Risk Assessment under Ambiguity: Precautionary Learning vs. Research Pessimism

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Risk Assessment under Ambiguity: Precautionary Learning vs. Research Pessimism"

Transcription

1 Risk Assessment under Ambiguity: Precautionary Learning vs. Research Pessimism Daniel Heyen Grantham Research Institute London School of Economics Boris Wiesenfarth Independent Researcher September 14, 2017 Timo Goeschl Department of Economics Heidelberg University Abstract Agencies charged with regulating complex risks frequently need to take decisions on risk assessment and risk management under conditions of ambiguity. What mandates should society write for such agencies? Two approaches stand out: Costbenefit analysis (CBA) based on expected utility theory and the Precautionary Principle (PP) based on maxmin expected utility (MEU). Using a model in which the agency can decide on the precision of a signal which provides noisy information on a payoff-relevant parameter, we compare CBA and PP. Contrary to intuition, a PP mandate will often give rise to a less informed regulator, making regulatory mistakes more likely. Keywords: scientific uncertainty; ambiguity; learning; risk assessment; precautionary principle; active information acquisition; regulatory mandates. JEL codes: D81, D83, Q58. We are grateful to Gregor Betz, Valentina Bosetti, Simon Dietz, Adam Dominiak, Juergen Eichberger, Itzhak Gilboa, Simon Grant, Antony Millner, Juan Moreno-Cruz, Joerg Oechssler, Frank Riedel, Bernard Sinclair-Desgagné, Christian Traeger, Nicolas Treich, and participants at the conferences AU- ROE 2012 Bern, Spring Meeting of Young Economists 2012 Mannheim, AERE 2012 Asheville, EAERE 2012 Prague, Workshop on Irreversible Choices 2012 in Brescia, the Harvard Geoengineering Summer School 2013 and the workshop and seminars at the Grantham Research Institute at LSE, the Department of Economics Heidelberg, FEEM, IASS, ZEW, Heidelberg Geoengineering Forum for their helpful comments and suggestions. The first two authors acknowledge the support of the German Research Foundation, grant no. GO 1604/2. Daniel Heyen also acknowledges support through the German Research Foundation s Postdoctoral Research Fellowship HE 7551/1-1. 1

2 1 Introduction In the early summer of 2011, the European Union experienced an outbreak of Shigatoxin producing Escherichia coli (STEC). 1 More than 3,100 cases of bloody diarrhoea and more than 850 of haemolytic uremic syndrome (HUS), a serious condition that can lead to kidney failure, were reported during the outbreak. deaths (EFSA 2012). There were 53 confirmed The outbreak of STEC was linked through epidemiological research to the consumption of fresh salad vegetables (BfR 2012). Because research found toxin producing E.coli on cucumbers from Spain, European Commission and German officials issued alerts and effectively required Spanish cucumbers to be withdrawn from the market (BBC 2011; BfR 2012). These events saddled Spanish vegetable growers, among others, with economic damages of several hundred millions of Euros (BBC 2011). After more research commissioned by the European Food Safety Authority (EFSA) and the German Interior Ministry, however, it became clear that officials had in all likelihood misidentified the source: Bean sprouts from a German farm, rather than contaminated Spanish cucumbers, carried the dangerous strain that gave rise to potentially lethal HUS among consumers (BfR 2012). While acknowledged as the most likely source, an entirely conclusive result on the cause of the outbreak has never been established. The STEC incident from 2011 typifies an important recurring problem for regulators. Here, a regulator was called upon to make decisions affecting both public mortality and morbidity risk and economic livelihoods on the basis of ambiguous evidence on the source of risk. Not only did the regulator have to make a risk management decision, viz. to decide on which produce to ban in order to eliminate the source of risk, thus imposing damages of several hundred million Euros on its producers. The regulator also had to decide on the scale of risk assessment, viz. collecting and screening thousands of samples in order to reduce the risk of erroneously banning harmless produce while allowing harmful produce to continue to be sold. Situations in which a regulator needs to take a highly consequential decision based on poor, but improvable knowledge, are commonplace in today s world (Kaebnick et al. 2016; Sunstein 2005a; Randall 2011; Graham 2001). This raises the question of what rules should govern these decisions. Differently put, under what mandate should a regulator reach its decisions on assessment and management of risks? Two approaches for writing this mandate stand out in the current discussion. One is the use of a traditional welfare-economic approach based on expected utility theory. This is the approach that underpins most forms of conventional cost-benefit analysis (CBA) (Viscusi et al. 2005). 2 The other is the Precautionary Principle (PP). Despite lacking a clear definition and being criticized on grounds of internally inconsistency and logical incoherence (Peterson 2006; Sunstein 2005b), the PP has been adopted by the European Commission (Eu- 1 The outbreak was first incorrectly classified as EHEC and has become widely known under this label. 2 This traditional approach is prone to subtleties as well, cf. Martin and Pindyck (2015). 2

3 ropean Commission 2000) and gained significance of a general principle of EU law (Recuerda 2006). The PP has several connotations, all of them rooted in the presence of fundamental uncertainties that challenge traditional risk assessments. One of these interpretations of the PP requests the regulator to build a margin of safety and avoid harm when the causal chain is subject to scientific uncertainty, and thus to prepare against unfavourable events (Zander 2010; Sunstein 2005c). A related, yet distinct, interpretation of the PP directly targets the level of information under which the regulator has to make her decision. In this widespread view, regulatory mandates based on the PP would lead to more science (Tickner 2002) and thus a better informed regulatory decision than conventional CBA mandates (Cranor 2005; Myers and Raffensberger 2005; Martuzzi 2007; Bourg and Whiteside 2009). How to meaningfully compare the implications of CBA and PP? Over the last decades, the literature on decision-making under uncertainty has offered alternatives to the subjective expected utility framework (Savage 1954) which underpins traditional CBA (Dasgupta and Pearce 1972; Shaw and Woodward 2008). These non-expected utility frameworks provide several coherent rationalizations of ambiguity averse preferences (Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989; Klibanoff et al. 2005; Chateauneuf et al. 2007), forming the decision-theoretic foundations of the PP in applications (Asano 2010; Athanassoglou and Xepapadeas 2012; Barrieu and Sinclair-Desgagné 2006; Basili et al. 2008; Gollier and Treich 2003; Lemoine and Traeger 2012; Millner et al. 2013; Treich 2010; Courbage et al. 2013; Vardas and Xepapadeas 2010). Despite being important steps into a solid economic foundation of the PP, these contributions do not focus on informational choices and are hence not capable of shedding light on the interplay of regulatory decision and research effort that was at the heart of the risk regulatory challenge during the STEC outbreak. Other contributions that put informational choices centre-stage (Gollier et al. 2000; Gollier and Treich 2003) maintains standard preferences that cannot capture the ambiguous state of knowledge that complicates many regulatory problems. The purpose of the present paper is to fill this gap and analyse the interplay of the PP with investments to improve the risk assessment precision. For this purpose, we study a model of active learning under ambiguity averse preferences. 3 We operationalize the PP as maxmin expected utility preferences (meu) (Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989), arguably the best-known axiomatization of ambiguity aversion. The maxmin rule is conceptually simple and, by avoiding some of the reservations against the idea of precaution, provides a relatively modest operationalization of the PP: Like other ambiguity averse decision-rules, meu offers a transparent framework for assessing different policy options that explicitly balances the costs and benefits of regulation. Also, and often a source of confusion, the maxmin rule in this form is sensitive to levels of uncertainty and infor- 3 The reader familiar with decision theory may be surprised to see the terms risk and ambiguity often appear next to each other in the present paper. We use the term risk here in the broad sense used in the risk regulation literature to describe all types of uncertain, potentially detrimental societal outcomes. 3

4 mation since choices are based on the worst probability scenario, not the worst possible outcome. 4 We model learning under ambiguity by relying on the framework of Epstein and Schneider (2007). A key innovation, and a contribution to the decision-theoretic literature on the value of information under ambiguity (Al-Najjar and Weinstein 2009; Siniscalchi 2009; Snow 2010; Hoy et al. 2014), is to give the meu decision-maker control over the precision of a noisy signal. Jointly, these steps demonstrate that intuition leads in many cases to a mistaken prediction about the relative research efforts expended by a regulator operating under a conventional CBA mandate and one operating under a PP mandate. In many settings conventional CBA, not the PP, leads to a greater effort to understand the true state of the world. The paper proceeds in three steps. By introducing two specific stylized examples of regulatory decision-making situations, we first illustrate numerically that in one of them the standard intuition holds, while in the other one it fails. This discrepancy of outcomes, in which the PP sometimes leads to more research, sometimes to less, justifies the development of a simple conceptual model that explains the nature of these effects. We develop such a model and demonstrate that there are two effects at work, a Precautionary Learning Effect that makes a PP regulator value risk assessment precision more highly than a CBA regulator, and a Research Pessimism Effect that has the opposite effect. Which effect dominates depends on the specific features of the decision-making situation. This means that no mandate will ensure that the regulatory decision is always better informed, irrespective of the circumstances. The insight that the choice of the mandate does not have a uniform impact on the regulator s level of information is not only important in its own right. The identification of the two countervailing effects also has immediate implications for the design of regulatory institutions. We will show that writing separate mandates for the two risk regulatory tasks can reconcile the PP with its notion of better informed decision-making. We proceed as follows. Section 2 numerically works out two stylized examples, the STEC example from above and the approval decision for a new pesticide by the Environmental Protection Agency. Despite being structurally very similar, the examples exhibit sharply different ramifications of the PP on the research effort. Section 3 develops the fundamental decision-theoretic model that embraces both examples and leads to a general analysis of risk management decisions and the choice of risk assessment precision in section 4 and section 5, respectively. The reader more interested in the formal analysis may thus skip section 2 and go straight to section 3. Section 6 demonstrates the existence of two countervailing effects of the PP on information acquisition and, by comparing their relative dependency on the payoff-structure, provides a compelling understanding of the contrarian findings in section 2. Section 7 concludes. 4 The set of probability scenarios combines the decision-maker s knowledge and preferences (Gilboa and Marinacci 2016) and is hence flexible enough to capture very extreme forms of the PP (when the set of considered probability scenarios includes the one which puts full weight on the worst outcome) as well as the CBA (when the set of scenarios contains only one medium element) 4

5 2 Two leading examples This section presents a motivating juxtaposition of two stylized numerical examples. The first example is a version of the STEC outbreak introduced earlier. The second example describes the approval decision by the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) for a novel pesticide. The examples are very similar in structure. Yet, basing risk regulation on the PP has sharply divergent implications for the regulator s risk assessment choices. These differences both motivate and anticipate the formal analysis in later sections. 2.1 Example 1: STEC outbreak and Food Safety The risk regulatory challenge at the heart of the STEC incident was uncertainty as to the origin of the epidemic outbreak. Several vegetables were considered, among them cucumbers and sprouts. As a simple caricature, suppose that the set of potential origins of STEC outbreak has been narrowed down to these two vegetables. The risk management decision is then which vegetable to remove from the market. 5 Table 1 gives a stylized specification of societal outcomes that arise under the two possible states of the world (origin of the outbreak) and the two different risk management decisions by the European authorities. The numerical values are illustrative but in the order of magnitude of the actual decision problem back in Table 1: Societal outcomes in millions EUR of the STEC risk management decision. Sprouts contaminated Cucumbers contaminated Ban sprouts Ban cucumbers Table 1 captures the fact that a product ban that removes a vegetable from the market results in losses to the agricultural sector that can be approximated by the market value of the product. Assume these losses are 500 million EUR for either one of the vegetables. Health damages caused by a STEC incident are assumed to amount to 1000 million EUR. The baseline for calculating the payoffs in table 1 is the STEC incident without any intervention. Against this baseline, a ban of either cucumber or sprouts delivers a positive payoff of = +500 million EUR if the banned vegetable is the source of STEC contamination. If the banned vegetable is not the contaminated one, then the ban only generates market value losses of 500 million EUR. 6 Which of the 5 The simultaneous occurrence of the dangerous strain in cucumbers and sprouts is extremely unlikely due to separate production lines and can thus be ignored. 6 There are de facto more risk management options, namely a ban of both products or of none. Both actions would result in payoffs of 0 EUR relative to the baseline, irrespective of the true state of the world. Once however the regulator has observed evidence that, say, sprouts are more likely to be the cause of the outbreak, banning sprouts strictly dominates banning both as well as banning none product. Vice versa for cucumbers. The actions ban both and ban none can hence be ignored right from the 5

6 two risk management options will be chosen depends on the regulator s attitude towards uncertainty and her state of knowledge regarding the source of the outbreak. Improving this state of knowledge is crucial for making a better decision. In the jargon of risk regulation this is called risk assessment and, in the present case, means devoting resources to sampling cucumbers and sprouts from different regions and testing them for the specific E.coli strain. Here we emphasize two aspects of such risk assessment. One is that information acquired over the course of testing is not just costly, it is also necessarily imprecise: The misleading detection of E.coli on Spanish cucumbers and the resulting misguided ban on cucumber sales are a case in point. The second aspect is that the degree of precision is a choice variable of risk assessment. The risk regulator, rather than being a passive recipient of research results, can decide how many resources to allocate to risk assessment research such as sampling and testing. This decision on risk assessment precision itself requires the regulator to weigh the costs and benefits of improved knowledge. With the payoff table and the choice of precision in mind, we now provide a comparison of the research decision of a risk regulator that follows a standard Cost Benefit Analysis (CBA) based on subjective expected utility (seu) and that of a risk regulator that employs an operational version of the Precautionary Principle (PP). The decisions share common assumptions about reasonable functional specifications on the likelihood of research outcomes and costs of different research precision levels (see appendix A). We start with the CBA risk regulator, who uses seu with a uniform initial prior over the two possible sources of the outbreak. The (noisy) information gained in the risk assessment transforms this initial prior on the source of the outbreak to a posterior view, thus informing the risk management decision. Given the payoffs and the functional specifications, the regulator can determine, through backward induction, the expected benefits and costs of research precision. 7 The results of this exercise are displayed in Table 2. Table 2: Risk assessment precision choice in the STEC example with a CBA mandate. Numbers are in millions of Euros. Precision level Expected benefits Costs Net benefits Low Medium High There are many familiar elements to Table 2: Marginal expected (gross) benefits are decreasing in research precision; marginal costs are non-decreasing. The expected gross benefits of choosing a high precision level approach 500 million EUR. This is intuitive: Perfect information, if attainable, would enable the correct risk management decision to be made without error. Weighing the expected gross benefits and costs in Table start. 7 The formal framework for calculating these numbers is developed in section 3. 6

7 2, the risk regulator equipped with the CBA decision rule chooses a medium precision level. Choosing a higher level would increase gross benefits, but not enough to justify the additional costs. Treating uncertainty in risk regulation on the basis of CBA has given rise to criticism. The argument is that risk regulatory challenges like the STEC outbreak typically go beyond the specific probabilistic requirements needed for a CBA based on seu. Proponents of the Precautionary Principle (PP) argue for acknowledging such deeper form of uncertainty and using robust decision rules ensuring a margin of safety (Sunstein 2005c; Zander 2010; Randall 2011; Wiener et al. 2013). A prominent example for such precautionary decision making is to describe the initial knowledge by a set of probability distributions and to base decision making on the worst probability scenario among them (maxmin expected utility, meu). 8 How does the STEC risk regulation change under this form of the PP? A set of initial priors implies that the ex-post knowledge after observing research results also forms a set of probability distributions (the Bayesian updates of all single priors). 9 The risk management decision, i.e. the decision which vegetable to take off the market, will be based on the worst of these ex-post beliefs. To determine the expected benefits and costs of research precision, the PP risk regulator determines the optimal risk assessment precision also through backward induction, i.e. by combining the value of the anticipated risk management decision with the expected research outcomes (evaluated under meu as well). Table 3: Risk assessment precision choice in the STEC example with a PP mandate. Numbers are in millions of Euros. Expected benefits are calculated based on the worst probability scenario. Precision level Expected benefits Costs Net benefits Low Medium High Table 3, the counterpart of table 2, presents the outcome of balancing research costs and benefits of research under the PP. First note that costs are the same, irrespective of the regulatory mandate. This is intuitive given that the cost side involves no uncertainty. The second commonality is that marginal expected gross benefits are decreasing in the level of precision. Third, expected benefits under the PP also approach the value of perfect information. The difference is in levels: Being calculated based on the worst probability scenario, expected benefits are systematically lower than their CBA counterparts. 8 Thus meu is typically less extreme than focusing on worst possible outcomes. For more discussion about the decision rule see section 3.3 and the concluding discussion in section 7. 9 For this example we consider the symmetric set of prior scenarios M 0 = [0.35, 0.65] around the uniform prior ρ 0 = 1/2. 7

8 As a result of the difference between the expected gross benefits, optimal precision levels under CBA and PP differ in a consequential way: Under PP, the risk regulator pursues a high level of precision in risk assessment; the CBA risk regulator pursues only a medium level of precision. The PP leads to more science and better informed decisions. Relative to the CBA mandate, higher information costs are tolerated in order to decrease the chance of further STEC infections and hence to improve the risk management decision. 2.2 Example 2: The EPA decides on a novel pesticide Like risk regulators elsewhere, the US Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) is charged with deciding on the approval of novel pesticides. In our example, the novel pesticide relies on an entirely new mechanism whose superior efficacy against a variety of pests has already been demonstrated. What has not been researched, however, is whether the new pesticide poses any threat to human health. Whether this is the case or not is critical for the EPA s approval decision, and the risk management task is substantially complicated by the lack of experience with this specific substance. The similarities to the first example are striking. While the authorities in example 1 were facing uncertainty as to whether sprouts or cucumbers were responsible for a serious STEC outbreak, the EPA is uncertain whether a novel pesticide has severe side-effects to human health or not. Intimately linked are two possible regulatory actions: To try and stop the STEC outbreak, the sale of either sprouts or cucumbers can be banned; likewise, the EPA can either approve or not approve the pesticide to prevent harm. Table 4 gives a stylized specification of the societal outcomes that arise under the two possible states of the world (harmfulness) and the two risk management decisions available to the EPA. We assume (uncertain) negative health impacts from a harmful pesticide to be 2000 million USD and (certain) agricultural benefits to be 1000 million USD. Relative to the baseline of non-approval, approving the pesticide gives rise to societal gains of million USD for a harmless and losses of = 1000 million USD for a harmful substance. Table 4: Societal outcomes in millions USD of EPA s risk management decision. Pesticide harmless Pesticide harmful Approval Non-approval 0 0 As in the STEC example, the EPA has an active role in determining the precision of risk assessment. Pesticides are routinely tested in animal organisms such as mice, rabbits or apes to assess their health impacts on humans. These tests involve a tradeoff: The reliability of toxicological tests increases the more similar the model organism 8

9 is to humans. At the same time, greater similarity to humans involves higher costs. This trade-off illustrates one of the ways in which research precision is a choice variable to the EPA. To compare CBA and PP, we again start with the precision choice under a CBA mandate and assume the same informational structure (both in terms of the likelihoods of erroneous research results as well as precision costs) as in the STEC example in 2.1. Expected benefits and costs are displayed in Table 5. A quick comparison with the STEC example (cf. table 2) shows that the numbers in both tables perfectly match. The reason is that on average, due to CBA s uniform prior over both states of the world, the prospect of gaining 500 in either state is equivalent with gaining 1000 in the good and 0 in the bad state of the world. In particular, trading off benefits and costs of research under the CBA mandate leads again to a medium level of risk assessment precision. Table 5: Risk assessment precision choice in the pesticide example with a CBA mandate. Numbers are millions of USD. Precision level Expected benefits Costs Net benefits Low Medium High We now compare this choice with risk regulation under a PP mandate. As in the STEC case, proponents of such a mandate could argue against CBA-based regulation on the grounds that the societal stakes implicit in the pesticide approval decision are high, and that the uncertainty in face of a novel substance is inevitably deep. We analyse the margin of safety regulation based on meu (with the same set of priors as in the STEC example to make results comparable). Adopting the PP in this form alters the risk management decision insofar as a positive approval decision now requires stronger evidence that the pesticide is harmless. It also changes the way the regulator assesses the value of different risk assessment precision levels. Table 6 presents the relevant information trade-off under the PP. As before, expected (gross) benefits are increasing in the level of precision with decreasing marginal benefits. It is also intuitive that the meu s worst probability focus gives rise to consistently lower expected benefits (table 5). Table 6: Risk assessment precision choice in the pesticide example with a PP mandate. Numbers are millions of USD. Expected benefits are calculated based on the worst probability scenario. Precision level Expected benefits Costs Net benefits Low Medium High The surprising observation is the final precision choice under the PP mandate. In 9

10 the STEC example, the consequences of adopting the PP followed the precautionary learning logic: The level of risk assessment precision increased relative to the CBAbased assessment. Here, the PP induces the EPA to reduce her expenditures for risk assessment relative to a CBA mandate. In other words, the EPA accepts a rise in wrong pesticide approval decisions in order to save lab testing costs. This choice under the PP clearly conflicts with the notion of the PP as leading to more science and better informed decisions. The divergent effects we have identified are puzzling given how similar the two examples are. Why would the PP lead to such disparate outcomes in terms of risk assessment precision? The following section develops a simple decision-theoretic framework that embraces both examples and thus opens them to a joint analysis. With this framework at hand it will be possible to verify the findings of the two examples in a general algebraic way and to identify two countervailing forces that together determine the value of information under meu. These forces relative strength under different payoff structures will facilitate a thorough understanding why the PP can give rise to such different and counterintuitive choices of risk assessment precision. 3 The general framework In order to shed light on the interplay of regulatory mandates and information acquisition, this section develops a parsimonious framework combining two building blocks. The first building block is a two states-two actions model with a noisy signal structure whose precision is a choice variable to the decision-maker. It is similar to Moscarini and Smith (2001), but instead of an optimal stopping problem in continuous time we focus on a one-shot signal structure. Around this active learning model, we build maxmin expected utility preferences as the second building block. From a decision-theoretic viewpoint our framework thus analyses active learning under ambiguity aversion and is, to our knowledge, the first model to do so. 10 The framework analyses the interplay of what the economic theory of uncertainty and information distinguishes as informational and terminal actions (Hirshleifer and Riley 1992). While this interplay is of general theoretical interest, we study it in the societal relevant domain of risk regulation where the interplay and appropriate design of risk assessment and risk management is a central matter of discussion (Sunstein 2002; Haimes 2015). 3.1 Timeline Figure 1 presents the time structure of the model. First, nature chooses a payoff relevant parameter θ from two possible values, θ and θ +. parameter is the true θ. The regulator is uncertain which In the STEC example in section 2.1, the risk regulator is 10 Related papers dealing with the value of information udner ambiguity aversion, but without the precision as a choice variable, are Snow (2010) and Hoy et al. (2014). 10

11 uncertain whether sprouts (θ = θ + ) or cucumbers (θ = θ ) is the origin of the STEC outbreak; in the second example in section 2.2, the EPA is uncertain whether a new pesticide is harmless and beneficial (θ = θ + ) or has severe side-effects to human health and the environment (θ = θ ). In the second stage, the regulator decides on the precision of risk assessment. The risk assessment outcome, modelled as a one-shot noisy signal, becomes available in stage three. These research results can be either inconclusive or they might provide evidence for one of the two parameter values being the true θ. As usual, however, there is some likelihood that even conclusive research results are wrong. The more resources the regulator invests into research precision (stage 2), the less likely get those erroneous findings. This option to influence the precision of the risk assessment process corresponds with the decision-theoretic concept of active learning, also known as active information acquisition. After research results from stage 3 have been observed and processed to a better, yet incomplete understanding of the decision problem, the regulator has to make the final risk management decision a (stage 4). The regulator chooses among (randomizations over) two actions, a and a +, where the first is optimal if θ = θ and the second if θ = θ +. In the examples, the actions available to the risk regulator are the ban of sprouts (a = a + ) or the ban of cucumbers (a = a ); the EPA can either approve the new pesticide (a = a + ) or not approve it (a = a ). In both examples, no action dominates the other: The optimal decision depends on the true state of the world θ. 1. Nature 2. RA precision 3. RA results 4. RM decision Figure 1: Time structure of the model. The regulator chooses how much to invest into the precision of risk assessment (stage 2) and makes the final risk management decision (stage 4). Both decisions have to be taken under incomplete (and typically ambiguous) knowledge because the regulator is uncertain which payoff relevant parameter θ was chosen by nature in stage 1. Risk assessment results in stage 3 however provide noisy information about θ. The precision of this information depends on the regulator s investment decision in stage 2. In the following subsections we will explain the missing components of the framework, 11

12 namely the payoff structure (3.2), the decision rules and updating procedures (3.3) and a specific signal structure that will later allow us to get sharp analytical results (3.4). 3.2 Payoff structure A risk regulatory setting is characterised by the societal outcomes under different combinations of state of the world θ and regulatory action a. Let π + denote the payoff if the true state is θ and the regulator chooses action a + ; all other notations accordingly. The assumptions π > π+ and π+ + > π + then reflect that there is no dominant action. We also assume that the difference in payoffs under correct and incorrect decision be independent of the states, π + + π + = π π+ =: a, and call a the error cost. It measures how large the cost of erroneous decision-making by the regulator is. The second parameter we define is the payoff asymmetry parameter π = π + + π = π + π+. This parameter captures, orthogonal to the interpretation of a, how asymmetric the regulatory setting is in terms of the unknown parameter θ. Parameter π is non-negative if we assume, without loss of generality, that π + + π. As a further simplification, we normalise payoffs such that π + π + = π+ + + π+ = 0. We will see in section 4 that this is equivalent with normalising the CBA regulator s value of the final risk management decision in the absence of information to 0. The initially four dimensional payoff space is now fully described by the error cost a and the payoff asymmetry π. Figure 2 gives a graphical illustration. Figure 2: The parameter a and π fully describe the payoff structure. The error cost a captures how wide the span between correct and wrong decision is. The payoff asymmetry π measures the extent to which payoffs differ across the two realizations of the unknown parameter θ. Table 7 summarizes how the two examples fit into the general framework. payoff asymmetry parameter π is zero in the STEC example as the final payoffs are symmetric over both parameter values θ and θ + ; the payoff only depends on whether the risk regulator is able to identify the contaminated vegetable. In contrast to that, π is positive in the pesticide example because the payoffs associated with a harmless pesticide, θ = θ +, are consistently higher than those associated with a harmful pesticide, The 12

13 θ = θ. We will see in section 6 that π is a central driver of the value of risk assessment precision under the PP. Table 7: The two examples from section 2 in the language of the general framework. Interpretation and Numbers Parameter STEC example (Sec. 2.1) Pesticide example (Sec. 2.2) θ + Sprouts contaminated Pesticide harmless θ Cucumbers contaminated Pesticide harmful a + Ban sprouts Approve pesticide a Ban cucumbers Deny pesticide approval π π π π a π Prior knowledge, Information, and Decision Rules This section describes how a regulator s prior knowledge is transformed to posterior knowledge upon observing the noisy, yet informative test results ( signal ) gained in the risk assessment. Any signal structure is characterised by a signal space S of possible test results and a likelihood function l : Θ (S) that describes how likely different test results s S are if θ is the true state of the world. For better readability we write l + (s) for l(θ + )(s). Because Θ has only two elements, every belief prior and posterior can be expressed as a single number in the unit interval. CBA regulation. How does the CBA regulator come to decisions on risk management and risk assessment? The basis for the standard CBA mandate is the maximisation of subjective expected utility (seu, Savage 1954). Integral part of this decision rule is the formation of a single belief ρ over Θ that best reflects the decision-maker s knowledge. Based on this belief, the optimal action in a set of alternatives A is found by maximising subjective expected utility, max E ρu(θ, a), (1) a A where u is a utility function. For simplicity we assume risk neutral preferences throughout. Depending on the context u either represents the outcomes under different risk management decisions or expected net benefits of different levels of risk assessment precision. Let the regulator initially hold ρ 0 [0, 1], her ex-ante belief that θ = θ +. If she 13

14 observes the signal s S, Bayesian updating transforms the prior to the posterior ρ 1 (s, ρ 0 ) = ρ 0 l + (s) ρ 0 l + (s) + (1 ρ 0 )l (s). (2) When the regulator initially has no information about the true θ Θ, she would usually follow the Principle of Insufficient Reason (see for instance Gilboa 2009) and hold the uniform prior ρ 0 = 1/2. With that, formula (2) simplifies further, ρ 1 (s, 1/2) = l + (s)/(l + (s) + l (s)). PP regulation. In light of the high stakes involved, the PP regulator may want to both acknowledge the poor level of knowledge typically available and make cautious decisions. Schmeidler 1989), Both aspects are captured in maxmin expected utility (meu, Gilboa and max min E µu(θ, a). (3) a A µ M The PP regulator bases her decision on a set of beliefs M and the optimal action is one that maximises utility based on the worst belief, where what is the worst belief may be action dependent. It is important to note that this decision-rule is less extreme than it may appear. The set M is not exogenously given but part of the preference structure (Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989; Etner et al. 2012). It hence combines scientific knowledge and the regulator s attitude towards uncertainty. In fact, in our stylized regulatory model neither regulator has any scientific knowledge in the first place. Recalling that we can express any belief about Θ on the unit interval, an accurate scientific description of the state of knowledge is hence the full set [0, 1]. Possible ways of dealing with this (lack of) scientific knowledge range from selecting the best single belief (the CBA approach) to an extreme form of precaution that uses (3) with the full set, i.e. preparing against the worst possible outcome. In analogy to the Principle of Insufficient Reason we assume that the initial prior set M 0 is symmetric around the uniform distribution, M 0 = [1/2 δ, 1/2 + δ] with 0 δ 1/2. We call δ the regulator s level of precaution, where the CBA regulator is the corner case δ = 0. We will see shortly that the extreme case δ = 1/2 is ruled out (see 3.4) so that we consider in this paper a moderate form of the PP. How to extend the static preferences in (3) to dynamic settings like ours? Epstein and Schneider (2007) provide an application-friendly framework of dynamic meu preferences that respects backward induction (recursive preferences) and beliefs are updated priorby-prior with the Bayesian updating formula (2), M 1 (s) = {ρ = ρ 1 (s, ρ 0 ) ρ 0 M 0 }. (4) 14

15 In other words, we assume full Bayesian updating of multiple priors. 11 This updating process has very intuitive features. For instance, a non-informative signal s with l (s) = l + (s) results in no learning, M 1 (s) = M 0. A maximal informative signal structure, on the other extreme, transforms M 1 into a singleton reflecting subjective certainty; for instance, observing a signal s that can only be observed in case of θ = θ +, l (s) = 0, gives rise to ex-post certainty that θ + must be the payoff relevant parameter, M 1 (s) = {1}. 3.4 The simple signal space with three elements In terms of the signal structure, a natural choice is to consider real-valued, normally distributed signals where l and l + have the same variance but different means. With decreasing variance (i.e. increasing precision, the reciprocal of the variance) the signal gets more informative as it becomes easier to infer whether the true parameter is θ or θ +. The main drawback of this approach, however, is its lack of analytical tractability, especially in the meu case. We thus design a discrete signal space that is rich enough to hold the non-trivial impact of meu on the value of information and at the same time allows closed form solutions. 12 The final justification for choosing this signal structure will be given in appendix B where we demonstrate numerically that the paper s main findings do not depend on the signal structure. Consider the signal space with three elements, S = {s, s?, s + }. Their interpretation is straightforward: The signals s and s + represent research results that suggest θ = θ and θ = θ + respectively, while s? models inconclusive research outcomes. A signal structure requires a specification of the likelihood of all signals under all parameters θ Θ. Assuming symmetry over θ and θ +, the signal structure is fully determined by specifying the likelihood of correct, erroneous and inconclusive research results P corr = l (s ) = l + (s + ), P mist = l (s + ) = l + (s ), P inconcl = l (s? ) = l + (s? ). (5) The likelihoods P corr, P mist and P inconcl are functions of the signal structure s precision τ R 0 and sum to one for all τ. We further assume that P corr, P mist and P inconcl are 11 For simplicity and to ensure dynamic stable preferences (Heyen 2014), we abstain from the ex-post rejection of beliefs that is allowed for in Epstein and Schneider (2007). 12 The simplest binary signal structure does not pass this test as the difference between precision choices under CBA and PP collapse. 15

16 twice continuously differentiable in τ and that for all precision level τ lim P corr(τ) = 1, P τ corr(τ) > 0 lim P mist(τ) = 0, P τ mist(τ) < 0 lim P inconcl(τ) = 0, P τ inconcl (τ) < 0 Assumptions (6a) to (6c) are straightforward: (6a) (6b) (6c) (1 2δ)P corr (τ) > (1 + 2δ)P mist (τ) (6d) (P corr P mist ) (τ) < 0. (6e) The noisiness of the signal structure decreases in the precision of the signal structure and vanishes in the limit of perfect information. Equivalent with (6c) is P corr + P mist > 0. Assumption (6d) is equivalent with ρ 1 (s + ) > 1/2 and ρ 1 (s ) < 1/2 and thus ensures that PP is moderate in the sense that conclusive research results result in clear beliefs and hence clear actions; otherwise information trivially has no value. In particular, assumption (6d) precludes the extreme regulator preferences δ = 1/2 right from the start. Assumption (6d) rules out, for given 0 δ < 1/2, small precision levels. A restriction on small precision levels also comes from the technical assumption (6e) which unambiguously holds in the limit because P corr P mist is non-negative and P corr P mist 0 for τ. Thus, assumptions (6d) and (6e) basically translate into the existence of a smallest feasible precision level. For the discrete signal structure just defined we can give simple expressions for the updating formula (2). Let ρ 0 be an initial prior. Then ρ 1 (s, ρ 0 ) = ρ 0 P mist ρ 0 P mist + (1 ρ 0 )P corr, ρ 1 (s?, ρ 0 ) = ρ 0, ρ 1 (s +, ρ 0 ) = ρ 0 P corr ρ 0 P corr + (1 ρ 0 )P mist. (7) From the inconclusive research result s? no information can be gained. Observation of s transforms the initial prior towards ρ 1 = 0, and this movement is stronger the higher the research precision τ. Observing s + induces a similar push to the right towards ρ 1 = 1. The formulas in (7) are of use both in the CBA and the PP analysis. For CBA, ρ 0 = 1/2. For the PP, every ρ 0 M 0 is updated in that way, together forming the set of posteriors M 1. This completes the exposition of the framework components. We move on to solving the model. In line with backward induction we begin with the risk management decision in section 4 and then analyse the risk assessment precision choice in Section 5. 16

17 4 Risk management decision The terminal risk management decision depends on the payoff structure, the confidence gained in the risk assessment process, and the regulatory mandate. This section will explain which risk management decisions are made under different mandates and, crucial for the subsequent analysis, how the value of these optimal decision depends on the risk regulator s ex-post confidence, where the level of ex-post confidence is directly linked to the precision of the just obtained risk assessment outcome. We begin with the general case of arbitrary signal and payoff structures (section 4.1) and then specialize to the two examples (section 4.2). 4.1 Risk management: The general case We analyse the risk management decision as a function of the risk regulator s then up-todate state of knowledge, i.e. the posterior ρ 1 (CBA regulator) and the set of posteriors M 1 (PP regulator). In focusing on the ex-post knowledge we do not have to make any assumptions on the signal structure that gave rise to this posterior knowledge. CBA regulation. The optimal risk management decision maximises expected terminal payoffs (cf. section 3.3), max a [0,1] ρ 1 ( aπ (1 a)π +) + (1 ρ1 ) ( aπ + + (1 a)π ). (8) Here, a is a randomization over the two actions a and a +, with a = 1 (a = 0) corresponding to the pure action a + (a ). Because the error cost a = π + + π + = π π+ does not depend on θ (cf. section 3.2), it is easy to show that the regulator strictly prefers the pure action a + (a ) if and only if ρ 1 > 1/2 (ρ 1 < 1/2); under inconclusive knowledge ρ 1 = 1/2 the regulator regards all randomizations a [0, 1] as equally reasonable. In line with the standard backward approach for recursively defined preferences we introduce the value of the risk management decision as a function of the posterior knowledge, ρ 1 V (ρ 1 ). 13 We express all payoffs in terms of error cost a and payoff asymmetry π and get for the CBA value of the risk management decision V (ρ 1 ) = ( 1 2 ρ 1)(a π ) ρ 1 < 1/2 0 ρ 1 = 1/2 (ρ )(a + π ) ρ 1 > 1/2. As a result of the normalisation π + π + = π+ + + π+ = 0 (see section 3.2) the value of inconclusive knowledge V (1/2) is zero. When the regulator s posterior knowledge 13 This has been used for the analysis of information acquisition problems before, see for instance Mirman et al. (1993); Grossman et al. (1977). (9) 17

18 ρ 1 approaches subjective certainty, ρ 1 = 0 and ρ 1 = 1, the value V (ρ 1 ) converges to π = (a π )/2 and π + + = (a + π )/2, respectively. 14 PP regulation. The test results have transformed the PP regulator s set of prior beliefs M 0 = [1/2 δ, 1/2 + δ] to the set of posteriors M 1 = [ρ 1, ρ 1 ]. The optimal risk management decison is (see 3.3) max a [0,1] ( min ρ 1 aπ (1 a)π ) + + (1 ρ1 ) ( aπ + + (1 ) ρ 1 M a)π. (10) 1 The optimal action a (M 1 ), again a randomization over actions a and a +, depends on the set of posteriors M 1. PP regulator chooses the pure action a + (a ). Only if all posteriors are higher (lower) than 1/2, the If however 1/2 M 1, the regulator randomizes over actions in a non-trivial way that depends on the payoff structure (see appendix C): The probability of choosing a + is 1/2 for symmetric settings π = 0 and decreases linearly as π increases; it is zero for π a. In particular, regulatory settings of high payoff asymmetry π a are characterised by the PP risk manager choosing a as long as the posterior knowledge remains ambiguous, 1/2 M 1. This is a direct consequence of the maxmin rule and an expression of precautionary decisionmaking. We will come back to this in the pesticide example below. What is the value of the risk management decision under the PP regulation? Based on the profile of optimal decisions we get a π ( 1 2 ρ 1)(a π ) ρ 1 < 1/2 V (M 1 ) = 0 1/2 M 1 (ρ )(a + π ) ρ 1 > 1/2. (11a) a < π ( 1 2 ρ 1 )(a π ) ρ 1 < 1/2 V (M 1 ) = ( 1 2 ρ 1 )(a π ) 1/2 M 1 (ρ )(a + π ) ρ 1 > 1/2. (11b) A first observation is that, due to the maxmin rule, the value of the risk management under PP (11) is never larger than the CBA counterpart (9). One difference to (9) is that the PP value depends on the shape of the payoff structure. While the value of ambiguous knowledge, 1/2 M 1, is zero (as in the CBA case) for modest payoff asymmetry, π a, it is a function of the lowest posterior ρ 1 and turns negative for high payoff asymmetry π > a (The pesticide example is the corner case π = a ). Also, what the worst posterior is, ρ 1 or ρ 1, depends on the context. It is noteworthy that the value in the high payoff asymmetry case is characterised by the single posterior ρ 1, while the value of the risk management decision in the low payoff asymmetry case cannot be expressed with a single posterior. 14 For π > a we have V (0) < V (1/2) so that the movement towards subjective certainty ρ 1 = 0 decreases value; this reduction however is over-compensated by the simultaneous value increase of those signal realizations that suggest θ +. 18

19 4.2 Risk management in the STEC and pesticide example We now apply the general results to the two examples and the simple signal structure with three possible test results. We begin with the optimal risk management decision and then discuss the associated value. Thanks to assumption (6d), conclusive risk assessment outcomes s + (s ) result in (non-randomized) risk management decision a + (a ), irrespective of the setting and mandate. This is different for inconclusive test results s?. Recall that, after obtaining s?, the CBA regulator is indifferent between all randomizations irrespective of the regulatory setting. The PP regulator, in contrast, finds a specific randomization optimal and this optimal decision depends on the setting. In the symmetric STEC example the PP regulator randomizes over banning cucumbers and sprouts with equal probabilities. For the asymmetric pesticide example, however, the PP regulator takes inconclusive test results s? as the sufficient reason for non-approval of the pesticide. This is expression of the PP s margin of safety notion. (a) STEC example (b) Pesticide example Figure 3: The value of the risk management decision of the two examples as a function of the posterior knowledge ρ 1 and evaluated for the three risk assessment outcomes s, s? and s +. The dark and light dots represent the CBA regulator (δ = 0) and PP regulator (δ > 0), respectively. The value of the risk management decision is depicted in Figure 3. The solid red lines show the value of the risk management decision as a function of the ex-post knowledge ρ 1 and is hence a graphical representation of (9). The dark dots accordingly represent the CBA regulator s value under the test results s, s? and s + that transform the initial knowledge ρ 0 = 1/2 to test result specific posteriors ρ 1 (s). Similarly, the light points represent, based on (11), the PP regulator s value. The set of priors M 0 = [1/2 δ, 1/2 + δ] is updated to test specific sets of posteriors M 1 (s, δ) and the worst of these posteriors determines the value V (s, δ). Due to the maxmin rule the PP value never exceeds the CBA value. The figure is drawn for a certain level of precision τ. Higher levels of precision would push the posteriors under s to the left and those under s + to the right, overall increasing the value associated with the risk management decision. 19

U n iversity o f H ei delberg. Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition

U n iversity o f H ei delberg. Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition U n iversity o f H ei delberg Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series No. 572 482482 Informativeness of Experiments for MEU A Recursive Definition Daniel Heyen and Boris R. Wiesenfarth October

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal May 0, 0 Abstract Machina (009, 0) lists a number of situations where standard models of ambiguity aversion are unable to capture

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples

Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples Recursive Ambiguity and Machina s Examples David Dillenberger Uzi Segal January 9, 204 Abstract Machina (2009, 202) lists a number of situations where Choquet expected utility, as well as other known models

More information

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from

Lecture Notes 1: Decisions and Data. In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from Topics in Data Analysis Steven N. Durlauf University of Wisconsin Lecture Notes : Decisions and Data In these notes, I describe some basic ideas in decision theory. theory is constructed from The Data:

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Ambiguity and the Centipede Game

Ambiguity and the Centipede Game Ambiguity and the Centipede Game Jürgen Eichberger, Simon Grant and David Kelsey Heidelberg University, Australian National University, University of Exeter. University of Exeter. June 2018 David Kelsey

More information

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION

RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES 1. INTRODUCTION INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 56, No., February 05 RECURSIVE AMBIGUITY AND MACHINA S EXAMPLES BY DAVID DILLENBERGER AND UZI SEGAL University of Pennsylvania, U.S.A.; Boston College, U.S.A., and Warwick

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

Robust Partially Observable Markov Decision Processes

Robust Partially Observable Markov Decision Processes Submitted to manuscript Robust Partially Observable Markov Decision Processes Mohammad Rasouli 1, Soroush Saghafian 2 1 Management Science and Engineering, Stanford University, Palo Alto, CA 2 Harvard

More information

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Ilan Lobel, Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh and Asuman Ozdaglar ABSTRACT We study a model of social learning with partial observations from

More information

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness

Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Ambiguity under Growing Awareness Adam Dominiak 1 and Gerelt Tserenjigmid 2 1,2 Department of Economics, Virginia Tech September 10, 2018 Abstract In this paper, we study choice under growing awareness

More information

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness On-Line Appendix Jérôme Dugast Thierry Foucault August 30, 07 This note is the on-line appendix for Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. It contains

More information

Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs

Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs 26 February 2009 Comparing Three Ways to Update Choquet Beliefs Abstract We analyze three rules that have been proposed for updating capacities. First we consider their implications for updating the Choquet

More information

Learning and Valuation with Costly Attention

Learning and Valuation with Costly Attention Learning and Valuation with Costly Attention Jacob LaRiviere a and William Neilson b June 2015 Abstract This paper develops a theoretical framework of consumer learning and product valuation when attending

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Imprecise Probability

Imprecise Probability Imprecise Probability Alexander Karlsson University of Skövde School of Humanities and Informatics alexander.karlsson@his.se 6th October 2006 0 D W 0 L 0 Introduction The term imprecise probability refers

More information

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate

An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty. Yosuke Hashidate An Axiomatic Model of Reference Dependence under Uncertainty Yosuke Hashidate Abstract This paper presents a behavioral characteization of a reference-dependent choice under uncertainty in the Anscombe-Aumann

More information

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty 1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty Sofarwehaveassumedawayaggregatefluctuations (i.e., business cycles) in our description of the incomplete-markets economies with uninsurable idiosyncratic risk

More information

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions 15-312: Foundations of Programming Languages Frank Pfenning Lecture 2 September 2, 2004 These supplementary notes review the notion of an inductive definition and

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention

Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention Srijita Ghosh Dept. of Economics, NYU September 19, 2016 Abstract We consider a rationally inattentive agent with Shannon s relative entropy cost function.

More information

The Role of Pre-trial Settlement in International Trade Disputes (1)

The Role of Pre-trial Settlement in International Trade Disputes (1) 183 The Role of Pre-trial Settlement in International Trade Disputes (1) Jee-Hyeong Park To analyze the role of pre-trial settlement in international trade dispute resolutions, this paper develops a simple

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Econometric Society Summer Meeting June 2012 Robust Predictions Agenda game theoretic predictions are very

More information

Persuading a Pessimist

Persuading a Pessimist Persuading a Pessimist Afshin Nikzad PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract While in practice most persuasion mechanisms have a simple structure, optimal signals in the Bayesian persuasion framework may not be so.

More information

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Roland Bénabou Jean Tirole. Review of Economic Studies 2003 Bénabou and Tirole Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation 1 / 30 Motivation Should a child be rewarded for passing

More information

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY

DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY August 18, 2003 Aanund Hylland: # DECISIONS UNDER UNCERTAINTY Standard theory and alternatives 1. Introduction Individual decision making under uncertainty can be characterized as follows: The decision

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach)

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2015 Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) Block 4 Jul 31 and Aug 1, 2015 Auction results Herd behavior and

More information

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 Economics Letters, 159: 221 223, 2017 DOI 10.1016/j.econlet.2017.07.027 THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 YANG LIU Abstract. This paper offers a fine analysis of different versions of the well known sure-thing

More information

Joint Estimation of Risk Preferences and Technology: Further Discussion

Joint Estimation of Risk Preferences and Technology: Further Discussion Joint Estimation of Risk Preferences and Technology: Further Discussion Feng Wu Research Associate Gulf Coast Research and Education Center University of Florida Zhengfei Guan Assistant Professor Gulf

More information

Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy: Basic features

Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy: Basic features Lecture 2 The Centralized Economy: Basic features Leopold von Thadden University of Mainz and ECB (on leave) Advanced Macroeconomics, Winter Term 2013 1 / 41 I Motivation This Lecture introduces the basic

More information

Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance.

Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance. Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance. Laura Veldkamp New York University, Stern School of Business, CEPR and NBER Spring 2009 1 Veldkamp What information consumes is rather obvious: It consumes

More information

On the errors introduced by the naive Bayes independence assumption

On the errors introduced by the naive Bayes independence assumption On the errors introduced by the naive Bayes independence assumption Author Matthijs de Wachter 3671100 Utrecht University Master Thesis Artificial Intelligence Supervisor Dr. Silja Renooij Department of

More information

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 Economics Letters, 159: 221 223, 2017. Doi: 10.1016/j.econlet.2017.07.027 THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 YANG LIU Abstract. This paper offers a fine analysis of different versions of the well known sure-thing

More information

Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers

Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers May, 31 st, 2014 Becker-Friedman Institute Ricardo Alonso and Odilon Camara Marshall School of Business - USC Introduction Sender wants to influence decisions

More information

Martin Gregor IES, Charles University. Abstract

Martin Gregor IES, Charles University. Abstract On the strategic non-complementarity of complements Martin Gregor IES, Charles University Abstract This paper examines the equilibrium provision of a public good if the private monetary contributions of

More information

A Comparative Study of Different Order Relations of Intervals

A Comparative Study of Different Order Relations of Intervals A Comparative Study of Different Order Relations of Intervals Samiran Karmakar Department of Business Mathematics and Statistics, St. Xavier s College, Kolkata, India skmath.rnc@gmail.com A. K. Bhunia

More information

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001)

Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001) Is it Possible to Define Subjective Probabilities in Purely Behavioral Terms? A Comment on Epstein-Zhang (2001) Klaus Nehring University of California, Davis April 2006 Abstract It is shown that well-behaved

More information

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B Lecture 2 Giulio Fella c Giulio Fella, 2014 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B - Lecture 2 40/197 Aim of consumption theory Consumption theory aims at explaining consumption/saving decisions

More information

Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models

Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models Structural Uncertainty in Health Economic Decision Models Mark Strong 1, Hazel Pilgrim 1, Jeremy Oakley 2, Jim Chilcott 1 December 2009 1. School of Health and Related Research, University of Sheffield,

More information

Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty

Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Discussion Paper No. 18-055 Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Helene Mass Discussion Paper No. 18-055 Strategies under Strategic Uncertainty Helene Mass Download this ZEW Discussion Paper from our

More information

Rationality and Uncertainty

Rationality and Uncertainty Rationality and Uncertainty Based on papers by Itzhak Gilboa, Massimo Marinacci, Andy Postlewaite, and David Schmeidler Warwick Aug 23, 2013 Risk and Uncertainty Dual use of probability: empirical frequencies

More information

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Maximilian Kasy Department of Economics, Harvard University 1 / 53 Takeaways for this part of class 1. A general framework to think about what makes a

More information

Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality

Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality Information, Utility & Bounded Rationality Pedro A. Ortega and Daniel A. Braun Department of Engineering, University of Cambridge Trumpington Street, Cambridge, CB2 PZ, UK {dab54,pao32}@cam.ac.uk Abstract.

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

IDENTIFICATION OF TREATMENT EFFECTS WITH SELECTIVE PARTICIPATION IN A RANDOMIZED TRIAL

IDENTIFICATION OF TREATMENT EFFECTS WITH SELECTIVE PARTICIPATION IN A RANDOMIZED TRIAL IDENTIFICATION OF TREATMENT EFFECTS WITH SELECTIVE PARTICIPATION IN A RANDOMIZED TRIAL BRENDAN KLINE AND ELIE TAMER Abstract. Randomized trials (RTs) are used to learn about treatment effects. This paper

More information

Managerial delegation in multimarket oligopoly

Managerial delegation in multimarket oligopoly Managerial delegation in multimarket oligopoly Arup Bose Barnali Gupta Statistics and Mathematics Unit Department of Economics Indian Statistical Institute Miami University, Ohio INDIA USA bosearu@gmail.com

More information

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions

Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions Lecture Notes on Inductive Definitions 15-312: Foundations of Programming Languages Frank Pfenning Lecture 2 August 28, 2003 These supplementary notes review the notion of an inductive definition and give

More information

Bayesian Networks 2:

Bayesian Networks 2: 1/27 PhD seminar series Probabilistics in Engineering : Bayesian networks and Bayesian hierarchical analysis in engineering Conducted by Prof. Dr. Maes, Prof. Dr. Faber and Dr. Nishijima Bayesian Networks

More information

Common Knowledge and Sequential Team Problems

Common Knowledge and Sequential Team Problems Common Knowledge and Sequential Team Problems Authors: Ashutosh Nayyar and Demosthenis Teneketzis Computer Engineering Technical Report Number CENG-2018-02 Ming Hsieh Department of Electrical Engineering

More information

Coordination and Continuous Choice

Coordination and Continuous Choice Coordination and Continuous Choice Stephen Morris and Ming Yang Princeton University and Duke University December 2016 Abstract We study a coordination game where players choose what information to acquire

More information

1 Motivation for Instrumental Variable (IV) Regression

1 Motivation for Instrumental Variable (IV) Regression ECON 370: IV & 2SLS 1 Instrumental Variables Estimation and Two Stage Least Squares Econometric Methods, ECON 370 Let s get back to the thiking in terms of cross sectional (or pooled cross sectional) data

More information

September Math Course: First Order Derivative

September Math Course: First Order Derivative September Math Course: First Order Derivative Arina Nikandrova Functions Function y = f (x), where x is either be a scalar or a vector of several variables (x,..., x n ), can be thought of as a rule which

More information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information joint with Stephen Morris (Princeton University) November 2010 Payoff Environment in games with incomplete information, the agents are uncertain

More information

Chapter Three. Hypothesis Testing

Chapter Three. Hypothesis Testing 3.1 Introduction The final phase of analyzing data is to make a decision concerning a set of choices or options. Should I invest in stocks or bonds? Should a new product be marketed? Are my products being

More information

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION

WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION Prerequisites Almost essential Welfare: Basics Welfare: Efficiency WELFARE: THE SOCIAL- WELFARE FUNCTION MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell July 2017 1 Social Welfare Function Limitations

More information

A BAYESIAN SOLUTION TO INCOMPLETENESS

A BAYESIAN SOLUTION TO INCOMPLETENESS A BAYESIAN SOLUTION TO INCOMPLETENESS IN PROBABILISTIC RISK ASSESSMENT 14th International Probabilistic Safety Assessment & Management Conference PSAM-14 September 17-21, 2018 Los Angeles, United States

More information

Technology Adoption and Adaptation to Climate Change A Case-Based Approach 1

Technology Adoption and Adaptation to Climate Change A Case-Based Approach 1 Technology Adoption and Adaptation to Climate Change A Case-Based Approach 1 Jürgen Eichberger 2 and Ani Guerdjikova 3 28 January 2011 1 Preliminary and incomplete. Please do not cite or distribute without

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Structure learning in human causal induction

Structure learning in human causal induction Structure learning in human causal induction Joshua B. Tenenbaum & Thomas L. Griffiths Department of Psychology Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305 jbt,gruffydd @psych.stanford.edu Abstract We use

More information

1 Using standard errors when comparing estimated values

1 Using standard errors when comparing estimated values MLPR Assignment Part : General comments Below are comments on some recurring issues I came across when marking the second part of the assignment, which I thought it would help to explain in more detail

More information

Indescribable Contingencies versus Unawareness and Incomplete Contracting

Indescribable Contingencies versus Unawareness and Incomplete Contracting Indescribable Contingencies versus Unawareness and Incomplete Contracting Wenjun Ma Burkhard C. Schipper Job Market Paper November 4, 204 Abstract Maskin and Tirole (999) postulated that even though agents

More information

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers joint work with Frederic Murphy Climate Policy and Long Term Decisions-Investment and R&D, Bocconi University, Milan,

More information

Decision theory. 1 We may also consider randomized decision rules, where δ maps observed data D to a probability distribution over

Decision theory. 1 We may also consider randomized decision rules, where δ maps observed data D to a probability distribution over Point estimation Suppose we are interested in the value of a parameter θ, for example the unknown bias of a coin. We have already seen how one may use the Bayesian method to reason about θ; namely, we

More information

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 1 7 Moral Hazard: Hidden Actions PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODELS The principal (or uninformed player) is the player who has

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

6 Evolution of Networks

6 Evolution of Networks last revised: March 2008 WARNING for Soc 376 students: This draft adopts the demography convention for transition matrices (i.e., transitions from column to row). 6 Evolution of Networks 6. Strategic network

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

The Island Problem Revisited

The Island Problem Revisited The Island Problem Revisited Halvor Mehlum 1 Department of Economics, University of Oslo, Norway E-mail: halvormehlum@econuiono March 10, 2009 1 While carrying out this research, the author has been associated

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Paradoxical Results in Multidimensional Item Response Theory

Paradoxical Results in Multidimensional Item Response Theory UNC, December 6, 2010 Paradoxical Results in Multidimensional Item Response Theory Giles Hooker and Matthew Finkelman UNC, December 6, 2010 1 / 49 Item Response Theory Educational Testing Traditional model

More information

Reasoning with Uncertainty

Reasoning with Uncertainty Reasoning with Uncertainty Representing Uncertainty Manfred Huber 2005 1 Reasoning with Uncertainty The goal of reasoning is usually to: Determine the state of the world Determine what actions to take

More information

RSMG Working Paper Series. TITLE: The value of information and the value of awareness. Author: John Quiggin. Working Paper: R13_2

RSMG Working Paper Series. TITLE: The value of information and the value of awareness. Author: John Quiggin. Working Paper: R13_2 2013 TITLE: The value of information and the value of awareness 2011 RSMG Working Paper Series Risk and Uncertainty Program Author: John Quiggin Working Paper: R13_2 Schools of Economics and Political

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

How Much Evidence Should One Collect?

How Much Evidence Should One Collect? How Much Evidence Should One Collect? Remco Heesen October 10, 2013 Abstract This paper focuses on the question how much evidence one should collect before deciding on the truth-value of a proposition.

More information

On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets

On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets Satoshi Fukuda September 23, 2018 Abstract This paper studies implications of the consistency conditions among prior, posteriors, and information

More information

Cournot and Bertrand Competition in a Differentiated Duopoly with Endogenous Technology Adoption *

Cournot and Bertrand Competition in a Differentiated Duopoly with Endogenous Technology Adoption * ANNALS OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE 16-1, 231 253 (2015) Cournot and Bertrand Competition in a Differentiated Duopoly with Endogenous Technology Adoption * Hongkun Ma School of Economics, Shandong University,

More information

ECE521 Lecture7. Logistic Regression

ECE521 Lecture7. Logistic Regression ECE521 Lecture7 Logistic Regression Outline Review of decision theory Logistic regression A single neuron Multi-class classification 2 Outline Decision theory is conceptually easy and computationally hard

More information

Second-Order Expected Utility

Second-Order Expected Utility Second-Order Expected Utility Simon Grant Ben Polak Tomasz Strzalecki Preliminary version: November 2009 Abstract We present two axiomatizations of the Second-Order Expected Utility model in the context

More information

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions. Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 3: Optimization - interior optima 1 Session: 11-12 Aug 2015 (Thu/Fri) 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization: introduction Decision-makers (e.g. consumers,

More information

Non-independence in Statistical Tests for Discrete Cross-species Data

Non-independence in Statistical Tests for Discrete Cross-species Data J. theor. Biol. (1997) 188, 507514 Non-independence in Statistical Tests for Discrete Cross-species Data ALAN GRAFEN* AND MARK RIDLEY * St. John s College, Oxford OX1 3JP, and the Department of Zoology,

More information

Mechanism Design with Ambiguous Transfers

Mechanism Design with Ambiguous Transfers Mechanism Design with Ambiguous Transfers Huiyi Guo Texas A&M University December 31, 2018 1 / 27 Motivation In practice, some mechanism designers introduce uncertain rules to the mechanisms, e.g., Priceline

More information

Risk Aggregation with Dependence Uncertainty

Risk Aggregation with Dependence Uncertainty Introduction Extreme Scenarios Asymptotic Behavior Challenges Risk Aggregation with Dependence Uncertainty Department of Statistics and Actuarial Science University of Waterloo, Canada Seminar at ETH Zurich

More information

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu

Recitation 7: Uncertainty. Xincheng Qiu Econ 701A Fall 2018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation 7: Uncertainty Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu 1 Expected Utility Remark 1. Primitives: in the basic consumer theory, a preference relation is

More information

Social Learning with Endogenous Network Formation

Social Learning with Endogenous Network Formation Social Learning with Endogenous Network Formation Yangbo Song November 10, 2014 Abstract I study the problem of social learning in a model where agents move sequentially. Each agent receives a private

More information

Simple Counter-terrorism Decision

Simple Counter-terrorism Decision A Comparative Analysis of PRA and Intelligent Adversary Methods for Counterterrorism Risk Management Greg Parnell US Military Academy Jason R. W. Merrick Virginia Commonwealth University Simple Counter-terrorism

More information

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World

Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States of the World heoretical Economics Letters, 013, 3, 17-1 http://dxdoiorg/10436/tel01335a004 Published Online September 013 (http://wwwscirporg/journal/tel) Action-Independent Subjective Expected Utility without States

More information

Weather Derivatives-Pricing and Design Issue in India

Weather Derivatives-Pricing and Design Issue in India Weather Derivatives-Pricing and Design Issue in India By Anshul Anand & Surendra Mahadik Introduction: In the last decades, agricultural policies of certain countries focused on adopting and strengthening

More information

Desire-as-belief revisited

Desire-as-belief revisited Desire-as-belief revisited Richard Bradley and Christian List June 30, 2008 1 Introduction On Hume s account of motivation, beliefs and desires are very di erent kinds of propositional attitudes. Beliefs

More information

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion

3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3 Intertemporal Risk Aversion 3. Axiomatic Characterization This section characterizes the invariant quantity found in proposition 2 axiomatically. The axiomatic characterization below is for a decision

More information

Value of Information Analysis with Structural Reliability Methods

Value of Information Analysis with Structural Reliability Methods Accepted for publication in Structural Safety, special issue in the honor of Prof. Wilson Tang August 2013 Value of Information Analysis with Structural Reliability Methods Daniel Straub Engineering Risk

More information

Likelihood and Fairness in Multidimensional Item Response Theory

Likelihood and Fairness in Multidimensional Item Response Theory Likelihood and Fairness in Multidimensional Item Response Theory or What I Thought About On My Holidays Giles Hooker and Matthew Finkelman Cornell University, February 27, 2008 Item Response Theory Educational

More information

A Summary of Economic Methodology

A Summary of Economic Methodology A Summary of Economic Methodology I. The Methodology of Theoretical Economics All economic analysis begins with theory, based in part on intuitive insights that naturally spring from certain stylized facts,

More information

A DECISION-RULE FOR TRANSPLANTING NON-CADAVERIC ORGANS

A DECISION-RULE FOR TRANSPLANTING NON-CADAVERIC ORGANS A ECIION-ULE FO TANPLANTING NON-CAAVEIC OGAN Amnon Levy, Economics iscipline, chool of Economics and Information ystems University of Wollongong This paper analyzes the minimum probability of success required

More information

Mathematical Statistics

Mathematical Statistics Mathematical Statistics MAS 713 Chapter 8 Previous lecture: 1 Bayesian Inference 2 Decision theory 3 Bayesian Vs. Frequentist 4 Loss functions 5 Conjugate priors Any questions? Mathematical Statistics

More information