / 19 K-trivials: synopsis During the last 10

More information

RANDOMNESS VIA INFINITE COMPUTATION AND EFFECTIVE DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY

RANDOMNESS VIA INFINITE COMPUTATION AND EFFECTIVE DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY RANDOMNESS VIA INFINITE COMPUTATION AND EFFECTIVE DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY MERLIN CARL AND PHILIPP SCHLICHT Abstract. We study randomness beyond Π 1 1-randomness and its Martin-Löf type variant, which was

More information

Randomizing Reals and the First-Order Consequences of Randoms. Ian Robert Haken

Randomizing Reals and the First-Order Consequences of Randoms. Ian Robert Haken Randomizing Reals and the First-Order Consequences of Randoms by Ian Robert Haken A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Recursion

More information

June 7, 2007 THE ISOMORPHISM PROBLEM FOR TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS IS ANALYTIC COMPLETE.

June 7, 2007 THE ISOMORPHISM PROBLEM FOR TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS IS ANALYTIC COMPLETE. June 7, 2007 THE ISOMORPHISM PROBLEM FOR TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS IS ANALYTIC COMPLETE. ROD DOWNEY AND ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We prove that the isomorphism problem for torsion-free Abelian groups

More information

Chaitin Ω Numbers and Halting Problems

Chaitin Ω Numbers and Halting Problems Chaitin Ω Numbers and Halting Problems Kohtaro Tadaki Research and Development Initiative, Chuo University CREST, JST 1 13 27 Kasuga, Bunkyo-ku, Tokyo 112-8551, Japan E-mail: tadaki@kc.chuo-u.ac.jp Abstract.

More information

RANDOMNESS NOTIONS AND PARTIAL RELATIVIZATION

RANDOMNESS NOTIONS AND PARTIAL RELATIVIZATION RANDOMNESS NOTIONS AND PARTIAL RELATIVIZATION GEORGE BARMPALIAS, JOSEPH S. MILLER, AND ANDRÉ NIES Abstract. We study the computational complexity of an oracle set using a number of notions of randomness

More information

Computability Theory

Computability Theory Computability Theory Domination, Measure, Randomness, and Reverse Mathematics Peter Cholak University of Notre Dame Department of Mathematics Peter.Cholak.1@nd.edu http://www.nd.edu/~cholak/papers/nyc2.pdf

More information

RANDOM REALS, THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM, AND ARITHMETIC CONSERVATION

RANDOM REALS, THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM, AND ARITHMETIC CONSERVATION THE JOURNAL OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000 RANDOM REALS, THE RAINBOW RAMSEY THEOREM, AND ARITHMETIC CONSERVATION CHRIS J. CONIDIS AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We investigate the question

More information

PRINCIPLES WEAKER THAN RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

PRINCIPLES WEAKER THAN RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS Π 1 1-CONSERVATION OF COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES WEAKER THAN RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS C. T. CHONG, THEODORE A. SLAMAN AND YUE YANG Abstract. We study combinatorial principles weaker than Ramsey s theorem

More information

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S 0002-9939(XX)0000-0 ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

More information

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ ALAN DOW Abstract. We prove that implies there is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff Lindelöf space of cardinality 2 ℵ1 which has points G δ. In addition, this space has

More information

THE IMPORTANCE OF Π 0 1 CLASSES IN EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS.

THE IMPORTANCE OF Π 0 1 CLASSES IN EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS. THE IMPORTANCE OF Π 0 1 CLASSES IN EFFECTIVE RANDOMNESS. GEORGE BARMPALIAS, ANDREW E.M. LEWIS, AND KENG MENG NG Abstract. We prove a number of results in effective randomness, using methods in which Π

More information

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. There is a set of reals U such that for every analytic set A there is a continuous function f which maps U bijectively to A. 1. Introduction A set

More information

Measures of relative complexity

Measures of relative complexity Measures of relative complexity George Barmpalias Institute of Software Chinese Academy of Sciences and Visiting Fellow at the Isaac Newton Institute for the Mathematical Sciences Newton Institute, January

More information

Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism

Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism Classes of Polish spaces under effective Borel isomorphism Vassilis Gregoriades TU Darmstadt October 203, Vienna The motivation It is essential for the development of effective descriptive set theory to

More information

ANY FIP REAL COMPUTES A 1-GENERIC

ANY FIP REAL COMPUTES A 1-GENERIC ANY FIP REAL COMPUTES A 1-GENERIC PETER CHOLAK, RODNEY G. DOWNEY, AND GREG IGUSA Abstract. We construct a computable sequence of computable reals X i such that any real that can compute a subsequence that

More information

COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE PARTIAL ORDERS

COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE PARTIAL ORDERS COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE PARTIAL ORDERS PETER A. CHOLAK, DAMIR D. DZHAFAROV, NOAH SCHWEBER, AND RICHARD A. SHORE Abstract. We study the degree spectra and reverse-mathematical applications of computably enumerable

More information

Random Reals à la Chaitin with or without prefix-freeness

Random Reals à la Chaitin with or without prefix-freeness Random Reals à la Chaitin with or without prefix-freeness Verónica Becher Departamento de Computación, FCEyN Universidad de Buenos Aires - CONICET Argentina vbecher@dc.uba.ar Serge Grigorieff LIAFA, Université

More information

LOWNESS FOR THE CLASS OF SCHNORR RANDOM REALS

LOWNESS FOR THE CLASS OF SCHNORR RANDOM REALS LOWNESS FOR THE CLASS OF SCHNORR RANDOM REALS BJØRN KJOS-HANSSEN, ANDRÉ NIES, AND FRANK STEPHAN Abstract. We answer a question of Ambos-Spies and Kučera in the affirmative. They asked whether, when a real

More information

THE POLARIZED RAMSEY S THEOREM

THE POLARIZED RAMSEY S THEOREM THE POLARIZED RAMSEY S THEOREM DAMIR D. DZHAFAROV AND JEFFRY L. HIRST Abstract. We study the effective and proof-theoretic content of the polarized Ramsey s theorem, a variant of Ramsey s theorem obtained

More information

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS MARCIN KYSIAK AND TOMASZ WEISS Abstract. We discuss the question which properties of smallness in the sense of measure and category (e.g. being a universally

More information

THE STRENGTH OF SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

THE STRENGTH OF SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS THE STRENGTH OF SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT, CARL G. JOCKUSCH, JR., BJØRN KJOS-HANSSEN, STEFFEN LEMPP, AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We study

More information

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES RODNEY G. DOWNEY, DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT, ASHER M. KACH, STEFFEN LEMPP, JOSEPH R. MILETI, AND ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We show that the existence of a nontrivial

More information

Reconciling data compression and Kolmogorov complexity

Reconciling data compression and Kolmogorov complexity Reconciling data compression and Kolmogorov complexity Laurent Bienvenu 1 and Wolfgang Merkle 2 1 Laboratoire d Informatique Fondamentale, Université de Provence, Marseille, France, laurent.bienvenu@lif.univ-mrs.fr

More information

Ultrafilters with property (s)

Ultrafilters with property (s) Ultrafilters with property (s) Arnold W. Miller 1 Abstract A set X 2 ω has property (s) (Marczewski (Szpilrajn)) iff for every perfect set P 2 ω there exists a perfect set Q P such that Q X or Q X =. Suppose

More information

Every set has a least jump enumeration

Every set has a least jump enumeration Every set has a least jump enumeration Richard J. Coles, Rod G. Downey and Theodore A. Slaman Abstract Given a computably enumerable set B, there is a Turing degree which is the least jump of any set in

More information

Schnorr trivial sets and truth-table reducibility

Schnorr trivial sets and truth-table reducibility Schnorr trivial sets and truth-table reducibility Johanna N.Y. Franklin and Frank Stephan Abstract We give several characterizations of Schnorr trivial sets, including a new lowness notion for Schnorr

More information

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES HRISTO GANCHEV AND MARIYA SOSKOVA 1. Introduction The local structure of the enumeration degrees G e is the partially ordered set of the

More information

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated Denis R. Hirschfeldt Department of Mathematics University of Chicago, USA Bakhadyr Khoussainov Department of Computer

More information

THERE IS NO ORDERING ON THE CLASSES IN THE GENERALIZED HIGH/LOW HIERARCHIES.

THERE IS NO ORDERING ON THE CLASSES IN THE GENERALIZED HIGH/LOW HIERARCHIES. THERE IS NO ORDERING ON THE CLASSES IN THE GENERALIZED HIGH/LOW HIERARCHIES. ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We prove that the existential theory of the Turing degrees, in the language with Turing reduction,

More information

Shift-complex Sequences

Shift-complex Sequences University of Wisconsin Madison March 24th, 2011 2011 ASL North American Annual Meeting Berkeley, CA What are shift-complex sequences? K denotes prefix-free Kolmogorov complexity: For a string σ, K(σ)

More information

From eventually different functions to pandemic numberings

From eventually different functions to pandemic numberings From eventually different functions to pandemic numberings Achilles A. Beros 1, Mushfeq Khan 1, Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen 1[0000 0002 6199 1755], and André Nies 2 1 University of Hawai i at Mānoa, Honolulu HI

More information

α-recursion Theory and Ordinal Computability

α-recursion Theory and Ordinal Computability α-recursion Theory and Ordinal Computability by Peter Koepke University of Bonn 1 3. 2. 2007 Abstract Motivated by a talk of S. D. Friedman at BIWOC we show that the α-recursive and α-recursively enumerable

More information

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY LINDELÖF SPACES GARY GRUENHAGE Abstract. We answer questions of Bennett, Lutzer, and Matveev by showing that any monotonically compact LOT S is metrizable, and any

More information

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals Boban Velickovic Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Prikry asked if it is relatively consistent with the usual axioms

More information

May 31, 2007 ON THE TRIPLE JUMP OF THE SET OF ATOMS OF A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA.

May 31, 2007 ON THE TRIPLE JUMP OF THE SET OF ATOMS OF A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA. May 31, 2007 ON THE TRIPLE JUMP OF THE SET OF ATOMS OF A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA. ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We prove the following result about the degree spectrum of the atom relation on a computable Boolean

More information

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL ALAN DOW AND OLEG PAVLOV Abstract. Hušek defines a space X to have a small diagonal if each uncountable subset of X 2 disjoint from the diagonal, has an uncountable

More information

STABILITY AND POSETS

STABILITY AND POSETS STABILITY AND POSETS CARL G. JOCKUSCH, JR., BART KASTERMANS, STEFFEN LEMPP, MANUEL LERMAN, AND REED SOLOMON Abstract. Hirschfeldt and Shore have introduced a notion of stability for infinite posets. We

More information

Mass Problems. Stephen G. Simpson. Pennsylvania State University NSF DMS , DMS

Mass Problems. Stephen G. Simpson. Pennsylvania State University NSF DMS , DMS Mass Problems Stephen G. Simpson Pennsylvania State University NSF DMS-0600823, DMS-0652637 http://www.math.psu.edu/simpson/ simpson@math.psu.edu Logic Seminar Department of Mathematics University of Chicago

More information

A Super Introduction to Reverse Mathematics

A Super Introduction to Reverse Mathematics A Super Introduction to Reverse Mathematics K. Gao December 12, 2015 Outline Background Second Order Arithmetic RCA 0 and Mathematics in RCA 0 Other Important Subsystems Reverse Mathematics and Other Branches

More information

RAMSEY S THEOREM AND CONE AVOIDANCE

RAMSEY S THEOREM AND CONE AVOIDANCE RAMSEY S THEOREM AND CONE AVOIDANCE DAMIR D. DZHAFAROV AND CARL G. JOCKUSCH, JR. Abstract. It was shown by Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman that every computable 2-coloring of pairs admits an infinite low

More information

DEFINABLE ENCODINGS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS

DEFINABLE ENCODINGS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS DEFINABLE ENCODINGS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS PETER A. CHOLAK AND LEO A. HARRINGTON 1. Introduction The purpose of this communication is to announce some recent results on the computably enumerable

More information

Effective descriptive set theory

Effective descriptive set theory Effective descriptive set theory Yiannis N. Moschovakis UCLA and University of Athens Mostowski100, October 13, 2013 Outline (I) A bit of history (3 slides) (II) The basic notions (7 slides) (III) Some

More information

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results)

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) Ehrhard Behrends Abstract A metric space (M, d) is said to have the small ball property (sbp) if for every ε 0 > 0 there exists a sequence

More information

Ramsey Theory and Reverse Mathematics

Ramsey Theory and Reverse Mathematics Ramsey Theory and Reverse Mathematics University of Notre Dame Department of Mathematics Peter.Cholak.1@nd.edu Supported by NSF Division of Mathematical Science May 24, 2011 The resulting paper Cholak,

More information

Computability Theory

Computability Theory Computability Theory Domination, Measure, Randomness, and Reverse Mathematics Peter Cholak University of Notre Dame Department of Mathematics Peter.Cholak.1@nd.edu Supported by NSF Grant DMS 02-45167 (USA).

More information

Uniquely Universal Sets

Uniquely Universal Sets Uniquely Universal Sets 1 Uniquely Universal Sets Abstract 1 Arnold W. Miller We say that X Y satisfies the Uniquely Universal property (UU) iff there exists an open set U X Y such that for every open

More information

Reverse mathematics and the equivalence of definitions for well and better quasi-orders

Reverse mathematics and the equivalence of definitions for well and better quasi-orders Reverse mathematics and the equivalence of definitions for well and better quasi-orders Peter Cholak Department of Mathematics, University of Notre Dame, USA Alberto Marcone Dipartimento di Matematica

More information

Cone Avoidance of Some Turing Degrees

Cone Avoidance of Some Turing Degrees Journal of Mathematics Research; Vol. 9, No. 4; August 2017 ISSN 1916-9795 E-ISSN 1916-9809 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education Cone Avoidance of Some Turing Degrees Patrizio Cintioli

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 1 May 2013

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 1 May 2013 VAN LAMBALGEN S THEOREM FOR UNIFORMLY RELATIVE SCHNORR AND COMPUTABLE RANDOMNESS arxiv:1209.5478v2 [math.lo] 1 May 2013 KENSHI MIYABE AND JASON RUTE Abstract. We correct Miyabe s proof of van Lambalgen

More information

Definability in the Enumeration Degrees

Definability in the Enumeration Degrees Definability in the Enumeration Degrees Theodore A. Slaman W. Hugh Woodin Abstract We prove that every countable relation on the enumeration degrees, E, is uniformly definable from parameters in E. Consequently,

More information

Using random sets as oracles

Using random sets as oracles Using random sets as oracles Denis R. Hirschfeldt André Nies Department of Mathematics Department of Computer Science University of Chicago University of Auckland Frank Stephan Departments of Computer

More information

ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS ON THE STRENGTH OF RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS PETER A. CHOLAK, CARL G. JOCKUSCH, JR., AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We study the proof theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of

More information

LOWNESS FOR BOUNDED RANDOMNESS

LOWNESS FOR BOUNDED RANDOMNESS LOWNESS FOR BOUNDED RANDOMNESS ROD DOWNEY AND KENG MENG NG Abstract. In [3], Brodhead, Downey and Ng introduced some new variations of the notions of being Martin-Löf random where the tests are all clopen

More information

COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS

COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS July 4, 2006 ANTONIO MONTALBÁN Abstract. We say that a countable linear ordering L is countably complementable if there exists a linear ordering L, possibly uncountable,

More information

GENERICS FOR COMPUTABLE MATHIAS FORCING

GENERICS FOR COMPUTABLE MATHIAS FORCING GENERICS FOR COMPUTABLE MATHIAS FORCING PETER A. CHOLAK, DAMIR D. DZHAFAROV, JEFFRY L. HIRST, AND THEODORE A. SLAMAN Abstract. We study the complexity of generic reals for computable Mathias forcing in

More information

Density-one Points of Π 0 1 Classes

Density-one Points of Π 0 1 Classes University of Wisconsin Madison Midwest Computability Seminar XIII, University of Chicago, October 1st, 2013 Outline 1 Definitions and observations 2 Dyadic density-one vs full density-one 3 What can density-one

More information

Every Incomplete Computably Enumerable Truth-Table Degree Is Branching

Every Incomplete Computably Enumerable Truth-Table Degree Is Branching Every Incomplete Computably Enumerable Truth-Table Degree Is Branching Peter A. Fejer University of Massachusetts at Boston Richard A. Shore Cornell University July 20, 1999 Abstract If r is a reducibility

More information

RESEARCH STATEMENT: MUSHFEQ KHAN

RESEARCH STATEMENT: MUSHFEQ KHAN RESEARCH STATEMENT: MUSHFEQ KHAN Contents 1. Overview 1 2. Notation and basic definitions 4 3. Shift-complex sequences 4 4. PA degrees and slow-growing DNC functions 5 5. Lebesgue density and Π 0 1 classes

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 May 2012

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 24 May 2012 FROM BOLZANO-WEIERSTRASS TO ARZELÀ-ASCOLI arxiv:1205.5429v1 [math.lo] 24 May 2012 ALEXANDER P. KREUZER Abstract. We show how one can obtain solutions to the Arzelà-Ascoli theorem using suitable applications

More information

Randomness and Recursive Enumerability

Randomness and Recursive Enumerability Randomness and Recursive Enumerability Theodore A. Slaman University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-3840 USA slaman@math.berkeley.edu Abstract One recursively enumerable real α dominates another

More information

The Absoluteness of Constructibility

The Absoluteness of Constructibility Lecture: The Absoluteness of Constructibility We would like to show that L is a model of V = L, or, more precisely, that L is an interpretation of ZF + V = L in ZF. We have already verified that σ L holds

More information

Kolmogorov-Loveland Randomness and Stochasticity

Kolmogorov-Loveland Randomness and Stochasticity Kolmogorov-Loveland Randomness and Stochasticity Wolfgang Merkle 1, Joseph Miller 2, André Nies 3, Jan Reimann 1, and Frank Stephan 4 1 Universität Heidelberg, Heidelberg, Germany 2 Indiana University,

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger.

A product of γ-sets which is not Menger. A product of γ-sets which is not Menger. A. Miller Dec 2009 Theorem. Assume CH. Then there exists γ-sets A 0, A 1 2 ω such that A 0 A 1 is not Menger. We use perfect sets determined by Silver forcing (see

More information

An introduction to OCA

An introduction to OCA An introduction to OCA Gemma Carotenuto January 29, 2013 Introduction These notes are extracted from the lectures on forcing axioms and applications held by professor Matteo Viale at the University of

More information

Time-bounded Kolmogorov complexity and Solovay functions

Time-bounded Kolmogorov complexity and Solovay functions Theory of Computing Systems manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Time-bounded Kolmogorov complexity and Solovay functions Rupert Hölzl Thorsten Kräling Wolfgang Merkle Received: date / Accepted:

More information

REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction

REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction RELIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERRITHMETIC HIERRCHY S DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE bstract. We construct a class of relations on computable structures

More information

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES RODNEY G. DOWNEY, DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT, ASHER M. KACH, STEFFEN LEMPP, JOSEPH R. MILETI, AND ANTONIO MONTALB AN Abstract. We show that the existence of a nontrivial

More information

Embedding and Coding Below a 1-Generic Degree

Embedding and Coding Below a 1-Generic Degree Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Embedding and Coding Below a 1-Generic Degree Noam Greenberg and Antonio Montalbán Abstract We show that the theory of D( g), where g is a 2-generic or a 1-generic degree

More information

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES XI CHEN Abstract. Following Kukie la, we show how to generalize some results from May s book [4] concerning cores of finite spaces to cores of Alexandroff spaces. It turns out

More information

Density-one Points of Π 0 1 Classes

Density-one Points of Π 0 1 Classes University of Wisconsin Madison April 30th, 2013 CCR, Buenos Aires Goal Joe s and Noam s talks gave us an account of the class of density-one points restricted to the Martin-Löf random reals. Today we

More information

Time-Bounded Kolmogorov Complexity and Solovay Functions

Time-Bounded Kolmogorov Complexity and Solovay Functions Time-Bounded Kolmogorov Complexity and Solovay Functions Rupert Hölzl, Thorsten Kräling, and Wolfgang Merkle Institut für Informatik, Ruprecht-Karls-Universität, Heidelberg, Germany Abstract. A Solovay

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 9 Dec 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 9 Dec 2016 RANDOMNESS VIA INFINITE COMPUTATION AND EFFECTIVE DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY MERLIN CARL AND PHILIPP SCHLICHT arxiv:1612.02982v1 [math.lo] 9 Dec 2016 Abstract. We study randomness beyond Π 1 1-randomness and

More information

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game

Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game Well-foundedness of Countable Ordinals and the Hydra Game Noah Schoem September 11, 2014 1 Abstract An argument involving the Hydra game shows why ACA 0 is insufficient for a theory of ordinals in which

More information

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order. October 12, 2010 Sacks Dicta... the central notions of model theory are absolute absoluteness, unlike cardinality, is a logical concept. That is why model theory does not founder on that rock of undecidability,

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski The onto mapping property of Sierpinski A. Miller July 2014 revised May 2016 (*) There exists (φ n : ω 1 ω 1 : n < ω) such that for every I [ω 1 ] ω 1 there exists n such that φ n (I) = ω 1. This is roughly

More information

Finding paths through narrow and wide trees

Finding paths through narrow and wide trees Finding paths through narrow and wide trees Stephen Binns Department of Mathematics and Statistics King Fahd University of Petroleum and Minerals Dhahran 31261 Saudi Arabia Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen Department

More information

(9-5) Def Turing machine, Turing computable functions. (9-7) Def Primitive recursive functions, Primitive recursive implies Turing computable.

(9-5) Def Turing machine, Turing computable functions. (9-7) Def Primitive recursive functions, Primitive recursive implies Turing computable. (9-5) Def Turing machine, Turing computable functions. A.Miller M773 Computability Theory Fall 2001 (9-7) Def Primitive recursive functions, Primitive recursive implies Turing computable. 1. Prove f(n)

More information

Selective Ultrafilters on FIN

Selective Ultrafilters on FIN Selective Ultrafilters on FIN Yuan Yuan Zheng Abstract We consider selective ultrafilters on the collection FIN of all finite nonempty subsets of N. If countablesupport side-by-side Sacks forcing is applied,

More information

Symbolic Dynamics: Entropy = Dimension = Complexity

Symbolic Dynamics: Entropy = Dimension = Complexity Symbolic Dynamics: Entropy = Dimension = omplexity Stephen G. Simpson Pennsylvania State University http://www.math.psu.edu/simpson/ simpson@math.psu.edu Worshop on Infinity and Truth Institute for Mathematical

More information

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Alf Dolich Kingsborough Community College Julia F. Knight University of Notre Dame Karen Lange Wellesley College David Marker University of Illinois at Chicago

More information