Belief-free Equilibria in Repeated Games

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Belief-free Equilibria in Repeated Games"

Transcription

1 Belief-free Equilibria in Repeated Games Jeffrey C. Ely Johannes Hörner Wojciech Olszewski November 6, 003 bstract We introduce a class of strategies which generalizes examples constructed in two-player games under imperfect private monitoring. sequential equilibrium is belief-free if, after every private history, each player s continuation strategy is optimal independently of his belief about his opponents private histories. We provide a simple and sharp characterization of equililibrium payoffs using those strategies. While such strategies have desirable robustness properties, they are not rich enough to generate a folk theorem in most games besides the prisoner s dilemma, even when noise vanishes. Introduction (Infinitely) repeated games have widespread application in economics as simple and tractable models of ongoing strategic relationships between agents. The tractability of the repeated game model is due to its recursive nature: the game that begins at date t is identical to the game that was begun at date 0. powerful set of analytical techniques have been developed to characterize The present paper develops some ideas from Ely and Välimäki (000) and Hörner and Olszewski (00). We are indebted to Juuso Välimäki for his work on the project in early stages. We are also grateful to Marcin Peski for his help with removing a flaw from Matsushima (00), to Ichiro Obara for pointing out an important error in an early draft of Hörner and Olszewski (00), and to Rakesh Vohra for his suggestions on dynamic programming literature. The paper has been presented at the Canadian Economic Theory Conference in 003, and in workshops at Northwestern University, University of Chicago and Harvard-MIT. We are grateful to those audiences for comments. Department of Economics, Boston University. ely@bu.edu. Financial support from NSF grant # is gratefully acknowledged. Department of Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences, Kellogg Graduate School of Management. j-horner@kellogg.northwestern.edu. Department of Economics, Northwestern University. wo@northwestern.edu.

2 behavior in repeated games. These methods exploit a recursive property of equilibrium made possible by the recursive structure of the repeated game. breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990), Fudenberg, Levine, and Maskin (994) and others have applied these techniques to a special class of equilibria, referred to as public equilibria, in which the behavior of all players is contingent only on information that is publicly known. While this restriction rules out some sequential equilibria, there is an important class of economic environments in which the restriction entails little loss of generality. In particular, if all of the information player i obtains about the behavior of his rivals is also public information (these are games with public monitoring), then all pure-strategy sequential equilibria are observationally equivalent to public equilibria, see breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990). Moreover, it is an implication of Fudenberg, Levine, and Maskin (994) that in games with public monitoring, all (pure or mixed) sequential equilibrium payoffs can be obtained by public equilibria, provided information is sufficiently rich and the players are sufficiently patient (this is the folk theorem.) Still, the restriction to games with public monitoring leaves out many potential applications. well-known example is a repeated oligopoly model in which firms compete in prices and neither these prices nor the firms sales are public information. This is the secret price-cut model of Stigler (964). For these repeated games with private monitoring, public strategies accomplish very little, and so to determine the equilibrium possibilities it is necessary to investigate strategies in which continuation play can be contingent on information held privately by the players. The difficulty appears to be that the recursive structure of equilibria is then lost, see Kandori (00). Recently however, some advances in the analysis of repeated games with private monitoring have made this obstacle appear less severe than at first glance. In the context of a two-player repeated prisoners dilemma, Piccione (00) and Ely and Välimäki (00) (hereafter VPE) identified a new class of sequential equilibrium strategies that can be analyzed using recursive techniques and showed that this class is sufficiently rich to establish a version of the folk theorem for that game. The key characteristic of these strategies is that when they are used, the optimal continuation strategy for a given player i is independent of that player s own history. This means that the history of the other player is a sufficient statistic for player i s payoffs and can thus be used as a state variable in a dynamic programming formulation of player i s optimization. In this paper, we look at two-player repeated games with private monitoring and consider strategies with exactly this property. We call the property belief-free because it implies that a player s belief about his opponent s history is not needed for computing a best-reply. Thus, the daunting complexity of tracking a player s beliefs over time to ensure that his strategy remains a best-reply is avoided for equilibria involving belief-free strategies. Belief-free strategies are attractive from the standpoint of robustness as well: because a player s beliefs are irrelevant, Moreover, the above results leave open the possibility that for a fixed discount factor or for information structures that are not sufficiently rich, some mixed-strategy sequential equilibrium may achieve more than any public equilibrium. In fact this possibility has been demonstrated by Fudenberg and Tirole (99) (exercise 5.0) and Kandori and Obara (003). See also Mailath, Matthews, and Sekiguchi (00) for similar examples in finitely repeated games.

3 the player need not worry whether he may have mis-interpreted his information about the past. Furthermore, equilibria depend only on the marginal distributions of each player s signal and not on the correlation. We demonstrate that these equilibria can be analyzed using recursive techniques which build on a variation of the concepts of self-generation and factorization due to breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990). We say that a payoff vector (v, v ) is strongly generated by a set of vectors W W if there is a mixed action profile α from the stage game, and for each player i, continuation values can be selected from W i so that α i is a best reply for player i and results in total payoff v i no matter what action from the support of α i he expects his opponent to play. It is the last condition that we add to the breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990) version of self-generation and this is the condition that captures the belief-free property of the equilibria we characterize. Let B(W ) be the set of all vectors strongly generated by W. We say that a set W for which W B(W ) is strongly self-generating and show that all members of a strongly self-generating set are belief-free equilibrium payoffs. Furthermore, the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs of a given game is itself a strongly self-generating set, indeed the largest such set. Finally, we characterize the structure of this largest strongly self-generating set W. In particular we show that iteratively applying the set-valued mapping B( ) beginning with the feasible set of payoffs results in a shrinking sequence of sets whose intersection is W. Furthermore, we show a version of the bang-bang principle for belief-free equilibrium payoffs. ny strongly self-generating set W of payoffs can be supported by belief-free strategies that are implementable by state automata whose only continuation payoffs are the extreme points of W, such as the strategies used in Ely and Välimäki (00). Next we consider two limiting cases: increasing patience and increasing monitoring accuracy. These are also the limits considered by VPE. For increasing patience (δ ), we show that the limiting set of equilibria can be easily characterized by a family of linear programs. This characterization is a version of the methods introduced by Fudenberg and Levine (994) and adapted by Kandori and Matsushima (998) to characterize the limiting set of public equilibria. s an example of this method, the maximum payoff for player i can be found by considering an auxiliary contracting problem where player i chooses a mixed action profile and gives utility penalties to player i as a function of observed signals in order to induce i to play a mixed action that results in as high as possible a net utility for i. We use this characterization to discover the boundaries of the belief-free equilibrium payoff set under the second limit, as the players monitor one another with increasing accuracy. We find a simple formula that can easily be computed by linear programming methods and apply it to a series of examples. These examples show that belief-free equilibria can support a large set of payoffs, but the prisoner s dilemma considered by VPE is apparently exceptional: in general this set is not large enough to establish the folk Fudenberg and Levine (994) analyzed public equilibria in games with long-run and short-run players, and Kandori and Matsushima (998) looked at equilibria of games with private monitoring in which all payoff-relevant behavior was conditioned on public announcements made by the players. 3

4 theorem. s a final application of our techniques, we consider the special case of games with independent monitoring. These are games in which, conditional on the chosen action profile, the players observe statistically independent signals. Whereas the folk theorem of VPE required signals to be nearly perfectly informative, recently Matsushima (00) demonstrated the folk theorem for the prisoner s dilemma with conditionally independent but only minimally informative signals. This was accomplished by augmenting the strategies used by Ely and Välimäki (00) with a review phase. We apply our results to provide a sufficient condition for equilibrium payoffs in arbitrary two action games with independent monitoring. The condition generalizes the result of Matsushima (00) and our techniques simplify the argument. The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section is a tour through the results of this paper by means of a worked example. In section 3 we introduce the notation used in the paper, present the definition of belief-free strategies, and establish some preliminary results. Section 4 introduces the concept of strong self-generation and uses it to characterize the set of belief-free equilibrium payoffs. The bang-bang result appears here. In section 5 we present our characterization results for discount factors near and near-perfect monitoring structures, and demonstrate their use with some examples. We also show here how our results can be applied to games with infinitely many strategies. Finally, section 6 takes up the case of independent monitoring and section 7 concludes. Introductory Example: Partnership Game To introduce the ideas and techniques of this paper, consider the following partnership game, a private-monitoring version of a game studied by Radner, Myerson, and Maskin (986), breu, Milgrom, and Pearce (99), Kandori and Obara (003). There are two players working on a common project. The two players simultaneously decide whether to work W or shirk S. Mixed actions are denoted α [0, ] and represent the probability of W. Each player realizes profit from the project which can be either high H or low L. Let m(σ a, a ) denote the marginal probability that player i realizes profit level σ {H, L} when the action (i.e. effort) choices are (a, a ) {W, S} {W, S}. Effort is costly, but raises the probability of high profits. Specifically, we assume that the cost and profit distributions are such that the players expected net payoffs, expressed as a function of the two players efforts are represented (perhaps after normalization) by the following table, where g and l are positive numbers. For simplicity, we shall suppose that the profit distributions depend only on the number of players exerting effort and not on their identity. Let p k denote the marginal probability that i realizes low profits when k {0,, } players choose W. Note that we are assuming that the individual players effort-conditioned profit distributions are symmetric and anonymous, but we make no assumptions on the correlation in profits across players. For notational convenience, define the following likelihood ratios r = p /p, and r 0 = p 0 /p, 4

5 W S W, l, + g S + g, l 0, 0 Figure : Normalized Partnership Game and values ( ) v = g r ( ) v = l r 0 We will assume that the likelihood ratios are sufficiently large that v > v. special case of this model is perfect correlation of the players realized profits. In this case, the (common) realized profit is always public information, and the game reduces to one of imperfect public monitoring. This is the case analyzed by breu, Milgrom, and Pearce (99) and these authors showed that v is the maximum symmetric perfect public equilibrium payoff. 3 We will now show using the techniques introduced in this paper that under our assumption on the likelihood ratios, for discount factors close enough to, this value can be achieved in a symmetric belief-free equilibrium for any degree of correlation in the players profits. Continuation Strategies and Belief-Free Equilibria In the repeated partnership game, in each period players choose whether to work or shirk as a function of their private history: their own history of past effort levels and realized profits. The continuation strategy used by player i starting in period t thus depends on the private history h i observed by player i. For each such continuation strategy, there is a set of best-reply continuation strategies for player i. In general because player i cannot infer h i from his own private history, i s best-reply at period t is based on an expected payoff calculation relative to i s conditional beliefs about h i. mong other difficulties, the need to track these conditional beliefs over time and across histories makes verification of sequential rationality an intractable problem in general. 4 We follow VPE by restricting attention to strategy profiles in which the set of best-replies for i is independent of the private history of player i. We call such strategies belief-free. In a sequential equilibrium involving belief-free strategies (belief-free equilibrium for short), there is a given set of actions t i such that player i is wiling to play any action in t i regardless 3 Kandori and Obara (003) also analyzed the public monitoring special case. They showed that for some parameter values, there are equilibria in non-public strategies with payoffs exceeding v. 4 See Kandori (00) for further discussion of the difficulties of characterizing sequential equilibrium in repeated games with private monitoring. 5

6 of the private history i has observed. Simply set t i to be the set of actions that are played by some optimal continuation strategy. Since the belief-free property implies that the set of optimal continuation strategies is history-independent, each element of t i will be optimal at each of i s t-length private histories. We refer to the set t = t t as the regime at period t. Belief-free equilibria can be classified according to the sequence of regimes,,.... For the partnership application, we will characterize the payoffs arising from a particularly simple class of belief-free equilibria: those in which the regime is constant over time and equal to the full set = {W, S} {W, S} of action profiles. Notice that in such a belief-free equilibrium every repeated game strategy is a best-response continuation strategy after every history. Continuation Values and Strong Self-Generation In any sequential equilibrium, for each player there is a set V i of potential continuation values. These are the payoffs from continuation strategy profiles that could arise after some finite history of play. In general, i s continuation value in period depends on the first period private histories of both players since continuation strategies do. In a belief-free equilibrium, the continuation value of player i can be treated as a function w i (a i, σ i ) only of the private history of i. That is because given the private history of i, each continuation strategy played by i is a best-reply and hence achieves the same value. This enables us to decompose the belief-free equilibrium strategy of player i into the initial mixed action α i and the continuation value function w i mapping private histories into V i. With this representation of i s strategy, we can determine the repeated game payoff of player i as a function only of i s first-stage action. Indeed, the first-stage action determines (together with α i ) the first-stage payoff as well as the distribution over (discounted) continuation payoffs. In order for the equilibrium to be belief-free with constant regime, it must be that both a i = W, S deliver repeated game payoff v i, i.e. v i = ( δ)u i (a i, α i ) + δ E(w i a i, α i ) where for any f : {W, S} {H, L} R we write E(f a i, α i ) = α i (a i )m(σ i a i, a i )f(a i, σ i ) a i {W,S} σ i {H,L} for the conditional expectation of f. In this case we say that v i is strongly generated by V i. We say that a set of payoffs V i is strongly self-generating for player i if every v V i is strongly generated by V i. The concept of self-generation was introduced by breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990) to characterize equilibria of repeated games with imperfect public monitoring. In general, no such simple characterization is available for repeated games with private monitoring. Our strong version of self-generation adds to theirs the constraint that the player be indifferent among each action in the given regime. With this constraint added, we show (Proposition ) that strongly self-generating sets of payoffs are belief-free sequential equilibrium payoffs. The 6

7 proof of this result is a straightforward adaptation of the original proof for games with public monitoring. Note that to show that an interval V i is strongly self-generating, it suffices to show that the endpoints are strongly generated by V i. To see this, note that the constraints are linear. Thus if they are satisfied for some the pairs (α i, w i ) and (α i, w i), then they are satisfied for any convex combinations of these. If the endpoints of the interval are strongly generated, then taking convex combinations will deliver all payoffs in the interior of the interval. nalysis Just as in the public monitoring case, where self-generation has yielded many simple techniques for further characterizing equilibrium payoffs (see Fudenberg and Levine (994) and Kandori and Matsushima (998)), we provide a simple linear-programming recipe for finding strongly self-generating sets. To illustrate the technique in the context of the partnership example, consider the following static moral hazard contracting problem. Player will select a mixed action α and make transfer payments to player depending on both the realization of α and profit σ. Denote by x (a, σ ) the payment to player. Faced with this contract, player will select an action a and obtain utility u (a, α ) + E(x a, α ) The objective is to select α and x in order to provide player a given utility level v and to make player indifferent between W and S. This gives rise to the following constraints. v = u (a, α ) + E(x a, α ) for both a = W, S. Consider any v which can be provided in this way subject to the additional constraint that x (, ) 0. lso suppose that v > v can be provided when we impose the constraint that x (, ) 0. Let α and α be the corresponding mixed action choices for player. We can show that the interval [v, v ] is strongly self-generating for player when δ is close enough to. To this end, define continuation values w (a, σ ) = v + δ x (a, σ ) δ Note that if x (, ) 0 then for δ close enough to, each continuation value is within [v, v ]. Substituting into the constraints for providing v, we have v = u (a, α ) + δ δ [ v + E(w a, α )] dding δ δ v to both sides and multiplying by δ shows that v is strongly generated by [v, v ]. similar manipulation shows that v is strongly generated by [v, v ]. 7

8 With these results in hand, we can now show that v is a belief-free symmetric equilibrium payoff. Our assumption on the likelihood ratios guarantees that v < v and thus we need only show that v can be provided using non-positive transfers and v can be provided using nonnegative transfers. To implement v, set α = and x (W, H) = 0. With such a contract, a choice of W earns player utility + p x (W, L) and S obtains ( + g) + p x (W, L). Equating these gives x (W, L) = g/(p p ) and this provides utility ( ) p g p p which is another way of writing v. Similarly, to implement v, set α = 0, x (S, L) = 0 and x (S, H) = l/(p 0 p ). 3 Definitions and Preliminary Results We analyze two-player repeated games with imperfect monitoring. Each player i =, has a finite action set i and a finite set of signals Σ i. n action profile is an element of :=. We use W to represent the set of probability distributions over a finite set W, and P (W ) to represent the collection of all non-empty subsets of W. Let i and := represent respectively the set of mixed actions for player i and mixed action profiles. For each possible action profile a, the monitoring distribution m ( a) specifies a joint probability distribution over the set of signal profiles Σ := Σ Σ. When action profile a is played and signal profile σ is realized, player i observes his corresponding signal σ i. Let m i ( a) denote the marginal distribution of i s signal. Letting ũ i (a i, σ i ) denote the payoff to player i from action a i and signal σ i, we can represent stage payoffs as a function of mixed action profiles alone: u i (α) = α (a) m i (σ i a) ũ i (a i, σ i ). a σ i Σ i Repeated game payoffs are evaluated using the discounted average criterion. The players share a common discount factor δ <. Let U i (σ) denote the expected discounted average payoff to player i in the repeated game when the players use strategy profile σ. t-length (private) history for player i is an element of H t i := ( i Σ i ) t. pair of t-length histories (called simply a history) is denoted h t. Each player s initial history is the null history, denoted. Let H t denote the set of all t-length histories, H t i the set of i s private t-length histories, H = t H t the set of all histories, and H i = t H t i the set of all private histories for i. repeated-game (behavior) strategy for player i is a mapping s i : H i i. strategy profile 8

9 is denoted s. For history h t i, let s h t i denote the continuation strategy derived from s following history h t i. Specifically, if h i ĥ i denotes the concatenation of the two histories h i and ĥi, then s hi is the strategy defined by s hi (ĥi) = s(h i ĥ i ). Given a strategy profile s, for each t and h t i H t i let B i (s h t i) denote the set of continuation strategies for i that are best replies to s i h t i. Definition strategy profile s is belief-free if for every h t, s i h t i B i (s h t i) for i =,. It is immediate that every belief-free strategy profile is a sequential equilibrium. We will therefore speak directly of belief-free equilibria. Belief-free equilibria are robust to certain perturbations in monitoring structure. For example a belief free equilibrium for a given monitoring structure remains a sequential equilibrium for any monitoring structure with the same marginal distributions. This follows because for a given continuation strategy of player i the payoff to any strategy of player i depends only on the induced distribution over the signals of player i. Thus, the set B i (s h t i) depends only on the marginal distribution over these signals. This observation implies an additional robustness property. If given s i, s i is an optimal strategy which is belief-free, then it is still optimal even if player i s ability to monitor player i s action is randomly perturbed. Conversely, if player i s strategy is robust in this sense, then it must be belief-free. Observe that public strategies in games with (perfect or imperfect) public monitoring are belief-free (because private histories are trivial). Notice also that in the literature on private monitoring, the strategies used by VPE are belief-free. On the other hand, the strategies used by Sekiguchi (997), Bhaskar and Obara (00), Mailath and Morris (00) and Matsushima (00) are not. There always exists a belief-free equilibrium, since any history-independent sequence of static equilibrium action profiles is belief-free. 3. Regimes Suppose that s is an equilibrium belief-free strategy profile. It is convenient to describe belief-free equilibria in terms of the sets of optimal actions in a given period t: t i = {a i i : h t i H t i such that s i (h t i)[a i ] > 0} We refer to t = t i t i as the regime that prevails at date t. Denote the set of all regimes by J := P( ) P( ). Every belief-free equilibrium gives rise to a sequence of (non-empty) regimes { t }. 3. Exchangeability s we show in this section, belief-free equilibria satisfy an exchangeability property, similar to the exchangeability of Nash equilibria in two-person zero sum games. In particular, given two distinct 9

10 belief-free equilibria, each governed by the same sequence of regimes, we obtain a new belief-free equilibrium by pairing player s strategy in the first equilibrium with player s strategy in the second. This property will be used to show that for any given sequence of regimes, the set of belief-free equilibrium payoffs has a product structure. Proposition Let { t } be a sequence of regimes and let s, s be two belief-free equilibria with regime sequence { t }. Then the profiles (s, s ) and ( s, s ) are also belief-free equilibria with regime sequence { t }. Proof: We will show a stronger result. ny strategy z which adheres to the regime sequence { t }, (i.e. z (h t ) t for every h t H) t is a belief-free sequential best-reply to s, i.e. z h t B (s h t ) for all t, and h t H t. It suffices to consider pure strategies z. For each t = 0,,... there exists a history h t such that the mixed action s (h t ) assigns positive probability to the pure action z (h t ). This is because z (h t ) t and t is the regime governing s in period t. We define a (continuation) strategy z h t to be the strategy which begins by playing z (h t ) and thereafter reverts to s h t. Note that z h t B (s h t ) for all t, and h t H t. This is because s h t B (s h t ) and z h t differs from s h t only in the initial period in which it plays one of the actions assigned positive probability by s h t. Now we construct a sequence of strategies for player, z t for t = 0,,.... First we set z 0 = z. Next, we inductively define z t by z(h t τ ) = z t (h τ ) if τ < t and z t h t = z h t. Observe that z t h t = z h t B (s h t ) for all t, and h t H t. Now, z t+ h t differs from z t h t only by replacing its continuation strategies with z h t+. Since this cannot reduce the payoff, we have z t+ h t B (s h t ) and by induction z t+k h t B (s h t ) for all t 0, k 0, h t. () By construction, for all k 0, z t+k (h t ) = z (h t ) and thus for any fixed h t, the sequence of continuation strategies z t+k h t converges, as k to z h t, history-by-history, i.e. in the product topology. Because discounted payoffs are continuous in the product topology, () implies which is what we set out to show. z h t B (s h t ) for all t, and h t H t. s a corollary, we have that the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs for a given sequence of regimes is a product set. Corollary Let W ({ t }) be the set of all payoffs arising from belief-free equilibria using regime sequence { t }. Then W ({ t }) = W W for some subsets W R and W R. 0

11 4 Strong Self-Generation In this section we develop a generalization of the breu, Pearce, and Stachetti (990) concept of self-generation to characterize belief-free equilibrium payoffs. Definition Let W = W W R and =. Payoff vector v R is generated by W using if for each player i there is a mixture α i i and a continuation payoff function w i : i Σ i W i such that v i ( δ)u i (a i, α i ) + δ σ i Σ i for each a i i, with equality for each a i i. α i (a i )m i (σ i a i, a i )w i (a i, σ i ) () a i i When there exists α i and w i as in the definition, say that the pair (α i, w i ) enforce i and generate v i. Let B (W ) designate the set of payoff vectors generated by W using. If W B (W ), then say that W is strongly self-generating using. Note that B (W ) is defined only in terms of marginal signal distributions, without any requirement on the joint distributions. Proposition If W is strongly self-generating using, then each element of W is a belieffree equilibrium payoff with constant regime. Conversely, the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs using the constant regime is itself a strongly self-generating set. Proof: Let v = (v i, v i ) belong to W. We will show that player i has a strategy which randomizes over i after every history against which player i s maximum payoff is v i and that this payoff is achieved by any strategy which randomizes over i after every history. Since the symmetric argument implies the same conclusion with the roles reversed, these strategies form a belief-free profile. Since W B (W ), for each u W i there is a mixture αi u i and a continuation value function w u which satisfy (). Construct a Markovian strategy for player i as follows. The i state of the strategy will be the continuation value for player i. In any stage in which the state is u, player i will play mixed action αi u. When in state u and having played action a i, and observed signal σ i, player i will transit to state w i(a u i, σ i ). The initial state will be v i. It now follows from equation () and the one-stage deviation property that when the marginal distribution of i s signal is given by m i, any strategy for player i which randomizes over i after every history is a best-reply and achieves payoff v i. To prove the converse, consider any belief-free equilibrium s with regime. Write w i (h) = U(s h ) for the continuation payoff to player i after history h. Let W i be the set of all possible continuation values for i in the equilibrium s. Formally W i = {w i (h) : h H}.

12 Let us first observe that in a belief-free equilibrium, w i (h) depends only on h i. To see why, suppose w i (h i, h i ) > w i ( h i, h i ). Then s i is not a best-reply to s hi i h i implying s is not belief-free. We can thus write w i (h) = w i (h i ). Consider any date t + and history h t. Because s is governed by regime, the mixed action α i := s i (h t i) played by i s opponent after h t belongs to i. Let a i i. Then there is a best-reply continuation strategy ŝ i for i which plays a i after history h t i; moreover, the best-reply continuation strategy must induce a best-reply after each possible subsequent history h t+ i thus ŝ i is a best-reply at each h t+ i. Because the equilibrium is belief-free, U(ŝ i, s i h t+ ) = w i(h t+ i i ) for every h t+ i. We can write h t+ i = (h t i; a i, σ i ). In this way we can view w i (h t+ i ) as a continuation value function w i (h t i;, ) taking values in W i. The payoff to i from using ŝ i against s i (h t i) can thus be written ( δ)u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i )m i (σ i a i, a i )w i (h t i; a i, σ i ) a i i σ i Σ i Since ŝ i is a best-reply against s i h t i, this is equal to w i (h t ). Moreover, since a i was an arbitrary element of i, this equality holds for all a i i. Finally since s is belief-free with regime, player i cannot achieve a greater continuation value with a strategy that begins with some action outside i. Thus, w i (h t ) must be greater than or equal to the above expression when a i / i. This shows that the pair (s i (h t i), w i (h t i;, )) enforce i and generate w i (h t ). Since h t was arbitrary, every element of W i can be so generated. pplying the same argument for player i shows that the set W = i= W i is strongly self-generating. Now let W be the union of all continuation values occurring along histories of all belief-free equilibria with regime. The set W is the union of strongly self-generating sets and is therefore strongly self-generating. The previous proposition characterized belief-free equilibria with a single regime prevailing in every period. Now suppose that W is strongly self-generating using some regime, and consider the set B (W ). Each element of this set can be generated by a mixed action profile in and continuation payoffs in W. It follows that any such payoff can be sustained by a belief-free equilibrium which begins in regime and remains in regime thereafter. We can construct more and more belief-free equilibrium payoffs by considering arbitrary sequences of regimes in this manner. Rather than pursue this directly however, we shall proceed in a slightly different way by allowing the players access to a public randomization device over regimes. t first glance, it may seem that public randomization and private monitoring do not go together, but it will be clear that public randomizations are used as a substitute for sequences of regimes in a manner similar to the case of perfect monitoring where public randomizations substitute for transitions among mixed action profiles.

13 4. Public Randomization We will suppose that in each period, the players publicly observe the outcome of a lottery over the set of regimes. The interpretation is that when a certain regime is realized in a certain period, the players will play action profiles from. Of course in equilibrium it must be optimal for a given player i to select his action from i. When the players have access to such a public randomization device a strategy now depends on private history as well as the sequence of realizations of the public randomization. The definition of belief-free equilibrium must also be appropriately modified. In particular, the set of best-replies can depend on the regime, but not on the private history. Formally, a public history of length t is a sequence y t = (,..., t ) Y t of regimes representing the outcomes of the public randomization device over the first t periods. strategy is now a mapping s i : t Hi t Y t i which specifies the mixed action to play for each public/private history pair. Continuation strategies s i (h t i,y t ) and best-reply continuation strategies B i (s (h t i, y t )) are defined as before. Definition 3 In the presence of a public randomization device, a strategy profile s is belief-free if for all t, y t t, and h t i H t i, s i (h t i,y t ) B i(s (h t i, y t )) for every h t i H t i. Strong self-generation is now defined with respect to a fixed public randomization over regimes. Definition 4 Let p J be a public randomization over regimes and W = W W a set of continuation payoffs. Say that v is p-generated by W if for each i and for each, there exist a mixture α i i and continuation value function wi : i Σ i W i such that for each a i : J i v i p() ( δ)u i (a i (), α i) + δ α i(a i )m i (σ i a i (), a i )wi (a i, σ i ) J a i i σ i Σ i (3) with equality if a i () i for each. We write v B p (W ) if v is p-generated by W. We will also abuse terminology and say that α i and wi generate v i. The set W is strongly self-generating if W B p (W ) for some public randomization p. The following proposition provides an algorithm which can be used to compute the set of all strongly self-generating payoffs for a given p. Proposition 3 For each p, there exists a maximal strongly self-generating set W. W is compact and convex. Let V be the convex hull of the feasible, individually rational payoffs. Set W 0 = B p (V ), and inductively W τ = B p (W τ ). Then W τ W τ for each τ and W = τ 0 W τ 3

14 Proof: The following observation will be used repeatedly in the proof. For any two sets W, W such that W W, if v is generated by W then v is also generated by W. Thus B p ( ) is monotonic in the sense that B p (W ) B p (W ) for W W. The union of strongly self-generating sets is itself strongly self-generating. This shows the existence of a maximal set W. We will first show that B p (W ) is convex. Let v, v be elements of B p (W ). By the definition of B p (W ), for each i and there are associated mixed actions α i(v), α i(v ) and continuation value functions wi (v) and wi (v ) used to generate v i and v i respectively. By the linearity of the inequalities in the definition of strong self-generation, any convex combination of v i and v i is generated by the corresponding convex combinations of α i(v) and α i(v ) and wi (v) and wi (v ). Since W B p (W ), monotonicity of B p ( ) implies B p (W ) B p (B p (W )) implying that B p (W ) is also strongly self-generating. But since W is maximal, B p (W ) W so that W = B p (W ). Thus, W is convex. Obviously W 0 V. Using monotonicity we conclude that W W 0 and inductively that W τ W τ. We now show that the operator B p ( ) preserves compactness. Obviously B p (W ) is bounded whenever W is. To show that B p (W ) is closed for compact W, let v r be a sequence of elements of B p (W ) with lim r v r = v. Then for each i and each regime, there are corresponding sequences (α i) r and continuation value functions (wi ) r taking values in co(w i ) used to generate vi r. By the compactness of i and co(w i ) there is a subsequence of r s such that (α i) r α i and (wi ) r (a i, σ i ) wi (a i, σ i ) co(w i ) for each of the finitely many pairs (a i, σ i ). By continuity, α i and wi generate v i, and therefore v B p (W ). Since V is compact and B p ( ) preserves compactness, W 0 and by induction each W τ are compact. Thus W τ is a nested sequence of compact sets and the set W := τ 0 W τ is compact. We now show that W is strongly self-generating. Let v W. Then for every τ there exist (α i) τ and (wi ) τ : i Σ i Wi τ which generate v i. We claim that there exist limit continuation values wi (a i, σ i ) W such that (passing to a subsequence if necessary) (wi ) τ (a i, σ i ) wi (a i, σ i ) for each pair (a i, σ i ). If not, then there exist a pair (a i, σ i ) and an open neighborhood U of W such that (wi ) τ (a i, σ i ) / U for infinitely many τ. This implies that U W τ for these τ. But U W τ is an infinite family of nested, non-empty, compact sets and hence, τ 0 [ U W τ ] = U τ 0 W τ = U W which is a contradiction. 4

15 gain, by continuity v i is generated by lim(α i) τ (passing to a further subsequence if necessary) and w i. Thus v B p (W ) and we have shown that W is strongly self-generating. It remains only to show that W includes W, which by the maximality of W would imply that W = W and conclude the proof. Since W V, we have W = B p (W ) W 0 and by induction W W τ for every τ. Thus W W. We can adapt the proof of Proposition to show that W is exactly the set of belief-free equilibrium payoffs using public randomization p. Proposition 4 Fix a public randomization p. The corresponding set W is equal to the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs using the public randomization p. s a corollary we can further characterize the structure of belief-free equilibrium payoff sets. Corollary For any given public randomization p, the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs using p is the product of closed intervals. Proof: Proposition and Corollary generalize immediately to a public randomization device, and the statement then follows from Corollary, Proposition 3, and Proposition Bang-Bang In this section we show that belief-free equilibrium payoffs can always be obtained by simple strategies that can be represented by a two-state automaton. s a corollary we obtain a version of the traditional bang-bang result that a set is strongly self-generating if and only if the set generates its extreme points. machine strategy for player i is defined as follows. There is a set of states Θ, and for each state θ Θ there is a behavior rule α θ : P() i and a transition rule φ θ : P() i Σ i Θ. The interpretation is as follows. When in state θ, if the outcome of the public randomization is regime, the strategy plays α θ (). Then, if the action a i is realized and the signal σ i is observed, a new state is drawn from the distribution φ θ (, a i, σ i ) and the strategy begins the next period in that state. Imagine that i were playing such a machine strategy and player i was informed each period of the state. Then we could compute the value v(θ) to player i of being in state θ. Furthermore, the transition rule would imply for each state the continuation value function w as follows i w i (a i, σ i ) = θ Θ v(θ ) φ θ (, a i, σ i )[θ ] Note that in the proof of Proposition we construct such a machine strategy whose continuation value functions replicate the continuation value functions used in the definition of strong 5

16 self-generation. In fact as we now show it is always possible to implement a belief-free equilibrium payoff using machine strategies which have only two states. 5 The values of the two states in i s machine correspond to the maximum and minimum belief-free equilibrium payoffs of player i. Proposition 5 Consider intervals V i = [v i, v i ] for i =,. Let ρ be a public randomization over regimes. Suppose for each i that v i is p-generated by V i using α i and w i and similarly for v i using ᾱ i and w i. Then every element v of V V is the payoff to a belief-free equilibrium in which each i plays a machine strategy with two states {θ, θ} whose behavior rules are α i, ᾱi respectively and whose derived continuation value functions are w i, w i, respectively. Proof: dapt the Markovian strategy used in the proof of Proposition as follows. There are only two states, corresponding to values v i and v i. Now, when then continuation value should be w [v i, v i ], player i will randomly transit to states v i and v i with probabilities q and q where w = qv i + ( q) v i. Finally, player i determines his initial state by similarly randomizing over the two states with probabilities calculated to provide initial value v i. The equilibria provided by proposition 5 satisfy a stronger robustness property than belieffree alone. To see this suppose that ᾱ i and α i are pure actions for each regime. In the initial period i is determining his state, and hence his initial action by randomizing. Regardless of the realization of this randomization, player i is indifferent over his actions in the regime. Thus, the equilibrium strategy of player i remains a best-reply even if before play i could observe the outcome of i s private randomization. 5 Characterizing Belief-Free Equilibrium Payoffs for δ close to 5. General Information Structure The preceding results can be used to determine the set of belief-free equilibrium payoffs for any given discount factor δ. When instead we are interested in the limit of these sets as δ approaches, a simpler characterization is available as we describe in this section. To get a feel for the techniques presented here, consider a fixed regime, and for the moment a given discount factor δ. Let W (δ) be the set of belief-free equilibrium payoffs given δ, using the constant regime. From previous results, we know that W (δ) is the product of closed intervals, so W (δ) = W (δ) W (δ). Let us write W (δ) = [w, w]. Because W (δ) is strongly self-generating (by Proposition 4), both w and w are generated by W (δ). Furthermore, w is the maximum value w generated by the interval [w, w], for if 5 In a related context, Kandori and Obara (003) also examine conditions under which two-state automata are sufficient. 6

17 w > w were generated by [w, w], then by Proposition 5, the set [w, w] W (δ) would be strongly self-generating, contradicting the definition of W (δ). Thus, w solves the following optimization problem w = max w such that for some α and w : Σ R [ ] w ( δ)u (a, α ) + δ α (a )m (σ a, a )w (a, σ ) a σ Σ for each a, with equality for each a. w (a, σ ) w a, σ w (a, σ ) w a, σ. Similarly, w is the minimum value w generated by the interval [w, w], and is thus the solution to the corresponding minimization problem. Conversely, the solutions to these problems characterize the boundaries of W (δ) whenever it is non-empty. Observe that for δ close to, the differences in continuation values required to satisfy the incentive constraints in the above problem can be made arbitrarily small. Thus, when w > w, the last constraint can always be satisfied when δ is close enough to. s a further simplification, let us define x (a, σ ) = δ [w δ (a, σ ) w] 0, substitute out for w (, ), and rewrite the maximization as follows. w = max w such that for some α and x : Σ R w u (a, α ) + α (a ) m (σ a, a ) x (a, σ ), a σ Σ with equality if a. We can interpret this characterization as follows. Player will select a mixed action α and levy fines x (a, σ ) on player depending on the realized action and signal. The objective is to induce player to select any action in and to provide the maximum total utility to player in the process. That maximum will turn out to be player s maximum belief-free equilibrium payoff using regime when δ is close to. To find the minimum, we analyze the corresponding minimization problem with the difference that player will offer bonuses rather than fines. In what follows, we formalize and extend this analysis to the case of an arbitrary public randomization over regimes and use it to characterize the set of all belief-free equilibrium payoffs for δ close to. For given = i i, define Mi as follows: 7

18 v i u i (a i, α i ) + Mi = sup v i such that for some (4) α i i x i : i Σ i R a i i σ i Σ i α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) x i (a i, σ i ), for all a i with equality if a i i. Similalry, define m i as follows: v i u i (a i, α i ) + m i = inf v i such that for some (5) a i i α i i x i : i Σ i R + σ i Σ i α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) x i (a i, σ i ), for all a i with equality if a i i. Here and in what follows, sup = and inf = +. The solutions to these linear programs will be used to provide tight bounds on the sets of belief-free equilibrium payoffs. 6 The set of payoffs inside the bounds will be shown to be strongly self-generating and therefore belief-free. On the other hand, it will be shown that any belief-free equilibrium value will be in the set. The following preliminary result is useful in the sequel. Lemma Every v i < M i is feasible for (4) and every v i > m i is feasible for (5). Let us order the regimes as J = {,..., J}. For i =,, let M i = ( ), Mi,..., Mi J and m i = ( ). m i,..., m J i Let M i = Mi m i and M i = M i m i. We distinguish the following three cases.. (The positive case) There exists p 0 such that M i p > 0, i =,.. (The negative case) There exists no p 0 such that M i p 0, i =,, with at least one strict inequality. 3. (The abnormal case) There exists no p 0 such that M i p > 0, i =,, but there exists p 0 such that M i p 0, i =,, with one strict inequality. 6 s formulated, these programs are not linear in (α i, x i ); they are however linear in (α i, y i ), where y i = α i x i : i Σ i R or R +. 8

19 Observe that which case obtains depends both on the stage game payoffs and on the monitoring structure. For a given stage game, let V be the limit of the set of (belief-free) equilibrium payoffs when δ. We claim that: Theorem V is a convex polytope. In. the positive case, V = {p 0: Mi p 0,i=,,p=} [m i p, M i p] ; (6). the negative case, V is the convex hull of the Nash equilibria of the bimatrix game; Proof: Consider the positive case. We first show that the right-hand side of (6) is included in V. We pick for each payoffs v, v, v, v and a public randomization p over regimes such that m i < v i Mi > v i and i=, p ( v i v i ) > 0 i =, (7) where e.g. v i = (v i ) J. Existence is guaranteed by the positive case. Define z i = p v i, z i = p v i. We will show that there exists δ < such that for all δ ( δ, ), the set U defined by U = co {z i, z i } i=, is strongly self-generating. Because the right-hand side of (6) is the closure of the union of all such sets U, this will prove its inclusion in V. By Proposition 5, it is enough to show that each of the extreme values is generated by the convex hull. Consider v i. Since Mi > v i, by Lemma, v i is a feasible value for (4) and hence there exists ᾱ i i and x i : i Σ i R such that for every a i () i ( ) v i u i ai (), ᾱ i + a i i σ i Σ i ᾱ i(a i )m i (σ i a i (), a i ) x i (a i, σ i ), (8) with equality if a i () i. (9) For each we multiply the above inequality by p() and then sum across regimes to find that for all strategies {a i ()} J, z i J ( ) p() u i ai (), ᾱ i + a i i ᾱ i(a i )m i (σ i a i (), a i ) x i (a i, σ i ), σ i Σ i with equality if a i () i for each. (0) 9

20 Define w i (a i, σ i ) = z i + δ x i (a i, σ δ i ) () substitute into (0), and re-arrange to obtain z i ( ) p() ( δ)u i ai (), ᾱ i + δ ᾱ i(a i )m i (σ i a i (), a i ) w i (a i, σ i ), J σ i Σ i a i i with equality if a i () i for each. Because x i (, ) 0, it follows from () and (7) that for all δ exceeding some δ <, w i (, ) belongs to U i. We have therefore shown that the extreme point z = ( z, z ) is generated by U. The symmetric derivation shows that z is generated by U. Let α i, and w i the corresponding strategies and continuation value functions. Now it is easily verified that e.g. the value (z i, z i ) is generated using α i, w i and ᾱ i, w i. Next we show that the right-hand side of (6) includes V. Observe that ( δ) Mi + δ V solves max ( δ) u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) V i (a i, σ i ) () α i i V i : i Σ i R a i i σ i Σ i subject to, for all a i i, a i i (with equality if a i i ), ( δ)u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i ) m i (σ i (a i, a i )) V i (a i, σ i ) a i i σ i Σ i ( δ) u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i ) m i (σ i (a i, a i )) V i (a i, σ i ) σ i Σ i Similarly, ( δ) m i a i i V i (a i, σ i ) V for all (a i, σ i ) i Σ i + δv solves min ( δ) u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i i V i : i Σ i R a i i (3) σ i Σ i α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) V i (a i, σ i ) (4) subject to, for all a i i, a i i (with equality if a i i ), ( δ)u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) V i (a i, σ i ) a i i σ i Σ i ( δ) u i (a i, α i ) + δ α i (a i ) m i (σ i a i, a i ) V i (a i, σ i ) σ i Σ i a i i V i (a i, σ i ) V for all (a i, σ i ) i Σ i (5) 0

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Equivalence of Public Mixed-Strategies and Private Behavior Strategies in Games with Public Monitoring Massimiliano Amarante Discussion

More information

Folk Theorems with Bounded Recall under (Almost) Perfect Monitoring

Folk Theorems with Bounded Recall under (Almost) Perfect Monitoring Folk Theorems with Bounded Recall under (Almost) Perfect Monitoring George J. Mailath Wojciech Olszewski May 30, 2008 Abstract A strategy profile in a repeated game has bounded recall L if play under the

More information

Computing Equilibria of Repeated And Dynamic Games

Computing Equilibria of Repeated And Dynamic Games Computing Equilibria of Repeated And Dynamic Games Şevin Yeltekin Carnegie Mellon University ICE 2012 July 2012 1 / 44 Introduction Repeated and dynamic games have been used to model dynamic interactions

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 25, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Uniqueness of a Pure Nash Equilibrium for Continuous Games Reading: Rosen J.B., Existence

More information

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES PRISCILLA T. Y. MAN Abstract. Reputation is often modelled by a small but positive prior probability that a player is a behavioral type in repeated games. This paper

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

A Foundation for Markov Equilibria in Infinite Horizon Perfect Information Games

A Foundation for Markov Equilibria in Infinite Horizon Perfect Information Games A Foundation for Markov Equilibria in Infinite Horizon Perfect Information Games V. Bhaskar, George J. Mailath and Stephen Morris March 5, 2009 Abstract We study perfect information games with an infinite

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games journal of economic theory 82, 267276 (1998) article no. ET982418 Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games Atsushi Kajii* Institute of Policy and Planning Sciences, University of Tsukuba, 1-1-1

More information

Efficiency results in N player games with imperfect private monitoring

Efficiency results in N player games with imperfect private monitoring Efficiency results in N player games with imperfect private monitoring Yuichi Yamamoto Graduate School of Economics, University of Tokyo The First Version: November 15, 2003 This Version: May 13, 2004

More information

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring

Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring Repeated Games with Perfect Monitoring Ichiro Obara April 17, 2006 We study repeated games with perfect monitoring (and complete information). In this class of repeated games, players can observe the other

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Optimal Shirking in Teams

Optimal Shirking in Teams Optimal Shirking in Teams Hajime Kobayashi Osaka Prefecture University Katsunori Ohta Wakayama University November 18, 2009 Tadashi Sekiguchi Kyoto University Abstract We study a model of repeated team

More information

Endogenous Monitoring

Endogenous Monitoring Endogenous Monitoring Michihiro Kandori Department of Economics University of Tokyo Ichiro Obara Department of Economics UCLA December 2, 2004 Abstract In the standard model of dynamic interaction, players

More information

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA MARIA GOLTSMAN Abstract. This note shows that, in separable environments, any monotonic social choice function

More information

Copyright (C) 2013 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of the Creative

Copyright (C) 2013 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of the Creative Copyright (C) 2013 David K. Levine This document is an open textbook; you can redistribute it and/or modify it under the terms of the Creative Commons attribution license http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0/

More information

Local Communication in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring

Local Communication in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring Local Communication in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring M Laclau To cite this version: M Laclau. Local Communication in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring. 2012. HAL Id: hal-01285070

More information

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax Title: The Castle on the Hill Author: David K. Levine Department of Economics UCLA Los Angeles, CA 90095 phone/fax 310-825-3810 email dlevine@ucla.edu Proposed Running Head: Castle on the Hill Forthcoming:

More information

Game Theory and Rationality

Game Theory and Rationality April 6, 2015 Notation for Strategic Form Games Definition A strategic form game (or normal form game) is defined by 1 The set of players i = {1,..., N} 2 The (usually finite) set of actions A i for each

More information

The Nash-Threats Folk Theorem with Communication and Approximate Common Knowledge in Two Player Games

The Nash-Threats Folk Theorem with Communication and Approximate Common Knowledge in Two Player Games he ash-hreats Folk heorem with Communication and pproximate Common Knowledge in wo Player Games he Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. our

More information

The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies

The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies The Folk Theorem for Finitely Repeated Games with Mixed Strategies Olivier Gossner February 1994 Revised Version Abstract This paper proves a Folk Theorem for finitely repeated games with mixed strategies.

More information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Seungjin Han May 20, 2011 Abstract In common agency problems, competing principals often incentivize a privately-informed agent s action choice

More information

Effi ciency in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring

Effi ciency in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring Effi ciency in Repeated Games with Local Monitoring Francesco Nava and Michele Piccione London School of Economics April 2013 Nava & Piccione (LSE) Local Monitoring April 2013 1 / 68 General Motivation

More information

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY 1 / 32 BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch May 15, 217: Lecture 1 2 / 32 Plan Normal form games Equilibrium invariance Equilibrium

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Asu Ozdaglar MIT March 2, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Review of Supermodular Games Reading: Fudenberg and Tirole, Section 12.3.

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction CRITICAL TYPES JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. Economic models employ assumptions about agents infinite hierarchies of belief. We might hope to achieve reasonable approximations by specifying

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Shaili Jain 1 and David C. Parkes 2 1 Yale University, New Haven, CT shaili.jain@yale.edu 2 Harvard University, Cambridge, MA parkes@eecs.harvard.edu Abstract.

More information

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Mark Fey Department of Political Science University of Rochester

More information

REPEATED GAMES. Jörgen Weibull. April 13, 2010

REPEATED GAMES. Jörgen Weibull. April 13, 2010 REPEATED GAMES Jörgen Weibull April 13, 2010 Q1: Can repetition induce cooperation? Peace and war Oligopolistic collusion Cooperation in the tragedy of the commons Q2: Can a game be repeated? Game protocols

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

Repeated Games with Almost-Public Monitoring 1

Repeated Games with Almost-Public Monitoring 1 Journal of Economic Theory 102, 189 228 (2002) doi:10.1006/jeth.2001.2869, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Repeated Games with Almost-Public Monitoring 1 George J. Mailath Department

More information

The Robustness of Repeated Game Equilibria to Incomplete Payoff Information

The Robustness of Repeated Game Equilibria to Incomplete Payoff Information The Robustness of Repeated Game Equilibria to Incomplete Payoff Information V.Bhaskar Dept. of Economics, University of Essex, UK Current version: April 2000 Abstract We analyse the role of mixed strategies

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Reputations. Larry Samuelson. Yale University. February 13, 2013

Reputations. Larry Samuelson. Yale University. February 13, 2013 Reputations Larry Samuelson Yale University February 13, 2013 I. Introduction I.1 An Example: The Chain Store Game Consider the chain-store game: Out In Acquiesce 5, 0 2, 2 F ight 5,0 1, 1 If played once,

More information

An Example of a Repeated Partnership Game with Discounting and with Uniformly Inefficient Equilibria

An Example of a Repeated Partnership Game with Discounting and with Uniformly Inefficient Equilibria Review of Economic Studies (1986) LIII, 059-069 @ 1986 The Society for Economic Analysis Limited An Example of a Repeated Partnership Game with Discounting and with Uniformly Inefficient Equilibria ROY

More information

Correlated Equilibria of Classical Strategic Games with Quantum Signals

Correlated Equilibria of Classical Strategic Games with Quantum Signals Correlated Equilibria of Classical Strategic Games with Quantum Signals Pierfrancesco La Mura Leipzig Graduate School of Management plamura@hhl.de comments welcome September 4, 2003 Abstract Correlated

More information

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Published as: Bhaskar Chakravorti and John P. Conley (2004) Bargaining Efficiency and the repeated Prisoners

More information

Order of limits in reputations

Order of limits in reputations Order of limits in reputations Nuh Aygün Dalkıran Theory and Decision An International Journal for Multidisciplinary Advances in Decision Science ISSN 0040-5833 Volume 81 Number 3 Theory Decis (2016) 81:393-411

More information

Less is More: An Observability Paradox in Repeated Games

Less is More: An Observability Paradox in Repeated Games Less is More: An Observability Paradox in Repeated Games KANDORI, Michihiro Faculty of Economics University of Tokyo OBARA, Ichiro Department of Economics UCLA August 8, 2006 Abstract We present a repeated

More information

Belief-free Equilibria in Games with Incomplete Information: Characterization and Existence

Belief-free Equilibria in Games with Incomplete Information: Characterization and Existence Belief-free Equilibria in Games with Incomplete Information: Characterization and Existence Johannes Hörner, Stefano Lovo, Tristan Tomala September 8, 2009 Abstract We characterize belief-free equilibria

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

Repeated Implementation with Finite Mechanisms and Complexity

Repeated Implementation with Finite Mechanisms and Complexity Repeated Implementation with Finite Mechanisms and Complexity Jihong Lee Seoul National University Hamid Sabourian University of Cambridge September 2012 Abstract This paper examines the problem of repeatedly

More information

1 The General Definition

1 The General Definition MS&E 336 Lecture 1: Dynamic games Ramesh Johari April 4, 2007 1 The General Definition A dynamic game (or extensive game, or game in extensive form) consists of: A set of players N; A set H of sequences

More information

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments University of Pennsylvania Department of Economics June 22, 2008 Introduction: Higher Order Beliefs Global Games (Carlsson and Van Damme, 1993): A B A 0, 0 0, θ 2 B θ 2, 0 θ, θ Dominance Regions: A if

More information

Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication)

Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication) Appendix B for The Evolution of Strategic Sophistication (Intended for Online Publication) Nikolaus Robalino and Arthur Robson Appendix B: Proof of Theorem 2 This appendix contains the proof of Theorem

More information

Bounding Equilibrium Payoffs in Repeated Games with Private Monitoring

Bounding Equilibrium Payoffs in Repeated Games with Private Monitoring Bounding Equilibrium Payoffs in Repeated Games with Private Monitoring Takuo Sugaya and Alexander Wolitzky Stanford Graduate School of Business and MIT April 27, 2016 Abstract We provide a simple suffi

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. In games with incomplete information, conventional hierarchies of belief are incomplete as descriptions of

More information

Efficient Repeated Implementation

Efficient Repeated Implementation Efficient Repeated Implementation Jihong Lee Yonsei University and Birkbeck College, London Hamid Sabourian University of Cambridge September 2009 Abstract This paper examines repeated implementation of

More information

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War.

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War. Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War. Online Appendix Alexandre Debs and Nuno P. Monteiro May 10, 2016 he Appendix is structured as follows. Section 1 offers proofs of the formal results

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Imperfect Monitoring and Impermanent Reputations

Imperfect Monitoring and Impermanent Reputations Imperfect Monitoring and Impermanent Reputations Martin W. Cripps Olin School of Business Washington University in St. Louis St. Louis, MO 63130-4899 cripps@olin.wustl.edu George J. Mailath Department

More information

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium YUICHIRO KAMADA 1 Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 Abstract Fudenberg and Levine (1993a) introduce the notion of self-confirming

More information

Continuous Time Limits of Repeated Games with Imperfect Public Monitoring 1

Continuous Time Limits of Repeated Games with Imperfect Public Monitoring 1 Continuous Time Limits of Repeated Games with Imperfect Public Monitoring 1 Drew Fudenberg and David K. Levine 2 This version: 5/25/2007 First version: 12/15/2005 Abstract: In a repeated game with imperfect

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information joint with Stephen Morris (Princeton University) November 2010 Payoff Environment in games with incomplete information, the agents are uncertain

More information

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (50b) Problem Set 0. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann 4/5/4 This problem set is due on Tuesday, 4//4..

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Leonardo Felli EC441: Room D.106, Z.332, D.109 Lecture 8 bis: 24 November 2004 Monopoly Consider now the pricing behavior of a profit maximizing monopolist: a firm that is the only

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

A Foundation for Markov Equilibria with Finite Social Memory

A Foundation for Markov Equilibria with Finite Social Memory A Foundation for Markov Equilibria with Finite Social Memory V. Bhaskar, George J. Mailath, and Stephen Morris January 31, 2012 Abstract We study stochastic games with an infinite horizon and sequential

More information

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Dov Monderer and Moshe Tennenholtz Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa 32000,

More information

On the Equilibrium Payoff Set in Repeated Games with Imperfect Private Monitoring

On the Equilibrium Payoff Set in Repeated Games with Imperfect Private Monitoring On the Equilibrium Payoff Set in Repeated Games with Imperfect Private Monitoring Takuo Sugaya and Alexander Wolitzky Stanford Graduate School of Business and MIT August 24, 2015 Abstract We provide a

More information

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations *

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * by Magnus Hatlebakk ** Department of Economics, University of Bergen Abstract: We present a new subgame perfect equilibrium

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static Information Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Frontiers of Economic Theory & Computer Science, Becker-Friedman Institute, August 2016 Mechanism Design and Information Design Basic Mechanism

More information

Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games

Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games Gabriel Y. Weintraub, Lanier Benkard, and Benjamin Van Roy Stanford University {gweintra,lanierb,bvr}@stanford.edu Abstract

More information

Consistent Beliefs in Extensive Form Games

Consistent Beliefs in Extensive Form Games Games 2010, 1, 415-421; doi:10.3390/g1040415 OPEN ACCESS games ISSN 2073-4336 www.mdpi.com/journal/games Article Consistent Beliefs in Extensive Form Games Paulo Barelli 1,2 1 Department of Economics,

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem MS&E 336 Lecture 8: Supermodular games Ramesh Johari April 30, 2007 In this lecture, we develop the theory of supermodular games; key references are the papers of Topkis [7], Vives [8], and Milgrom and

More information

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values Anastasios Dosis ESSEC Business School and THEMA École Polytechnique/CREST, 3/10/2018 Anastasios Dosis (ESSEC and THEMA) Informed Principal with Common

More information

Deterministic Calibration and Nash Equilibrium

Deterministic Calibration and Nash Equilibrium University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Statistics Papers Wharton Faculty Research 2-2008 Deterministic Calibration and Nash Equilibrium Sham M. Kakade Dean P. Foster University of Pennsylvania Follow

More information

Community Enforcement beyond the Prisoner s Dilemma

Community Enforcement beyond the Prisoner s Dilemma Community Enforcement beyond the Prisoner s Dilemma Joyee Deb New York University Julio González-Díaz University of Santiago de Compostela PRELIMINARY (April 2010) Abstract We study two-player games played

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 1 Outline Introduction Syllabus Web demonstration Examples 2 About Me: Peter Cramton B.S. Engineering, Cornell University Ph.D. Business

More information

Immediately Reactive Equilibria in Infinitely Repeated Games with Additively Separable Continuous Payoffs

Immediately Reactive Equilibria in Infinitely Repeated Games with Additively Separable Continuous Payoffs Immediately Reactive Equilibria in Infinitely Repeated Games with Additively Separable Continuous Payoffs Takashi Kamihigashi and Taiji Furusawa December 21, 2006 Abstract This paper studies a class of

More information

Basics of Game Theory

Basics of Game Theory Basics of Game Theory Giacomo Bacci and Luca Sanguinetti Department of Information Engineering University of Pisa, Pisa, Italy {giacomo.bacci,luca.sanguinetti}@iet.unipi.it April - May, 2010 G. Bacci and

More information

Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal

Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Games on Social Networks: On a Problem Posed by Goyal Ali Kakhbod Demosthenis Teneketzis November 13, 2017 arxiv:1001.3896v4 [cs.gt] 9 Feb 2012 Abstract Within the context of games on networks S. Goyal

More information

Global Dynamics in Repeated Games with Additively Separable Payoffs

Global Dynamics in Repeated Games with Additively Separable Payoffs Global Dynamics in Repeated Games with Additively Separable Payoffs Takashi Kamihigashi and Taiji Furusawa June 8, 200 Abstract This paper studies the global dynamics of a class of infinitely repeated

More information

A Primer on Strategic Games

A Primer on Strategic Games A Primer on Strategic Games Krzysztof R. Apt Abstract This is a short introduction to the subject of strategic games. We focus on the concepts of best response, Nash equilibrium, strict and weak dominance,

More information

Bertrand-Edgeworth Equilibrium in Oligopoly

Bertrand-Edgeworth Equilibrium in Oligopoly Bertrand-Edgeworth Equilibrium in Oligopoly Daisuke Hirata Graduate School of Economics, University of Tokyo March 2008 Abstract This paper investigates a simultaneous move capacity constrained price competition

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Ilan Lobel, Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh and Asuman Ozdaglar ABSTRACT We study a model of social learning with partial observations from

More information

When is the individually rational payoff in a repeated game equal to the minmax payoff?

When is the individually rational payoff in a repeated game equal to the minmax payoff? When is the individually rational payoff in a repeated game equal to the minmax payoff? Olivier Gossner and Johannes Hörner November 21, 2006 Abstract We study the relationship between a player s (stage

More information

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information)

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information) Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan 200 Good luck!!! Question (duopoly games with imperfect information) Consider a duopoly game in which the inverse demand function is linear where it is positive

More information

Asymmetric Social Norms

Asymmetric Social Norms Asymmetric Social Norms Gabriele Camera Chapman University University of Basel Alessandro Gioffré Goethe University December 8, 2016 Abstract Studies of cooperation in infinitely repeated matching games

More information

Subgame-Perfection in Quitting Games with Perfect Information and Differential Equations

Subgame-Perfection in Quitting Games with Perfect Information and Differential Equations Subgame-Perfection in Quitting Games with Perfect Information and Differential Equations Eilon Solan September 3, 2002 Abstract We introduce a new approach to study subgame-perfect equilibrium payoffs

More information

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring M. W. Cripps, G. Mailath, L. Samuelson UCL, Northwestern, Pennsylvania, Yale Theory Workshop Reputation Effects or Equilibrium Robustness Reputation Effects: Kreps,

More information

Delayed-Response Strategies in Repeated Games with Observation Lags

Delayed-Response Strategies in Repeated Games with Observation Lags Delayed-Response Strategies in Repeated Games with Observation Lags Drew Fudenberg Yuhta Ishii Scott Duke Kominers First Version: September 23, 2011 This Version: August 19, 2013 Abstract We extend the

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION. Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION. Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES PRICE AND CAPACITY COMPETITION Daron Acemoglu Kostas Bimpikis Asuman Ozdaglar Working Paper 12804 http://www.nber.org/papers/w12804 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts

More information

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper No. 1848 ON THE LIMIT EQUILIBRIUM PAYOFF SET IN REPEATED AND STOCHASTIC GAMES Johannes Hörner, Satoru Takahashi

More information

Microeconomics. 2. Game Theory

Microeconomics. 2. Game Theory Microeconomics 2. Game Theory Alex Gershkov http://www.econ2.uni-bonn.de/gershkov/gershkov.htm 18. November 2008 1 / 36 Dynamic games Time permitting we will cover 2.a Describing a game in extensive form

More information

Nash-solvable bidirected cyclic two-person game forms

Nash-solvable bidirected cyclic two-person game forms DIMACS Technical Report 2008-13 November 2008 Nash-solvable bidirected cyclic two-person game forms by Endre Boros 1 RUTCOR, Rutgers University 640 Bartholomew Road, Piscataway NJ 08854-8003 boros@rutcor.rutgers.edu

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Game Theory 1 / 43 Introduction Why game theory? In the introductory lecture, we defined Industrial Organization as the economics

More information